1 Introduction

“Sensation” is a key notion in both traditional and current philosophical accounts of perception. This “venerable subject” (Peacocke, 1983, p. 4)—long a source of philosophical perplexity—continues to serve as the general heading under which philosophers group their discussions of several basic features of perception.Footnote 1 In particular, the notion of sensation is used to address forms of perceptual “givenness”.Footnote 2

In this paper, I will focus on the question of whether it is possible to grant sensation a role in theories of perception without conceiving the notion as the name for a mythological Given or raising the set of problems typically related to givenness. To do so, I will draw upon Wilfrid Sellars’ attempt to establish a philosophical framework for sensation, reconstructing his argument and mobilizing several of its features in order to develop an account of sensation—not far from Sellars’ own—which is amenable to a contemporary, non-problematic philosophical conception of perception.Footnote 3 To isolate the line of Sellars’ argument that interests me, I will proceed in three steps.

The first is introductory: before getting into details, I will unpack some of the metaphilosophical assumptions underwriting Sellars’ take on sensations. The aim here is to provide the general coordinates for the angle from which he approaches the issue. Sellars notably tends to conceptualize sensation in terms of “conceptual frameworks” (SPR, p. 60). He emphasizes that only by properly understanding the framework under investigation and situating it within a historical (or quasi-genealogical) account of its origins and evolution can we understand when and how things went wrong (and produced our current mistaken interpretations). These general parameters are expressed in a famous passage:

There are two obvious ways in which a philosopher can attack a theory which he believes to be mistaken. He can seek to reduce it to absurdity by developing its implications and showing them to be either mutually inconsistent or incompatible with the incontrovertible. Or he can attempt to trace the error back to its roots, and show why those who defend it have been led to speak as they do. Of these two methods, it is clear that only the latter is capable of definitive results. A mistaken theory can be compared to a symptom of a disease. By the use of inadequate medicaments one can often ‘cure’ the symptoms while leaving the disease untouched. (P, p. 185)

In other words, therapeutic correction of mistaken views involves first constructing the right story, or non-problematic framework, for sensation, and then addressing how such a framework got misinterpreted. Part I of the paper will therefore be guided by the following question: what is the appropriate conceptual role for sensation in our framework for perception? My analysis will focus on Sellars’ famous account of sensation as a concept belonging to the Manifest Image (MI) framework of perception. Unlike other interpreters, I will argue that it is possible to read Sellars’ argument as introducing “sensation” as one part of a larger theory aiming to explain some kinds of overt verbal behavior, not phenomenal properties. In isolating this line of Sellars’ thinking, I will emphasize why it should be distinguished from an alternative stance also present in his work that positions phenomenal properties as explananda—and thus bears different theoretical implications.

In part II of the paper, I will focus on Sellars’ distinct adverbial understanding of sensation. Standard adverbialism about perception is famous for its theoretical unattractiveness and is generally considered a philosophical dead end. Many scholars have argued against it, and some of its most famous proponents, such as Michael Tye, have later come to reject it.Footnote 4 Sellars is often reductively positioned within this family of accounts and consequently sidelined. However, recent conversation has brought new life to adverbialism, with many authors now defending it as a viable theory.Footnote 5 As I will argue, Sellarsian adverbialism is of a non-standard type. On the one hand, it differs from most well-known, traditional adverbialist accounts (such as Tye’s or Ducasse’s) and these differences, as I will highlight, enable it to avoid standard objections to adverbialism (including the intentionality of experience). On the other hand, as I will also show, Sellars’ adverbialism can profit from current philosophical discussions. This is particularly evident vis-à-vis his solution to the Many Property Problem (MPP), since that philosophical issue is often understood to have dealt adverbialism a fatal blow and therefore has also been at the center of its recent rediscovery. After isolating Sellars’ response to this problem, I will assess the compatibility of his views with current positions (especially the account put forth by D’Ambrosio, 2019, 2021).

In the third and final section of the paper, I will focus on phenomenal properties, which are often taken as synonymous with sensation. In light of Sellars’ argument—which positions verbal behavior as the primary explanandum for sensation—I argue that phenomenal properties can be accounted for in a way that does not render them problematic. I will thus build off the interpretation of Sellars’ adverbial theory isolated and contextualized in the first parts of the paper to show how Sellars’ position yields a conception of sensation able to (a) preserve relationality as a basic feature of experience and (b) accommodate the main issues compelling philosophers to introduce “sensation” into accounts of perception (e.g., phenomenal features of perception) without affirming the mythological implications often accompanying the notion. My aim here is twofold: to illuminate a particularly rich line of argument in Sellars’ framework and to show how it can be pursued in current philosophical debates. My general approach in the paper will therefore be to focus on some Sellarsian views while showing how others are not logically implied by the former and can be resisted. The resulting view, which I claim is still Sellarsian, offers a non-problematic form of adverbialism with relevance for current conversations on “sensation”.Footnote 6 This revised Sellarsian account appears to move in the same direction as current strains of “new adverbialism” (D’Ambrosio, 2019, 2021). Perhaps more surprisingly, it is also compatible with direct realism and, in its analysis of the MI, with the idea that perception is relational in nature.

2 What is the question to which the notion of “sensation” is the answer?

In describing the motivations underwriting current theories of perception, Tim Crane notices that

One reason we are provoked to offer a philosophical theory or account of some phenomenon is that the phenomenon is itself intrinsically puzzling, or because some argument is constructed to demonstrate that it is problematic or even impossible. So it is ... with philosophical theories of perception. The sense-data, intentionalist and disjunctivist theories of perception are attempts to answer the apparent contradictions found within the phenomena of perception when we consider certain actual or possible perceptual scenarios. (Crane, 2006, p. 141)

As the passage cited in the introduction shows, Sellars’ interest in how theories of sensation are formulated is guided partly by an additional therapeutic aim: to identify and resolve the philosophical puzzles affecting a number of existing theories (especially those advancing what he famously labelled the Myth of the Given and the version of that myth that we might call the Myth of Sensation).Footnote 7

To perform this therapy, Sellars sets out to properly understand the conceptual framework for sensations or sense impressions, analyzing what Gilbert Ryle has called their “conceptual cartography.”Footnote 8 In fact, Sellars shares a number of stances with Ryle’s metaphilosophical approach—as well as his resulting treatment of “sensation” (Ryle, 1949, 1956)—that helpfully distinguish his approach.Footnote 9 Both Ryle and Sellars consider the endeavor of reconstructing the proper conceptual frameworks for notions such as “sensation” to be the main business of the philosopher. Moreover, both think such reconstructions have therapeutic consequencesFootnote 10 and understand such philosophical analysis as not primarily a positive exercise of theory construction but rather a clarificatory endeavor.Footnote 11 Let’s call this general attitude the Ryle-Sellars approach to sensation: it aims to tackle issues related to sensation by correctly locating the notion in the appropriate conceptual framework.Footnote 12

More specifically—and this points to another, more substantial point of convergence between Ryle and Sellars—they think the right way of framing sensation is to see it as part of a larger theory. Indeed, both are convinced that “sensation” is a theoretical notion, i.e., one that belongs to a theory or proto-theory developed to account for some phenomena concerning perception.Footnote 13 To explain how this theory was formulated, Sellars presents a “quasi-historical argument, a myth in the platonic sense” (SM, p. 165): the famous myth of Jones. This myth constitutes a rational reconstruction of mentalistic vocabulary in non-mentalistic terms. Its basic outline is by now well know and has been widely explored in the scholarship.Footnote 14 What matters for my purposes is the account the myth offers of the role “the framework of sense impression” (SM, p. 53) plays in our explanation of certain kinds of verbal behaviors: in a community of Ryleian ancestors, who have no concepts or vocabulary for inner episodes (and thus must be conceived as “thinking-out-loud” or performing “candid overt speech”),Footnote 15 sensations are introduced by a mythical theorist, the genius Jones, to account for a case of hallucination when a member of the community utters “there is X in front of me” but there is no corresponding object (EPM §60 ff.).Footnote 16 Jones provides the explanatory resources to account for this occurrence by postulating that the hallucinator is in a particular state causally linked to her verbal-conceptual behavior. This state is called “sensation” or “sense impression”.

Let me stress here that for Sellars hallucinations cause various sorts of behaviors that can potentially have “no detectable verbal output” (EPM, §56). In other words, behaviors can be “silent” (de Vries & Triplett, 2005, p. 177). However, although such behaviors (broadly understood) eventually constitute part of the explanandum of the Myth of Jones, they are not the primary explanandum. As Sellars stresses in several later texts, the myth aims above all to explain a more specific kind of behavior:

it is part of this general picture that perceptual thinking out-loud, i.e., candid vocal behavior in perceptual contexts, be the primary explicandum in a philosophical analysis of concepts pertaining to perception (SSIS, p. 400, my emph.).

There is thus evidence to support seeing “perceptual thinking out loud” or “candid vocal behavior” as the explanatory target of Jones’ theory and candid vocal hallucinatory behavior as the corresponding target of sensations.Footnote 17

After having invented this theory (thereby introducing the new vocabulary of “sensation”) to solve the related explanatory demands, Jones then trains members of his community to use it—not only by ascribing sensations to others but also through self-attributions of sensation. Afterwards, Jones “disappeared without a trace” (SM, p. 165). This origin story for “sensation” is only the first part of Sellars’ broader approach to perception, but from a Sellarsian perspective it is sufficient to perform the initial therapeutic function of pointing to a plausible non-mentalistic conception of the notion.Footnote 18

A few things are worth noticing at this point before we address Sellars’ further elaboration of sensation—which is notably presented in adverbial terms. First, as in classical adverbial theories of perception, in Sellars’ myth sensations are introduced through reference to cases of hallucination. Yet unlike classical adverbialism (such as Tye’s and Ducasse’s), the explanandum is not some property of experience, qualitative feature, or experience itself (generally understood in terms of “how things appear to one”) but rather a conceptual response grasped via verbal behavior.Footnote 19 Jones’ definition of sensation does not refer to any fact or property regarding experience. In fact, the story does not seem to rely on the notion of experience at all, especially understood as a modification of one’s state. The concept of experience and its properties are up to this point left out of the picture. This has important consequences for Sellars’ adverbialism, since most criticisms of adverbialism premise their attacks on an experiential definition of sensation.Footnote 20 Second, it is also worth noting that this also applies to phenomenal characteristics of experience: in Sellars’ reconstruction, sensation does not name some form of phenomenal given (in the sense of qualia) or aspect of private experience (what it is like to be in a certain state). At least in this context, Sellars maintains that sensations are not phenomenal features or something “inner”Footnote 21 but rather states of persons in the MI. Third, it is worth recalling two additional well-known points about Sellars’ attempt to de-mentalise sensations: (1) as defined in the proto-theory, sensations are not “intentional”.Footnote 22 Furthermore, (2) they are not apperceived (at least certainly not as sensations, and I will try to suggest they are not apperceived at all) (SM, p. 10, FMPP I, §157. I will come back to this issue). This implies that the criticism of adverbialism as “incapable of doing justice” to the essential fact about perception, “namely its intentionality” (Butchvarov, 1980, p. 272), is misplaced for Sellars’ theory. In a sense, considering what I have said so far, this criticism is neutralized even before the theory’s adverbial characterization even comes to the fore.Footnote 23

At this point, Sellars leaves various aspects of perception still unexplained (putatively intrinsic non-intentional qualitative elements of perception, for instance) or unaccommodated for (e.g., the distinction some contemporary philosophers make between properties of things that appear to us and properties of experience that appear to us), but this openness might represent a positive affordance of Sellars’ conceptual genealogy. Indeed, despite its deliberate minimalism, the theory of Jones bears distinct therapeutic import: it preserves the direct realist intuitions of the MI from the threats posed by the argument of hallucination (more on this in Sect. 1.2), and it reveals interpretations of sensation as a given mental item to be non-compelling by providing an alternative, non-problematic interpretation of the notion compatible with the MI. At the same time, the framework leaves room for further qualification of sensation, if necessary, to accommodate additional phenomena (or conceptual issues which have not yet arisen).Footnote 24

Moreover, this minimalist account allows us to take an important additional step: to locate the origins of what I have called the Myth of Sensation. For Sellars, identifying the origin of this second Myth requires analyzing how the Jonesian interpretation of sensation slipped toward understanding the notion as the name for a phenomenal mental given (with a specific categorial status, apperceived as always already having that status, and sometimes given an epistemically justificatory role). Sellars locates this slippage in a mistaken philosophical understanding of the shift from a third-person use of the term to first-person usage. This shift is not interpreted in light of Jones’ theory but rather as an expression of acquaintance with some form of Givenness. For Sellars, over time and “under Cartesian pressure” (FMPP, 1981, p. 22), this shift from third to first person produced the “myth of sensation”. Yet by correct reconstruction of the original meaning of the notion, we can resist this pressure and avoid getting caught up in the myth.Footnote 25

2.1 Sensation, direct realism, and the Manifest Image of perception

It is worth pausing here briefly to recognize that the general conception of sensation introduced thus far is compatible with a form of direct realism, since within this framework “physical objects are really and directly perceived and … there is no more basic form of (visual) knowledge than seeing physical objects and seeing that they are, for example, red and triangular on this side”(SPR, p. 87). According to Sellars’ MI of perception, when all goes well, people directly perceive objects and their properties: under normal circumstances, attending to an object is not a way of being modified in a certain way nor an experience of mere modification. Only in cases of hallucination do sensations enter as part of our explanations to account for our hallucinatory states. This is compatible with a mixed adverbial account of perception, such as the one recently offered by D’Ambrosio (2019, 2021). According to this “new adverbialism”, perception is a relational and directed activity but can include adverbial components to account for cases in which it is not successful.Footnote 26 Sellars’ account preserves relationality in a similar way—at least (and this is key) in cases of actual perception within the MI framework—while sensations enter the picture only in cases of hallucination.

The understanding of Sellars’ notion of sensation that I have sketched out so far also moves in the general direction of contemporary realist accounts (Locatelli & Wilson, 2017), such as the naïve realism and Object View (OV) advocated by Brewer (2011, 2017). Sellarsians would agree with Brewer’s formulation of OV:

perceptual presentation irreducibly consists in conscious acquaintance with mind-independent physical objects. It is not to be elucidated or further understood, either in terms of a relation of direct acquaintance with mind-dependent entities that are suitably related to mind-independent things, or in terms of a relation with some kind of representational content (Brewer, 2011, p. 109).

For Brewer, as for Sellars, a relational account is what makes perception intelligible, “with the exception of hallucination” (Brewer, 2011, p. 99). Unlike Brewer and the disjunctivists, however, the Sellarsian line that I have been foregrounding identifies hallucinatory cases as the proper theoretical turf for a specific notion of “sensation” which is not a perceptible factor shared by veridical perception and hallucination but rather a proto-theoretical state that specifically explains hallucinatory conceptual behavior.Footnote 27

3 Adverbialism about sensations

Adverbialism is notably a core element of a Sellarsian account of sensation. Traditionally, adverbialism is motivated by the attempt to avoid metaphysical commitment to some controversial perceptible entia non grata (such as sense data) (Jacobson & Putnam, 2014, p. 556; cf. also Tye, 1984, p. 185). This is certainly at least part of the motivation underwriting Sellars’ approach. At the same time, however, another strong reason for adopting adverbialism (e.g., an understanding of sensations as modifications of persons) is that it is naturally consistent with the ontology of the common sense framework in which Sellars’ theory of “sensation” was formulated (i.e. the MI, whose basic category is that of persons). Thus the sensational state of “sensing red” is best construed by the term-introducing genius Jones as a state or modification of persons.Footnote 28 Interpreted adverbially, “sensing red” means sensing in a certain manner, i.e., “sensing-redly”. In a renowned example, sensing redly is “construed as analogous to waltzing” (SSOS, p. 103): it would be incorrect to describe someone dancing a waltz as if there were two entities, the dancer and the waltz, and an additional relation occurring between them. Rather, dancing a waltz is a manner of dancing (waltzing), which describes a nonrelational state of the dancing person (SM, p. 168; SSOS, p. 103; Conrnman, 1978, p. 69). This conception of persons in certain “states” is naturally embedded in the MI, such that Sellars considers adverbialism—and its typical rephrasing of transitive sentences involving the verb “sense” (e.g., “I sense red”) into intransitive adverbial constructions (“I sense redly”)—as mere clarification and not a revisionary metaphysics: “I find these adverbial structures clarifying and reject the view that the task of philosophy is to revise” (RA, p. 294).

Notably, adverbialism is not generally regarded as relevant in theories of perception and, until recently, was commonly considered a philosophical dead end. Recently, however, a new debate has emerged around it, which has led to a reappraisal and defense of its basic insights and their philosophical advantages.Footnote 29 Central in this regard has been discussion of the so-called Many-propery Problem (MPP), the problem traditionally understood to have delivered the coup de grâce to adverbial theories and to which most current proponents of adverbialism must offer solutions. If we want to recover some Sellarsian views on sensation, it is then important to ask whether Sellars’ views are vulnerable to the MPP? What is Sellars’ answer to the problem, and what stances towards it are available to a Sellarsian position as we have constructed it so far?

Before investigating how Sellars did and might have replied to the problem, let me point to a few further, relevant aspects of his view of sensation, which will be essential to grasping Sellars’ reply to the MPP. First, as I have shown above, Sellars’ adverbialism contains some sui generis features that set it apart from standard adverbial theories. One of them is that sensational states are “thoroughly non-cognitive”: their “mediation is causal rather than epistemic” (SPR, p. 91).Footnote 30 As I mentioned earlier, this non-cognitive character implies that we have no awareness of sensations as sensations. This naturally raises the question: what features of sensation cause one to conceptually respond “this is red” and not “this is blue” in the absence of a corresponding object? What is it about sensations that accounts for differentiation in the conceptual response? Jones’ theory has an answer that brings the notion of analogy into the picture: states must have properties analogous to the objects which in standard circumstances bring about a particular conceptual response.

These non-conceptual states must have characteristics which, without being colors are sufficiently analogous to color to enable these states to play this guiding role. (SM, p. 18)

More generally, sensations are states whose characteristics are analogous to the properties of physical objects that in standard cases are conceptually presented in experience.Footnote 31 The analogical interpretation of sensation is introduced by Jones because of its “explanatory power” (ATS, p. 150 and FMPP, p. 72): the analogy constrains and explains the conceptual response associated with the occurrence of a particular sensation. Accordingly, Sellars argues that properties of sensation (“red-ly” and “square-ly”) can be derivatively grasped only in terms of properties and predicates of objects in the MI (such as “red”, “square”, etc.).

Importantly, Sellars stresses that “the analogy is between sense impressions and physical objects and not between sense impressions and perceptions of physical objects” (SPR, p. 93).Footnote 32 This view is consistent with the naïve realist and direct realist insight that the fundamental properties involved in perception (and, in this case, also in non-cognitive sensations) are “to be given precisely by citing and/or describing those very mind-independent physical objects of acquaintance”(Brewer, 2011, p. 94).Footnote 33 Sellars had already endorsed this claim in EPM and in Phenomenalism, arguing for the logical priority of object-talk over look-talk—explaining the latter in terms of the former is essential to his direct realism.Footnote 34

3.1 The Many Property Problem

First raised by Jackson (1975), the MPP is one of the main reasons for the abandonment of adverbial theories of perception. It is no surprise then that the resurgence of adverbialism in recent years has gone hand-in-hand with the advancement of various debated solutions to the problem (Banick, 2018; D’Ambrosio, 2019, 2021; Grzankowski, 2018; Kriegel, 2011). In addition, several authors have argued that the MPP applies not only to adverbialism but also to other kinds of theories of perception, including intentionalist ones (Crane-Grzankowski, unpublished; D’Ambrosio, 2021).

In recent discussions, the MPP is usefully interpreted as resulting from the combination of two problems: the expressive problem and the inference problem.

The expressive problem pertains to the correct reformulation, in adverbial terms, of sentences like

  1. (a.)

    Wilfrid senses a green square and red circle.

The issue arises from the fact that the sentence can be paraphrased as

  1. (b.)

    Wilfrid senses greenly and squarely and redly and circularly.

However, such a paraphrase, which takes the form of a conjunction of adverbial expressions, makes (a.) ultimately indistinguishable from the following sentence

  1. (c.)

    Wilfrid senses a green circle and a red square,

which can be paraphrased in the exact same way.

To solve this expressive problem, one might consider green and square as forming a distinct syntactic unit, and thus paraphrase the sentence with the adverbial terms “green-squarely” and “red-circularly”. The adverbial formulation of (a.) would then become

  1. (d.)

    Wilfrid senses green-squarely and red-circularly.

This would enable distinction between the two cases (a. and c.), but it raises further problems, since sentence (d.) does not validate inferences intuitive to the original phrasing (such as the move from “Wilfrid senses green-squarely” to “Wilfrid senses squarely”). This is the inference problem.

The scholarly debate has already seen various strategies emerge to approach this issue first raised by Jackson.Footnote 35 Sellars’ reply makes clear that he sees the problem located primarily in the ontological and metaphysical assumptions at stake in Jackson’s formulation. For Sellars, Jackson seems to understand “sensing” in a way that suggests a person can engage in only one act of sensing at a time—similar to how one can take only one breath at a time. Yet Sellars argues that this is not necessarily the case.Footnote 36 Indeed, considering multiple simultaneous acts of sensing is the only way to have “an intelligible answer to the many property problem” (ATS, p. 147)”. In Sellars’ words,

the only real hope for an adverbial solution to Jackson’s problem requires that’ there be a legitimate sense, available to adverbialists, in which [1.] a person can be simultaneously engaged in more than one sensing, and in which [2.] one act of sensing can consist of two or more constituent acts of sensing (ATS, p. 147, my numbering)

The adverbialist must find a way to express such a possibility, and this is what guides Sellars: premised in this assumption, he attempts to articulate an answer to the problem of giving expression of this phenomenon.Footnote 37

As a preliminary move, he introduces two corrections to the above-mentioned formulation (d.) “Wilfrid senses red-triangularly”. First, he claims that the correct rephrasing would be to say that Wilfrid senses “a red-triangle-ly”, with the article “a” playing an important role, since it points to the individuation of the sensing state. Second, he stresses that reference to the object is essential to the adverbial reformulation: “a red triangle” must be interpreted as “a red and triangular object” and paraphrased as “(a red and triangular object-)ly”—which is different from simply saying “red-triangular-ly”.Footnote 38 Reference to object locutions is in fact entailed in Sellars’ above-mentioned thesis of analogical counterparts, which states that sensations have properties analogous to objects.

Analogy is indeed fundamental for Sellars’ entire conception of sensation and is also key to his approach to the MPP problem, because he considers the individuation of a sensation possible in terms of the properties of the object that in standard circumstances cause a conceptual response (Tye, 1975). In visual sensations, for instance, the structures and compositions of sensations reflect the structures and compositions of objects that in standard cases (such as seeing) are present in the visual field. In the context of sensation, then, the concept of relations among objects in the visual field is translated into adverbial terms, so “clearly what we need is two-place adverbs pertaining to sensory states” (ATS, p. 153). Sellars acknowledges that such a theory remains largely promissory and still needs to be properly elaborated. Still, the direction in which he is tries to move to work out a solution is clear and based on an extension of the analogical intuitions of the mythological Jones: not only do sensations have properties analogous to the objects that cause them, but they also stand in relation to each other in ways that are analogous to the relation among the corresponding objects.

For example, Sellars introduces the adverbial predicate “adjoinigly” as the counterpart of “adjoining” understood as the relation among objects in space.Footnote 39 The upshot of his view is that “the composition of sensations, thus, is the counterpart of the composition of the objects which are their proper causes” (ATS, p. 154). In this way Sellars thinks he can “specify identity conditions for sensations with respect to a person P and a time t” (ATS, p. 154).Footnote 40 Although the appropriate general ontology of events and states must still be elaborated, Sellars maintains that this general direction offers a way out of the inference problem represented by the MPP.Footnote 41

With these assumptions in place, we can better grasp Sellars’ answer to the two above-mentioned problems. In response to the expressive problem, he maintains that relations among sensations must be expressed via specifically regimented counterpart predicates. In other words,

  1. (a.)

    Wilfrid senses a green square and red circle.

must be rephrased as

  1. (e.)

    Wilfrid senses (a green and square object)-ly adjoining-ly (a red and circular object)-ly.Footnote 42

Sellars thinks that mentioning “object” in the locution “(a green and square object)-ly” is “essential to preserve the structure” (ATS, 154). Preserving the structure—i.e., assuming the analogy of counterparts and relations between objects and sensations—allows us to validate the right inferences, since for Sellars, according to the hypothesis proposed, the conceptual properties of “green” and “square” in an adverbial context “are conveyed by the fact that these same words in physical object discourse stand for an attribute having analogous conceptual properties” (ATS, p. 150). This enables Sellars to claim that “we can justify treating adverbial expressions pertaining to visual sensations as syntactically composite and subject them to the desired logical manipulations” (Ibid., p. 160)—and thus solve the inference problem.

Such a view is far from uncontroversial: the fact that it is based on the simple postulation of a structural analogy may appear to some, in Sellars’ words, to be “theft instead of honest toil” (ATS, 155).Footnote 43 However, what my reconstruction brings to the fore is that Sellars’ views are compatible with (and developed along the same line as) some current strategies for solving the MPP, including the one recently endorsed by D’Ambrosio (2019, 2021). At a general level, the solution provided by D’Ambrosio is built upon an understanding of “sensing” as conceptually dependent on “seeing”. D’Ambrosio conceives this dependence in terms of success conditions, essentially formalizing the idea that successful (i.e., accurate) sensing is seeing (D’Ambrosio, 2021, p. 822). Without going into the details of D’Ambrosio’s analysis, which would be beyond the scope of this paper, we can still identify this assumption as a) first enabling him to construe seeing as essentially relational and b) second specifying sensing in terms of seeing. In this way, D’Ambrosio “takes relational seeing as explanatorily fundamental” (ibid., p. 811). Furthermore, and most importantly, this conception postulates a structural link between discourse on sensing and discourse on seeing, to the extent that the properties of the first can be specified and expressed in terms of the second and thus solve the MPP. D’Ambrosio formalizes the following strategy:

by specifying accuracy conditions for Mary’s sensation, the analysis … shows how structural relationships between properties yield logical relationships between states of sensing those properties, thus validating upward monotonicity, and solving the inferential problem (D’Ambrosio, 2021, p. 823).

This strategy is also open to Sellars, at least in the views that I have reconstructed so far. Again, when all goes well, for Sellars the subject perceives the world in a relational way. In cases of hallucinations, the subject instead “senses”. This state is construed as structurally analogous to seeing, such that inferences in seeing speech can be validated in sensing speech—since, as D’Ambrosio argues, in contexts such as “the case of a hallucination, there simply is no object to which the hallucinating subject is related. This captures the main desiderata on an adverbial view of perception” (Ibid., p. 831).Footnote 44

3.2 Criticism

At this point, some scholars may object that my interpretation moves beyond Sellars and, in a substantial way, against his approach. In fact, in many passages Sellars seems to extend the Myth of Jones to claim that “sensations” are present in all perception. He thus appears to defend “the idea that visual perception always involves sense impressions” (SM, p. 15, my emphasis) and that “direct perception of physical objects is mediated by the occurrence of sense impressions” (ATS, p 150; cf. also SPR, p. 90). I do not want to deny that this line of thought can be identified in Sellars. As my reconstruction suggests, however, these claims are an extension of Sellars’ original Ryleian argument rather than a necessary consequence of it (the myth gets enriched with the idea that sensation mediates not only cases of hallucination but also episodes of veridical perception). It is moreover important to notice that this extension is not logically entailed by the myth’s premises or the Sellarsian argument I have reconstructed, and therefore—even if a position Sellars eventually endorses—it must be argued for on independent grounds. It is these grounds that we might want to question.

For instance, commitment to the claim that sensation mediates all perception (and not only hallucinations) may require acceptance of a stronger ‘common factor’ conception of experience, which, added to what we have seen so far, would lead to considering sensations a constitutive part of veridical experience. However, this is not necessarily so. Similarly, there may well be an argument present in Sellars independent of the Jonesian myth that leads to the same conclusion. Nonetheless, for our purposes what is worth noting is that the claim “sensation always mediates perception” does not come from the argument about hallucination analysed above but from a different route. If extending sensations to normal cases is not philosophically compelling, then Sellars’ alleged commitment to sensation as always involved in perception can be resisted: the mediation of sensation in all experience is not part of the core of Jones’ theory, which allows us to reject this claim and still retain a coherent Sellarsian adverbial take on sensation.Footnote 45 Our resulting theory still preserves all relevant explanatory significance and can perform its therapeutic role.

3.3 Sensation and phenomenal properties

In the reconstruction above, the definition of impressions does not include “phenomenal properties” of experience. Interestingly, what today’s scholars call sensational content (i.e., intrinsic, perceptible non-conceptual properties of experience) does not fall under the Sellarsian heading of “sensation”, at least not directly. The separate treatment of the two issues—sensation, one one hand, and phenomenal aspects on the other—is part of Sellars’ strategy for avoiding conceptual confusion and the insurgence of problematic mythological accounts. However, understood in the general sense, phenomenal features are a constitutive part of perception, which makes the ability to account for them one of the criteria for evaluating the adequacy of a theory of perception. The question thus arises: in following the Sellarsian approach that I have outlined, how should one account for these features of perception? Sellars himself acknowledges, after a phenomenological analysis, that perceptions are characterized by particular sensory modalities:

phenomenologically speaking, the descriptive core consists in the fact that something in some way red and triangular is in some way present to the perceiver other than as thought of (SK, I.55).

This claim is the conclusion of a well-known argument that starts with the difference between “seeing x” and “believing x”Footnote 46 and maintains that the distinctive feature of the former is it involves something like a perceptual presence (something somehow present in perception other than thoughts). How should we conceive of this phenomenal element?

To understand Sellars’ response, we should take a step back to consider what Sellars means by phenomenological analysis. What does he think one learns by performing a phenomenological analysis of one’s experience? Here Sellars’ reflections move in a direction that is again compatible with direct realism: he does not consider phenomenological analysis a special kind of direct inspection or introspection of an element of our experience—i.e., what Tye calls a “quasi-scanning process” (Tye, 2002, p. 144). Rather, the phenomenologist brackets the causal and dispositional properties of the presented objects, as well as some other categorial features of perception. However, doing so does not result in discovery of new entities but in removal of categories that are embedded in perception and pertain to physical object discourse. This is an important aspect of Sellars’ account.

We, as phenomenologists, can bracket the concept of an expanse of red in that radical way which involves an abstraction from all those implications involved in being the concept of something physical. But by so abstracting we do not acquire a concept of red which belongs to a more basic determinate category—we simply abstract from such determinate categorial status it has, and construe it merely as a particular having some determinate categorial status or other. Our phenomenological abstraction no more reveals a new determinate category than the concept of some color or other generates the concept of a new shades of red (FMPP, p. 20, my emph.)

As Jay Rosenberg summarizes, “the phenomenological attitude brackets causal and dispositional properties and the like, but does not shift the sense of sensory quality predicates” (Rosenberg, 2000, p. 146),Footnote 47 which are originally defined as predicates of physical objects. The predicates by which one describes and grasps the phenomenology of one’s experience are thus predicates that pertain to physical objects.Footnote 48

In general, this view is consistent with the direct realist intuitions distinctive of the MI of perception and importantly avoids the perplexity connected to the idea of purely phenomenal properties. The result is an account of the structure of perception that gives strong priority to what, in contemporary terms, can be called “presented elements” over “phenomenal properties” (Martin, 1998, p. 21). This view, however, does not imply that experience is completely transparent or diaphanous (i.e., that differences in phenomenal properties are only differences in presented elements) but—to continue with this non-Sellarsian vocabulary— claims that any specification of phenomenal properties can only be made in terms of properties (i.e., predicates) of presented elements. Understood in this way, a Sellarsian view therefore appeals to the set of arguments on the transparency of experience deployed by direct realists.

A last question might arise at this point: should these phenomenal features of perception be identified with what, in a different line of argument, we have called “sensations”? There seems to be no need to make this connection. Logically, the two lines of argument are separable (Sellars seems to keep them separate),Footnote 49 and nothing of what we have said so far requires integrating them. Though Sellars seems to suggest in more than one place that there is a link between his “theory of sensation” and philosophical reflection on perceptible properties,Footnote 50 there is no philosophical need to connect them. The pressure to unify these frameworks again seems to have different sources which can be rejected or resisted as unnecessary. Also because, as suggested above (§2), keeping the framework of sensation separable from the analysis of phenomenal content enables Sellars to diagnosis the problems around sensation, which can be treated as arising precisely from attempts to merge—for one reason or another—the two levels of analysis (confusing the logical dimension of sensation with the logical dimension of phenomenal content). I will not analyze here how such confusions might be accounted for. It is sufficient to emphasize that there does not seem to be any particular pressure to correlate the two lines of argument.Footnote 51

At an exegetical level, this is another point at which my Sellarsianism might be seen as a heterodox departure from Sellars texts in order to pursue a promising line of argument that is followed on in a Sellarsian spirit. As I hope to have demonstrated, however, the line of Sellars’ thought that I follow reveals how talk of “sense impressions” might have arisen and clarifies how it might have gone wrong, while also pointing to a non-problematic way of understanding sensation.Footnote 52 This is exactly what Sellars’ reflections on sensations aimed to achieve.

4 Conclusions

In this paper, I have presented a reconstruction of Sellars’ adverbialist account of sensation. Keeping in mind his general philosophical method of exploring conceptual frameworks, I have surveyed his adverbialist approach to the notion. I have focused in particular on the Myth of Jones and the argument it contains, unfolding some of its core insights—while showing that others can be resisted—in order to establish it as a viable account of sensation.

In the Sellarsian approach that I have presented, adverbialism about sensation can be integrated into a broader relational conception of experience in which sensation is introduced to perform a particular explanatory role. According to this view, in the MI perception is relational, but cases of hallucination justify the introduction of the notion of “sensation”, which is best understood in adverbial terms. The insights developed in articulating this point are consistent, in a specific sense that I have clarified, with those presented by proposals of a “new adverbialism” such as D’Ambrosio’s (2019, 2021).

In the account I have presented, the notion of “sensation” is introduced and defined in a way that does not expose it to standard criticisms of adverbialism, especially those related to insufficiently accounting for intentionality and the phenomenal character of experience—which I have addressed in the last part of this paper. As heterodox as it may be, my approach is nonetheless recognizably Sellarsian in its emphasis of arguments that are crucial to his account.

As Sellars himself notices, this “framework of sense impressions is not a formalized theory,” which implies that its “force and limitations…must be tickled out piecemeal by exploring the logic of sample uses of the framework.” (SPR, p. 93). Further scholarship is necessary to deepen and widen this Sellarsian framework in both historical and theoretical terms, to refine it, and to address philosophical uses of ‘sensation’ in the past and present. As I have pointed out, further work is also necessary to explore the notion's conceptual apparatus, including the relation between sensation and phenomenal experience that I have excavated.Footnote 53 Sellars is convinced that his treatment of the “broad issues of philosophical strategy, and even a large-scale map of the jungle of perceptual epistemology can bring decisive clarification” (SPR, p. 93). Starting from this premise, I hope to have shown how a Sellarsian approach to sensation can point us towards a both explanatorily adequate and metaphysically acceptable account of this notion.