Skip to main content
Log in

Undermining versus rebutting: options for responding to evolutionary debunking arguments

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the success of evolutionary debunking arguments hinges on what theory of epistemic justification one endorses. More specifically, I argue that what it takes to satisfactorily respond to evolutionary debunking arguments depends on what view of epistemic justification one is operating under and that a thorough analysis of any line of response to evolutionary debunking arguments must take into account whether there is a specific view of justification motivating the response or looming in the background. In particular, I argue that pace Andrew del Rio’s claim in the article “Why Undermining Evolutionary Debunkers is Not Enough,” merely undermining the empirical claim can in fact be a successful line of response to debunkers if one endorses a particular version of doxastic conservatism. I also argue that examining how satisfying a response to an evolutionary debunking argument seems to us and considering what theory of justification is looming in the background of the response can shed light on the plausibility of certain theories of epistemic justification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material

Not applicable.

Code availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For examples of prominent evolutionary debunking arguments see, e.g., Joyce (2006), Joyce (2016), Ruse (1995), and Street (2006).

  2. See, e.g., Kahane (2011), Koon (2021), Korman & Locke (2020), and Morton (2019).

  3. Kyriacou (2019) makes a similar point but focuses on metaepistemic norms and what he refers to as the “demarcation problem.”

  4. In the remainder of this paper, I will refer to epistemic conservatism as doxastic conservatism.

  5. According to del Shafer-Landau (2012), Fitzpatrick (2014, 2015), and Vavova (2014, 2015) are examples of mere underminers.

  6. Levy and Levy (2020) and Plakias (2022) seem to employ this strategy.

  7. There are also authors who target the epistemic premise rather than the empirical premise. See e.g., Brosnan (2011). However, for the purposes of this paper, I will focus on responses that target the empirical premise.

  8. Joyce refers to this view as “epistemic conservatism.”

  9. Although it is not clear that any of the mere underminers del Rio mentions explicitly endorse doxastic conservatism, Fitzpatrick (2015) seems to endorse such a view, at least implicitly, when he states that when we become aware of a debunking argument the “default justification we may have had for our moral beliefs is thereby defeated” (p. 890).

  10. For further explanations of doxastic conservatism see e.g., Chisholm (1980), Foley (1983), Harman (1986), and Vahid (2004).

  11. Lycan (1985, 1988, 2013) and Chisholm (1980) seem to endorse something like this version of doxastic conservatism.

  12. Harman (1986) seems to endorse something like this version of doxastic conservatism.

  13. Brosnan (2011) makes a similar point about how EDAs may fail to undermine justification but lays out the discussion in terms of probabilities of our moral judgments being true.

  14. Bergmann (2005) endorses a similar view.

  15. Steup (2021) endorses a similar view.

  16. In this paper, I focus specifically on doxastic justification. However, propositional justification raises similar complications.

  17. For more on the dialectic surrounding various theories of epistemic justification see e.g., Alston (1993), BonJour (1985), Cohen (2002), Huemer (2000), Huemer (2007), Pryor (2000), and Steup (2018).

  18. See, for example, Foley (1983), Vahid (2004), Feldman (2003), and Christensen (1994).

  19. This example comes from Christensen (1994).

  20. This view is endorsed by Huemer (2007).

  21. Huemer (2007) also adds a basing requirement for justification, which states that S must base the belief that P on the undefeated appearance. However, I will leave this basing requirement aside for the purposes of this paper.

  22. One complication to consider is what an “appearance” might be like in the context of a moral belief as opposed to a perceptual belief. Huemer (2005 p. 102) notes that initial intellectual appearances are intuitions. Thus, a relevant comparison in the moral realm to an appearance may be a moral intuition. For further discussion of appearances within the moral realm, see Fuqua (2021).

  23. Similar concerns are raised by Markie (2005) and Tooley (2013).

  24. While phenomenal conservatism requires evidence or positive reasons for a belief in the form of an appearance, the views I am categorizing as epistemic credentialism require evidence or positive reasons beyond an appearance.

  25. Steup (2004) defends a related view of perceptual justification, which he refers to as internalist reliabilism.

  26. Reliability evidentialism is importantly distinct from more traditional theories of reliabilism in that it is an internalist rather than an externalist theory.

  27. There are a few competing views about what a priori justification entails. For example, Bonjour (1998) argues that an a priori justified belief is one that is justified by appeal to reason or pure thought alone. Kitcher (1984) adds that an a priori justified belief is one that cannot be defeated by experience.

  28. There are also several other more commonly cited issues with reliability evidentialism and similar views. Such issues include epistemic circularity and infinite regress worries. Alston (1993), Fumerton (1988), and Vogel (2000) highlight some of these issues. Others have claimed that reliability evidentialism is overly demanding. See e.g., Huemer (2013).

  29. Alternatively, some may be amenable to the idea that the version of phenomenal conservatism endorsed by Huemer (2007), or the version of strict doxastic conservatism endorsed by Bergmann (2005) are plausible candidates for middle ground theories. However, others may feel that these two theories still make justification too easy to come by in the first place.

  30. I am extremely grateful to two anonymous referees for their helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (1993). The reliability of sense perception. Cornell University Press

  • Bergmann, M. (2005). Defeaters and higher-level requirements. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55(220), 419–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Harvard University Press

  • BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason: A rationalist account of a priori justification. Cambridge University Press

  • Brosnan, K. (2011). Do the evolutionary origins of our moral beliefs undermine moral knowledge? Biology and Philosophy, 26(1), 51–54

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1980). A version of foundationalism. Midwest studies in philosophy, 5, 543–564

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 309–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1994). Conservatism in epistemology. Nous, 28, 69–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • del Rio, A. (2021). Why undermining evolutionary debunkers is not enough.Synthese,1–16

  • Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. New Jersey: Pearson Education, Inc

    Google Scholar 

  • FitzPatrick, W. (2014). Why there is no Darwinian dilemma for ethical realism. In Michael Bergmann, & P. Kain (Eds.), Challenges to moral and religious belief: disagreement and evolution. Oxford University Press

  • FitzPatrick, W. (2015). Debunking evolutionary debunking of ethical realism. Philosophical Studies, 172, 883–904

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1983). Epistemic conservatism. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 43(2), 165–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1988). Foundationalism, conceptual regress, and reliabilism. Analysis, 48(4), 178–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuqua, J. (2021). Ethical mooreanism. Synthese, 1–23

  • Harman, G. (1986). ) Change in View. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2000). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Rowman & Littlefield

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. Springer

  • Huemer, M. (2007). Compassionate phenomenal conservatism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(1), 30–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2013). Phenomenal conservatism uber allies. In Tucker, C. (ed.), 328–350

  • Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality. MIT press

  • Joyce, R. (2016). Essays in moral skepticism. Oxford University Press

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45: 103–125

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). The nature of mathematical knowledge. Oxford University Press on Demand

  • Koon, J. (2021). The epistemology of evolutionary debunking.Synthese

  • Korman, D. Z., & Locke, D. (2020). Against minimalist responses to moral debunking arguments. Oxford studies in metaethics

  • Kyriacou, C. (2019). Evolutionary debunking: the demarcation problem. Logos and Episteme, 10(2), 175–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Levy, Y. (2020). Evolutionary debunking arguments meet evolutionary science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 100, 491–509

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1985). Conservatism and the data base.Manuscript. [JTT]

  • Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. CUP Archive

  • Lycan, W. G. (2013). Phenomenal conservatism and the principle of credulity. Seemings and justification: new essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism, 293–305

  • Markie, P. (2005). The mystery of direct perceptual justification. Philosophical Studies, 126(3), 347–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, J. (2019). When do replies to the evolutionary debunking argument against moral realism beg the question? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(2), 265–280

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plakias, A. (2022). Disagreement and doubts about darwinian debunking. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 1–15.

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34(4), 517–549

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1995). Evolutionary naturalism: selected essays. Routledge

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2012). Evolutionary debunking, moral realism and moral knowledge. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 7, 1–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (2004). Internalist reliabilism. Philosophical Issues, 14, 403–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (2018). Destructive defeat and justificational force: The dialectic of dogmatism, conservatism, and meta-evidentialism. Synthese, 195(7), 2907–2933

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (2021). Defeaters, Higher-Order Evidence, and Epistemic Dilemmas. Epistemic Dilemmas: New Arguments, New Angles

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (2013). Michael Huemer and the principle of phenomenal conservatism. In Tucker, C. (ed.), 306–327

  • Vahid, H. (2004). Varieties of epistemic conservatism. Synthese, 141, 97–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vavova, K. (2014). Debunking evolutionary debunking. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 9, 76–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vavova, K. (2015). Evolutionary debunking of moral realism. Philosophy Compass, 10, 104–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2000). Reliabilism leveled. Journal of Philosophy, 97(11), 602–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

None.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emily Slome M.A..

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest/competing interests

None.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Slome, E. Undermining versus rebutting: options for responding to evolutionary debunking arguments. Synthese 200, 253 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03723-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03723-w

Keywords

Navigation