Skip to main content
Log in

What is so special about episodic memory: lessons from the system-experience distinction

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Compared to other forms of memory, episodic memory is commonly viewed as special for being distinctively metarepresentational and, relatedly, uniquely human. There is an inherent ambiguity in these conceptions, however, because “episodic memory” has two closely connected yet subtly distinct uses, one designating the recollective experience and the other designating the underlying neurocognitive system. Since experience and system sit at different levels of theorizing, their disentanglement is not only necessary but also fruitful for generating novel theoretical hypotheses. To show this, I first argue that accepting the phenomenally conscious contents of episodic remembering as metarepresentational does not necessitate a metarepresentational conception of the episodic memory system. In its stead, I sketch an alternative account on which the metarepresentational character of episodic remembering is generated through the interaction of first-order outputs of the episodic memory system with other neurocognitive components of the brain. Complemented with a first-order account of the memory system, the system-experience distinction further supplies a novel understanding of the human uniqueness of episodic recollection, one that is compatible with there being an evolutionarily conserved episodic memory system. Overall, by distinguishing the two equivocal senses of “episodic memory” in our theorizing, we unearth an opportunity to understand how the distinctive phenomenology of our episodic recollection is related to and implemented in the cognitive architecture.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is now commonly referred to as “what-where-when” information.

  2. Autonoesis is more generally associated with mental time travel, which includes event constructions in both the past and future directions. As Tulving (1985, p. 1) puts it, autonoesis “mediates an individual’s awareness of his or her existence and identity in subjective time extending from the personal past through the present to the personal future”. My concern in this paper is with episodic memory only, and for our purposes, of most relevance is the unique sense of self rather than the temporality of autonoetic consciousness. For general discussions of autonoesis and mental time travel, see Perrin (2016), Perrin and Rousset (2014), and Vandekerckhove and Panksepp (2009).

  3. Some recent phenomenological characterizations do not explicitly put the emphasis on experiential self-awareness as Tulving does. Thus, Dokic (2014) characterizes the phenomenology in terms of what he calls an “episodic feeling of knowing”. Likewise, Fernández (2019) and Perrin et al. (2020) propose that central to episodic remembering is a certain “feeling of pastness”. Note that these characterizations are nevertheless Tulvingian, in that they share a commitment to the unique sense of self as characteristic of episodic remembering. For instance, the notion of the feeling of pastness in recent literature is grounded in the rememberer’s own subjective past, not the past in general (cf. B. Russell, 1921).

  4. The system-experience distinction advocated here is not a controversial one, even though I will say a bit more in Sect. 2 to bring out its significance for our purposes. In her assessment of the (dis)continuism debate, Robins (2020) calls attention to what is essentially the same distinction between episodic remembering, as an occurrent mental state, and the episodic memory system. Why has this distinction been largely overlooked, however? My suggestion is that the two uses of the term “episodic memory”—one designating a conscious state with a distinctive phenomenology, the other designating a neurocognitive system—are both perfectly natural and closely connected. Notwithstanding their connection, they sit at different levels of theorizing, and the exact way in which they are connected is an open and empirical question.

  5. Note that while both claims can be understood as a metarepresentation thesis about episodic memory, only the latter is strictly about the episodic memory system. Here the notion of metarepresentation is that of a representation of a representation as a representation (Perner, 1991), and Tulving himself is ultimately concerned with whether the episodic memory system is metarepresentational in this sense. In proposing an explanation for childhood amnesia, for example, Tulving and colleagues argue for a subtle but what they consider crucial distinction between encoding personally experienced events and encoding events as personally experienced: “[to] episodically remember a prior happening, the episode must have been originally encoded as a subjective experience and integrated into the personal perspective of the rememberer” (Wheeler et al., 1997, p. 346; emphasis added).

  6. I take the representational structure of the memory system to be specified by the contents the system is specialized to store. The qualification “specialized” is important, since, after all, everyone should allow that some contents stored within the episodic memory system are metarepresentational. Some experiences have a metarepresentational structure to begin with (e.g., seeing oneself as dancing, assessing one’s subjective certainty) and will be remembered as such. Moreover, remembering is itself an experience which may be recursively embedded in future remembering states (e.g., remembering oneself remembering). Occasionally storing such metarepresentational contents is compatible with a memory system specialized to store first-order contents.

  7. For the sake of the argument, I take for granted that autonoetic episodic remembering does have a metarepresentational structure, effectively accepting the metarepresentation thesis construed as a claim about episodic recollective experience. To be sure, this is an assumption that some have called into question (see, e.g., Carruthers, 2018; Conway, 2001; Ganeri, 2017). But my goal here is to make the case that even accepting it does not lead to the conclusion that the episodic memory system is metarepresentational.

  8. While not specifically focusing on episodic memory, Kriegel (2015) suggests that the phenomenology may be better explained under nonreductive representationalism. His idea is that when we episodically remember an event and experience it as past, this pastness is not part of what is represented (i.e., a conceptual ingredient of the content), but rather an aspect of how the remembering represents what it does (i.e., an irreducible mode of presentation). Additionally, an anonymous referee suggests that another option would be to consider how the phenomenology might be explained in a non-representationalist approach to consciousness. In what follows, I will have to set these intriguing suggestions aside. The literature by and large assumes a reductive representationalist approach, so I will not circumvent a methodological commitment shared by my interlocutors.

  9. Here I choose two general findings from vision primarily because vision science is arguably one of the more mature branches of cognitive psychology, the lessons of which may be reasonably expected to generalize. Masked priming occurs when certain target stimuli are presented for short durations and then masked by other stimuli, such that participants will report not having seen the target stimuli, even though the influence of the target stimuli can be observed in downstream behavior. Initial findings in support of the ventral-dorsal split come from blindsight patients, who, despite their lack of conscious experience within an area of their visual field, were able to appropriately control their motor actions. The phenomenon has since been investigated in neurological and neural network-based studies as well (Fang & He, 2005; Goodale, 2014; Milner & Goodale, 1995; Weiskrantz, 1999). Notably, the ventral-dorsal split fits a general pattern that many cognitive tasks can be performed in the absence of conscious awareness (for a review and discussion, see Shea & Frith, 2016). As a relevant further example, recent evidence shows that individuals with aphantasia (who self-reportedly lack voluntary visual imagery) can perform just as well as typical individuals on imagery-related memory tasks, likewise suggesting a dissociation between conscious experience and cognitive function (Keogh et al., 2021; Pounder et al., 2021).

  10. Epistemic generativity is a technical notion first introduced in epistemology (Lackey, 2005). For our purposes, the basic idea behind it can be illustrated by the observation that in remembering something episodically one does not merely know that such-and-such happened, but also knows why one knows, viz. on the basis of remembering (see also Dokic, 2001; Fernández, 2016). On the account offered by Mahr and Csibra (2018), this is because episodic recollection comes with a representation of its own origin.

  11. It is somewhat surprising that theorists working in the generative framework have not said more to flesh out these different and potentially other possibilities. But there are two exceptions. McCarroll (2018) proposes that observer memory involves an implicit representation of the self via a particular mode of presentation of the past event. Likewise, Cheng, Werning and Suddendorf (2016) suggest that autonoesis may be grounded in either the perspectival character or the phenomenological transparency of the constructed scenario. I have some reservations about these proposals, which will become clear shortly.

  12. Consider, for example, how in seeing something as being a certain distance away in that direction, the organism’s internal representation of the object constitutively involves information associated with the organism’s egocentric perspective. It is relative to this perspective that the location of the object is specified, but the perspective itself need not be represented as such. This is the sense in which perceptual experience involves minimal self-representation.

  13. What if we locate metarepresentational embedding strictly at the stage of retrieval, thus within the bounds of the episodic memory system? In this case, the contents stored within the episodic memory system can be purely first-order—including both the what-where-when information and self-representation. But they are not merely retrieved alongside each other; rather, when retrieved they are combined into metarepresentations before becoming available to downstream “consumer” systems. This, then, may be another way for a first-order memory system to give rise to autonoetic episodic remembering. While such an organization of the episodic memory system is certainly possible, it seems rather mysterious as to why the retrieved-as-metarepresentational contents are not instead encoded as metarepresentational and stored as such in the first place. There is certainly more to be said here, but fleshing out the proposal and its implications would go beyond the scope of this paper.

  14. We may call such temptations to conflate features of representational content of conscious experience and features of discrete neurocognitive systems “feature internalizing”. This is analogous to what Millikan (1991) calls “content internalizing”, a mistake that projects representational content to the vehicles of representations.

  15. Indeed, Perrin et al.’s (2020) metacognitive account of the phenomenology of episodic recollection is one in which the feeling of pastness is developmentally enriched by other acquired concepts such as self and causality.

  16. A consequence is that, in the same way that we do not have direct, privileged access to others’ minds, the interpretive sensory-access theory contends that we do not have direct, privileged access to our own minds either. In my view, the interpretive sensory-access theory is well-supported by behavioral, imaging, and neuropsychological evidence (see also Carruthers, 2013; Cassam, 2014; Rimkevičius, 2020). But a full defense is beyond the scope of what can be accomplished in the space available. Hence, I will instead motivate utilizing this theory with the uncontroversial idea that memory is, after all, a form of knowledge and that episodic memory in particular is viewed as a form of self-knowledge. Developed to explicate the nature of self-knowledge, the interpretive sensory-access theory is thus well-suited for our purposes.

  17. It is an ongoing debate as to what the types of heuristic cues are utilized by memory monitoring. For my purposes, I am not taking a stand on whether the cues are based on contents or procedural features. Hence here I include cues of both types.

  18. This account assumes that remember is part of the conceptual repertoire of the mindreading system. Also assumed to be part of the mindreading system are implicit inferential rules such as “remembering entails knowing”, “reporting that one remembers that such-and-such entails that one remembers that such-and-such”. Whereas the development of the conceptual repertoire and inferential rules of the mindreading system is a matter of ongoing investigation, that the mindreading system in human adults is thus equipped is not in dispute.

  19. I thank an anonymous referee for inviting me to further clarify my thinking on these issues.

  20. It is telling, in this regard, that the so-called minimalist approach to episodic memory and its development is motivated precisely by deference to the conceptual richness of autonoetic remembering (J. Russell, 2014; J. Russell & Hanna, 2012). If what I have been arguing is on the right track, however, this deference is not really necessary.

  21. Charitably understood, the human uniqueness thesis is purely negative: extant evidence does not substantiate the proposition that nonhuman animals have episodic memory. In this sense, the human uniqueness thesis serves as a null hypothesis. But devising an apt null hypothesis in comparative cognition research is not as straightforward as it may seem (Andrews & Huss, 2014; Mikhalevich, 2015), and as I shall argue, the logical strength of the human uniqueness thesis is particularly strong even as a null hypothesis, especially when the system-experience distinction is not drawn.

  22. Recall that for human beings, episodic memory is standardly assessed by the remember/know paradigm, wherein the subjects verbally report either remembering or merely knowing something. This paradigm plainly is not applicable to nonhuman animals.

  23. Tulving’s (2005) own suggestion to comparative psychologists is to look for evidence of future-directed mental time travel in nonhuman animals. But this likely only pushes the question one step back. For the same considerations that count against attributing episodic memory to nonhuman animals on the basis of non-linguistic behavioral evidence will likely count against attributing future-directed mental time travel to nonhuman animals as well (Suddendorf, 2013).

  24. This point applies to cases involving neuropsychological patients and young children as well (see, e.g., Klein & Nichols, 2012; J. Russell, 2014), where the disputes in my view are not about different theoretical possibilities, but are instead due to different opinions regarding what the equivocal term “episodic memory” denotes.

  25. This is related to a point recently raised by Craver (2020) regarding what he calls the “epistemic” versus “empirical” conception of episodic memory. While he is not concerned with the human uniqueness thesis in particular, Craver urges against assuming that the epistemic conception on which episodic remembering is an epistemic achievement can be reduced to the episodic memory system. One reason for this is that as an epistemic achievement, remembering as we know it is part of a much larger practice of communicating as well as tracking what we know about the world. It is thus likely to implicate more cognitive resources than a memory system specialized for storing and retrieving information.

References

  • Alba, J. W., & Hasher, L. (1983). Is memory schematic? Psychological Bulletin, 93(2), 203–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, T. A., & Fortin, N. J. (2013). The evolution of episodic memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110(Supplement 2), 10379–10386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews, K., & Huss, B. (2014). Anthropomorphism, anthropectomy, and the null hypothesis. Biology and Philosophy, 29(5), 711–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Muñoz, S. (2019). Cognitive phenomenology and metacognitive feelings. Mind and Language, 34(2), 247–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bachmann, T., & Francis, G. (2013). Visual masking: Studying perception, attention, and consciousness. Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, J. (2012). Do animals engage in conceptual thought? Philosophy Compass, 7(3), 218–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, A. (2020). The impure phenomenology of episodic memory. Mind and Language, 35(5), 641–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2013). Morgan’s canon, meet hume’s dictum: Avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons. Biology and Philosophy, 28(5), 853–871.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1998). Reason and the first person. In C. Wright, B. C. Smith, & C. Macdonald (Eds.), Knowing our own minds (pp. 243–270). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading the self. In S. Baron-Cohen, M. Lombardo, & H. Tager-Flusberg (Eds.), Understanding other mind: Perspectives from developmental social neuroscience (pp. 467–486). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2018). Episodic memory isn’t essentially autonoetic. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 41, e6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2014). Self-knowledge for humans. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, S., & Werning, M. (2016). What is episodic memory if it is a natural kind? Synthese, 193(5), 1345–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, S., Werning, M., & Suddendorf, T. (2016). Dissociating memory traces and scenario construction in mental time travel. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 60, 82–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., & Dickinson, A. (1998). Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature, 395(6699), 272–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., Emery, N. J., & Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: Complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational Animals? (pp. 197–216). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M. A. (2001). Phenomenological records and the self-memory system. In C. Hoerl & T. McCormark (Eds.), Time and memory (pp. 235–255). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2020). Remembering: Epistemic and empirical. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11, 261–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dally, J. M., Emery, N. J., & Clayton, N. S. (2006). Food-caching western scrub-jays keep track of who was watching when. Science, 312(5780), 1662–1665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2001). Is memory purely preservative? In C. Hoerl & T. McCormack (Eds.), Time and memory (pp. 213–232). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2014). Feeling the past: A two-tiered account of episodic memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(3), 413–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eacott, M. J., & Norman, G. (2004). Integrated memory for object, place, and context in rats: A possible model of episodic-like memory? Journal of Neuroscience, 24(8), 1948–1953.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eichenbaum, H., Fortin, N. J., Ergorul, C., Wright, S. P., & Agster, K. L. (2005). Episodic recollection in animals: “If it walks like a duck and quacks like a duck….” Learning and Motivation, 36(2), 190–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fang, F., & He, S. (2005). Cortical responses to invisible objects in the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nature Neuroscience, 8(10), 1380–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, J. (2006). The intentionality of memory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(1), 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, J. (2016). Epistemic generation in memory. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92(3), 620–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández, J. (2019). Memory: A self-referential account. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, J. (2017). Mental time travel and attention. Australasian Philosophical Review, 1(4), 353–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, J. (1988). Functional aspects of recollective experience. Memory and Cognition, 16(4), 309–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, J., & Richardson-Klavehn, A. (2000). Remembering and knowing. In E. Tulving & F. I. M. Craik (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of memory (pp. 229–244). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A. (2014). How (and why) the visual control of action differs from visual perception. Proceedings of the Royal Society b: Biological Sciences, 281(1785), 20140337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences, 15(1), 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, T. J., Myggland, A., Duperreault, E., May, Z., Gallup, J., Powell, R. A., Schalomon, M., & Digweed, S. M. (2016). Episodic-like memory in zebrafish. Animal Cognition, 19(6), 1071–1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irish, M., Lawlor, B. A., O’Mara, S. M., & Coen, R. F. (2011). Impaired capacity for autonoetic reliving during autobiographical event recall in mild Alzheimer’s disease. Cortex, 47(2), 236–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irish, M., & Piguet, O. (2013). The pivotal role of semantic memory in remembering the past and imagining the future. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keogh, R., Wicken, M., & Pearson, J. (2021). Visual working memory in aphantasia: Retained accuracy and capacity with a different strategy. Cortex, 143, 237–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keven, N. (2016). Events, narratives and memory. Synthese, 193(8), 2497–2517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B. (2013). Making the case that episodic recollection is attributable to operations occurring at retrieval rather than to content stored in a dedicated subsystem of long-term memory. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 7, 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B. (2014). Autonoesis and belief in a personal past: An evolutionary theory of episodic memory indices. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(3), 427–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S. B., & Nichols, S. (2012). Memory and the sense of personal identity. Mind, 121(483), 677–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., & Goldsmith, M. (1996). Monitoring and control processes in the strategic regulation of memory accuracy. Psychological Review, 103(3), 490–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., Goldsmith, M., & Pansky, A. (2000). Toward a psychology of memory accuracy. Annual Review of Psychology, 51(1), 481–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kouwenberg, A.-L., Walsh, C. J., Morgan, B. E., & Martin, G. M. (2009). Episodic-like memory in crossbred Yucatan minipigs (Sus scrofa). Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 117(3–4), 165–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2015). Experiencing the present. Analysis, 75(3), 407–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurilla, B. P., & Westerman, D. L. (2008). Processing fluency affects subjective claims of recollection. Memory and Cognition, 36(1), 82–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2005). Memory as a generative epistemic source. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(3), 636–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lind, S. E., & Bowler, D. M. (2008). Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness in autism spectrum disorders: The roles of self-awareness, representational abilities, and temporal cognition. In J. Boucher & D. M. Bowler (Eds.), Memory in autism: Theory and evidence (pp. 166–187). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and experience. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahr, J. B., & Csibra, G. (2018). Why do we remember? The communicative function of episodic memory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 41(E1), 1–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markowitsch, H., & Staniloiu, A. (2011). Memory, autonoetic consciousness, and the self. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(1), 16–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maunsell, J. H. (2015). Neuronal mechanisms of visual attention. Annual Review of Vision Science, 1, 373–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarroll, C. (2018). Remembering from the outside. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2001). The child in time: Temporal concepts and self-consciousness in the development of episodic memory. In C. Moore & K. Lemmon (Eds.), The self in time: Developmental perspectives (pp. 203–227). Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2011). Is memory a natural kind? Memory Studies, 4(2), 170–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2012). Metacognition and endorsement. Mind and Language, 27(3), 284–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2016a). Mental time travel: Episodic memory and our knowledge of the personal past. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2016b). Confabulating, misremembering, relearning: The simulation theory of memory and unsuccessful remembering. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhalevich, I. (2015). Experiment and animal minds: Why the choice of the null hypothesis matters. Philosophy of Science, 82(5), 1059–1069.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1991). Perceptual content and Fregean myth. Mind, 100(4), 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, E. A., Wise, S. P., & Graham, K. S. (2018). Representational specializations of the hippocampus in phylogenetic perspective. Neuroscience Letters, 680, 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musholt, K. (2013). Self-consciousness and nonconceptual content. Philosophical Studies, 163(3), 649–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owens, D. (1996). A Lockean theory of memory experience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(2), 319–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pastalkova, E., Itskov, V., Amarasingham, A., & Buzsáki, G. (2008). Internally generated cell assembly sequences in the rat hippocampus. Science, 321(5894), 1322–1327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1986). Analogue content. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 60(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (2000). Memory and theory of mind. In E. Tulving & F. I. M. Craik (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of memory (pp. 297–312). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (2001). Episodic memory: Essential distinctions and developmental implications. In C. Moore & K. Lemmon (Eds.), The self in time: Developmental perspectives (pp. 181–202). Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., & Ruffman, J. (1995). Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: Developmental evidence and a theory of childhood amnesia. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 59(3), 516–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrin, D., Michaelian, K., & Sant’Anna, A. (2020). The phenomenology of remembering is an epistemic feeling. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, Article 1531.

  • Perrin, D. (2016). Asymmetries in subjective time. In K. Michaelian, S. B. Klein, & K. K. Szpunar (Eds.), Seeing the future: Theoretical perspectives on future-oriented mental time travel (pp. 39–61). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Perrin, D., & Rousset, S. (2014). The episodicity of memory: Current trends and issues in philosophy and psychology. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(3), 291–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piolino, P., Desgranges, B., Clarys, D., Guillery-Girard, B., Taconnat, L., Isingrini, M., & Eustache, F. (2006). Autobiographical memory, autonoetic consciousness, and self-perspective in aging. Psychology and Aging, 21(3), 510–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pounder, Z., Jacob, J., Evans, S., Loveday, C., Eardley, A., & Silvanto, J. (2021). Individuals with congenital aphantasia show no significant neuropsychological deficits on imagery-related memory tasks [Preprint]. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/gqayt

  • Rasmussen, A. S., & Berntsen, D. (2011). The unpredictable past: Spontaneous autobiographical memories outnumber autobiographical memories retrieved strategically. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(4), 1842–1846.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, A. S., Ramsgaard, S. B., & Berntsen, D. (2015). Frequency and functions of involuntary and voluntary autobiographical memories across the day. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice, 2(2), 185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redshaw, J. (2014). Does metarepresentation make human mental time travel unique? Does metarepresentation make human mental time travel unique? Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 5(5), 519–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renoult, L., Irish, M., Moscovitch, M., & Rugg, M. D. (2019). From knowing to remembering: The semantic–episodic distinction. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(12), 1041–1057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rimkevičius, P. (2020). The interpretive-sensory access theory of self-knowledge: Empirical adequacy and scientific fruitfulness. Problemos, 97, 150–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robins, S. (2020). Defending Discontinuism, Naturally. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(2), 469–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1921). The analysis of mind. George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J. (2014). Episodic memory as re-experiential memory: Kantian, developmental, and neuroscientific currents. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(3), 391–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J., & Hanna, R. (2012). A minimalist approach to the development of episodic memory. Mind and Language, 27(1), 29–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salwiczek, L. H., Watanabe, A., & Clayton, N. S. (2010). Ten years of research into avian models of episodic-like memory and its implications for developmental and comparative cognition. Behavioural Brain Research, 215(2), 221–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society b: Biological Sciences, 362(1481), 773–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N., & Frith, C. D. (2016). Dual-process theories and consciousness: The case for `Type Zero’ cognition. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2016(1), niw005.

  • Sheth, B. R., & Young, R. (2016). Two visual pathways in primates based on sampling of space: Exploitation and exploration of visual information. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience, 10.

  • Spence, C. (2011). Crossmodal correspondences: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 73(4), 971–995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Squire, L. R. (1992). Memory and the hippocampus: A synthesis from findings with rats, monkeys, and humans. Psychological Review, 99(2), 195–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T. (2013). Mental time travel: Continuities and discontinuities. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(4), 151–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (2007). The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(3), 299–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson (Eds.), Organization of memory (pp. 381–403). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1985). Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology/psychologie Canadienne, 26(1), 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2002). Episodic memory: From mind to brain. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? In H. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The Missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness (pp. 3–56). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Umbach, G., Kantak, P., Jacobs, J., Kahana, M., Pfeiffer, B. E., Sperling, M., & Lega, B. (2020). Time cells in the human hippocampus and entorhinal cortex support episodic memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(45), 28463–28474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Woerkum, B. (2021). The evolution of episodic-like memory: The importance of biological and ecological constraints. Biology and Philosophy, 36(2), 11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vandekerckhove, M., & Panksepp, J. (2009). The flow of anoetic to noetic and autonoetic consciousness: A vision of unknowing (anoetic) and knowing (noetic) consciousness in the remembrance of things past and imagined futures. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(4), 1018–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L. (1999). Consciousness lost and found: A neuropsychological exploration. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. A., Stuss, D. T., & Tulving, E. (1997). Toward a theory of episodic memory: The frontal lobes and autonoetic consciousness. Psychological Bulletin, 121(3), 331–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectiviy and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful comments and discussions, I am grateful to Juan Álvarez, Vilius Dranseika, Chris Masciari, Chris McCarroll, Denis Perrin, Aida Roige, and Alvin Zhou. I thank Peter Carruthers, Kirk Michaelian, and André Sant'Anna for their encouragement as well as extensive comments on multiple earlier drafts. An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Issues in Philosophy of Memory 2; I am grateful to the participants for their questions. Finally, I thank the two anonymous reviewers for providing valuable comments and suggestions on how to improve this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shen Pan.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pan, S. What is so special about episodic memory: lessons from the system-experience distinction. Synthese 200, 5 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03500-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03500-9

Keywords

Navigation