Skip to main content
Log in

What epistemologists of testimony should learn from philosophers of science

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The thesis of this paper is that, if it is construed individualistically, epistemic justification does not capture the conditions that philosophers of science would impose on justified belief in a scientific hypothesis. The difficulty arises from beliefs acquired through testimony. From this I derive a lesson that epistemologists generally, and epistemologists of testimony in particular, should learn from philosophers of science: we ought to repudiate epistemic individualism and move towards a more fully social epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Wellbourne (1986), Hardwig (1991), Faulkner (2000), Lackey (2006), Schmitt (2006), and Goldberg (2010). Interestingly, the topic has received a bit more sustained attention in the philosophy of science literature. See e.g. Solomon (2001), Longino (2002) and Miller (2015).

  2. The literature here is vast. For seminal work see Fricker (1987, 1994), Coady (1992), Burge (1993), and Audi (1997).

  3. See E. Fricker (1987; 1995; 2006a; 2006b); Fumerton (2006); Audi (1997); and many others. These views are critically discussed in Wright (2016); Madison (2016) replies to Wright.

  4. See Goldman (2001) and Kenyon (2012).

  5. See Lehrer (2006).

  6. See Tucker (2016), Philips et al. (unpublished MS).

  7. See Shogenji (2006).

  8. See Lipton (2007).

  9. See A. Goldman (1999) and many others. Of course, such reliabilist views hold that the reliability properties of the process-type by which an audience A apprehends and monitors testimony will be affected by the preponderance of true testimonies in A’s environment. Still, this is seen as an environmental condition (akin to the perceptual invariances in one’s perceptual environment), rather than as an admission that others’ epistemic perspective bears on the epistemic goodness of one’s own beliefs.

  10. I thank an anonymous referee of this journal for indicating the need to address this.

  11. I thank an anonymous referee for urging that I consider this concern; I am borrowing some of the language in which I am formulating the concern from the referee report itself.

  12. I do not assume here that the non-testimonial case cannot involve any testimony; only that it does not involve a testimony of H itself.

  13. See e.g. Longino (2002).

  14. For a description of a real-life example of something in this vicinity, see Miller (2015).

  15. As Branden Fitelson has emphasized (2008: pp. 618–19), any attempt to connect ‘justification’ in the philosophy of science sense (or at least that which was in play in confirmation theory a la Carnap) with that in epistemology will require significant “bridging principles.” The point I will be making in what follows is consistent with Fitelson’s point.

  16. I thank an anonymous referee for pointing out the need to make this point.

  17. The claim that they are required is the reductionist position. My present point is simply that one can still wonder whether this is so even after INDIVIDUALISM is rejected. Of course, if INDIVIDUALISM is rejected, then to embrace reductionism is to hold that adequate positive reasons rationalize acceptance without ensuring that the resulting belief is justified. But such ‘hybrid’ views are familiar; see e.g. Faulkner (2000) and Lackey (1999).

  18. See the references in footnotes 3–9.

  19. By ‘the scientific evidence itself’ I have in mind the sort of evidence that is gathered in scientific inquiry.

  20. The point here was first made by Hardwig (1991). Hardwig took the point to indicate the ineliminable role of trust in scientific communities. I take the point to indicate something slightly different (for which see below).

  21. See Longino (2002), Meeker (2004), Wylie and Nelson (2007), Elgin (2017), and Anderson (2020, Sect. 6).

  22. This point was emphasized by Longino (2002) and is discussed at length in Kitcher (2011).

  23. This was the absurdity of the idea that a non-scientist S can have better, more probative evidence for a scientific hypothesis than the source scientist on whose testimony S is relying.

  24. See Goldberg (2014) for an articulation of this notion and a defense of its applicability to the case of testimony.

  25. In presenting this notion of reliance, I am following Holton (1994).

  26. Such reasons are relevant to the rationality of my reliance; but they don’t serve to vindicate that reliance.

  27. I offered an extended defense of the argument to follow in Goldberg (2010).

  28. This was the picture on which the de re nature of our reliance in testimony cases is only manifest when it comes to the knowledgeableness of a testimonial belief.

  29. This is why they analyze INADEQUATE SCIENTIFIC TESTIMONY in a manner analogous to STOPPED CLOCK: a case in which the badness in the source affects knowledge but not justification.

References

  • Anderson, E. (2020). Feminist epistemology and philosophy of science. In Zalta, E. N. (ed). The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/feminism-epistemology/>.

  • Audi, R. (1997). The place of testimony in the fabric of knowledge and justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34(4), 405–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2017). True enough. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faulkner, P. (2000). The social character of testimonial knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 97(11), 581–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (2008). Goodman’s ‘new riddle.’ Journal of Philosophical Logic, 37(6), 613–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (1987). The epistemology of testimony. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 61, 57–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (1994). Against gullibility. In B. K. Matilal & A. Chakrabarti (Eds.), Knowing from Words (pp. 125–161). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (2006a). Second-hand knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 592–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (2006b). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225–250). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2006). The epistemic role of testimony: Internalist and externalist perspectives. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 77–92). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2010). Relying on Others. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2014). Interpersonal epistemic entitlements. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 159–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(1), 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 88(12), 693–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton, R. (1994). Deciding to trust, coming to believe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72(1), 63–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenyon, T. (2012). The informational richness of testimonial contexts. Philosophical Quarterly, 63(250), 58–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2006). It takes two to tango: Beyond reductionism and non-reductionism in the epistemology of testimony. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 160–189). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (1999). Testimonial knowledge and transmission. Philosophical Quarterly, 49(197), 471–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (2006). Testimony and trustworthiness. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 145–159). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2007). Alien abduction: Inference to the best explanation and the management of testimony. Episteme, 4(3), 238–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Madison, B. (2016). Internalism in the epistemology of testimony redux. Erkenntnis, 81(4), 741–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meeker, K. (2004). Justification and the social nature of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 156–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (2015). Why (some) knowledge is the property of a community and possibly none of its members. Philosophical Quarterly, 65(260), 417–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimtt, F. (2006). Testimonial justification and transindividual reasons. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 193–225). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (2006). A defense of reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs. Noûs, 40(2), 331–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, A. (2016). The generation of knowledge from multiple testimonies. Social Epistemology, 30(3), 251–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welbourne, M. (1986). The community of knowledge. Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. (2016). Internalism in the epistemology of testimony. Erkenntnis, 81(1), 69–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A., & Nelson, L. (2007). Coming to terms with the values of science: Insights from feminist science studies scholarship. In H. Kincaid, J. Dupré, & A. Wylie (Eds.), Value free science? Ideals and illusions (pp. 58–87). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to express my gratitude to various people with whom I have discussed these topics over the past several years: Peter Graham, Kareem Khalifa, Chris Kelp, Tim Kenyon, Jennifer Lackey, Jack Lyons, Boaz Miller, Carry Osborne, Baron Reed, and Mona Simion. Thanks as well to three referees from this journal, for their very thoughtful comments on earlier versions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sanford C. Goldberg.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the topical collection “New Directions in Social Epistemology”, edited by Adam Carter and Christoph Kelp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldberg, S.C. What epistemologists of testimony should learn from philosophers of science. Synthese 199, 12541–12559 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03342-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03342-x

Keywords

Navigation