Skip to main content
Log in

Calculus as method or calculus as rules? Boole and Frege on the aims of a logical calculus

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

By way of a close reading of Boole and Frege’s solutions to the same logical problem, we highlight an underappreciated aspect of Boole’s work—and of its difference with Frege’s better-known approach—which we believe sheds light on the concepts of ‘calculus’ and ‘mechanization’ and on their history. Boole has a clear notion of a logical problem; for him, the whole point of a logical calculus is to enable systematic and goal-directed solution methods for such problems. Frege’s Begriffsschrift, on the other hand, is a visual tool to scrutinize concepts and inferences, and is a calculus only in the thin sense that every possible transition between sentences is fully and unambiguously specified in advance. While Frege’s outlook has dominated much of philosophical thinking about logical symbolism, we believe there is value—particularly in light of recent interest in the role of notations in mathematics and logic—in reviving Boole’s idea of an intrinsic link between, as he put it, a ‘calculus’ and a ‘directive method’ to solve problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Wilson (2006, p. 523).

  2. These expressions should be approached with caution, as they have been used for various purposes and interpreted in numerous different ways; for further discussion, see Sect. 6 below, in particular note 50. Note that Frege generally writes lingua characterica, but that other authors typically use lingua characteristica instead. Nothing much hinges on this, but for reference, here is the source of the discrepancy: Leibniz, who coined the phrase, actually used the latter spelling; the former (mistaken) spelling comes from a spurious title for one of Leibniz’s manuscripts introduced by a much-circulated eighteenth-century edition (Raspe 1765), which was then used by Trendelenburg (1856), Frege’s main source on the topic. We thank an anonymous reviewer for this remark.

  3. See below, especially footnote 14, p. 7.

  4. We are here glossing on Boole’s own account (see in particular (Boole 1854, ch. XV, pp. 226–242), and not aiming for a historically accurate rendition of the goals of syllogistic.

  5. Boole (1854, p. 59).

  6. In fact, Boole uses indefinite class symbols ambiguously, a difficulty that we shall point out here but ignore in the sequel, as it does not bear on our main points. In most settings, he takes such symbols to be absolutely indefinite, that is, to denote a class that can be empty, equal to the full universe of discourse, or anything in between. But Boole also translates the Aristotelian form ‘Some \(A\) is \(B\)’ as \(va=vb\), in which—if the traditional interpretation of such forms is to be preserved—\(v\) has to be interpreted as an indefinite non-empty class. For a careful discussion written from a Boolean perspective, see Venn (1881, ch. VI–VII).

  7. Boole (1854, pp. 134–137). We follow Boole’s rendition of Aristotle; the passage in question is Nicomachean Ethics II.5 (1105b20–1106a15).

  8. In traditional tables of the canonical syllogistic forms, there are other restrictions, which Boole neglects (it is expected that the major term will come first, for instance). The discrepancy arises because Boole does not fully do justice to traditional logic: he takes syllogistic’s classification of inference forms as a full-fledged theory of reasoning, whereas traditional textbooks would also contain a broader theory exploring how non-canonical pieces of reasoning are to be brought into one of the standard forms. This need not detain us further, as we are only concerned with Boole’s own portrayal of syllogistic.

  9. There is yet another form that can be requested of the conclusion: one may want the list of those combinations of the selected terms that are excluded by the premises, i.e., that correspond to classes that the premises force to be empty (for more on this, see Sect. 4 below). In Boole’s system, this amounts to seeking an equation of the form \(V=0\), in which \(V\) is a sum of combinations of class symbols or their negations; such an equation is equivalent to having each of the members of the sum be separately equal to 0. This form is the most exhaustive, being equivalent to the premises (or to the premises once elimination has been performed, if some terms have been eliminated), whereas equations of the form \(x=\ldots \) will usually be weaker.

  10. Boole (1854, p. 10). Note that Boole uses the word ‘premise’ to refer to the data, or given relations, of the kind of logical problems he considers; the word thus takes on a broader meaning than may be usual (i.e., it does not refer merely to the starting points of some individual inference).

  11. Boole (1854, p. 165).

  12. Boole (1854, pp. 168–169)

  13. Boole (1854, pp. 178–179).

  14. Schröder (1877, pp. 25–28), Lotze (1884, pp. 219–221) = Lotze (1912, pp. 265–267), Wundt (1880, vol. 1, pp. 356–357), Frege (1979, pp. 39–45) = Frege (1969, pp. 45–51), Venn (1881, pp. 280–281), and McColl (1878, pp. 23–25). That this single problem has been solved by logicians of various outlooks whose solutions would repay further comparison has already been noted by Gabriel (1989, p XXIII).

  15. See Boole (1854), pp. 146–147.

  16. As Boole puts it, ‘It will be observed, that in each of the three data, the information conveyed respecting the properties \(A\), \(B\), \(C\), and \(D\), is complicated with another element, \(E\), about which we desire to say nothing in our conclusion. It will hence be requisite to eliminate the symbol representing the property \(E\) [\(\ldots \)]’ (Boole 1854, p. 146).

  17. Note that \(\Delta \) is our own notation to denote some arbitrary algebraic expression.

  18. In our case, we indeed get \(U = T = {\bar{c}}d+c{\bar{d}}+{\bar{b}}{\bar{c}}{\bar{d}}\) and \(W = ST = 0\) (it is easy to see that the product ST vanishes, because each combination of a summand from S and a summand from T multiplies out to a term containing both a symbol and its negation, e.g. c and \({\bar{c}}\), and thus to zero), but on the face of it, we obtain a nonzero term for \(V = {\bar{S}}\). However, one can also see that \({\bar{S}}{\bar{T}} = 0\), which means that \(V{\bar{U}} = 0\): in terms of classes, V is included in U, so that in the solution \(a = U + uV\), where u is an indefinite class term, V is redundant and can be discarded—thereby correctly falling back on Boole’s solution (Schröder 1877, p. 27).

  19. For instance, as discussed in the previous section, one might ask for the expression of \(ab\) in terms of \(c\) and \(d\), that is, seek a relation of the form \(ab=\ldots \) instead of the simpler \(a=\ldots \) or \(b=\ldots \). Boole would then introduce an auxiliary term \(t\) with an additional premise \(t=ab\), then eliminate \(a\) and \(b\) as well as other unwanted terms and proceed as above, seeking a solution of the form \(t=\ldots \), where \(t\) can ultimately be replaced by \(ab\) again (Boole 1854, pp. 140–142).

  20. See note 6 above.

  21. See Boole (1854, p. 84): ‘Every primary proposition can thus be resolved into a series of denials of the existence of certain defined classes of things, and may, from that system of denials, be itself reconstructed.’

  22. See Jevons (1870). For an introduction and further references, see Gardner (1958, ch. 5).

  23. See Jevons (1874, in particular p. 135 and ch. VII); Venn (1881, pp. 255–260) discusses Jevons’ table, then compares it with his diagrams.

  24. Jevons (1874, p. 130); Jevons (1887, p. 113).

  25. Jevons (1887, p. 113); this sentence is missing from the 1874 edition.

  26. Venn (1881, p. 301).

  27. See Lotze (1884, pp. 219–221) = Lotze (1912, pp. 265–267). This solution is included in a ‘Note on the Logical Calculus’ that Lotze only added to the second, 1880 edition of his Logic.

  28. For a fuller discussion of Lotze’s outlook on this point as well as of parallels with Frege, see Heis (2013) as well as Gabriel (1989). Note that Frege, although he knew Lotze’s book, may not have been aware that the second edition contained an addendum treating the very problem he chose to discuss in his manuscript on Boole; see Gabriel, op. cit, p. XX and XXIII.

  29. Frege (1993b, p. 97).

  30. Frege (1979, p. 46).

  31. Frege (1979, p. 34, translation altered) = Frege (1969, p. 38). The ‘metaphor’ here refers to something like Euler diagrams, described by Frege earlier, that represent concepts by the area inside a circle or closed curve.

  32. Ibid. Frege makes a similar point, but framed as a criticism of Kant, in the Grundlagen, §88 (Frege 1884, pp. 99–101) = (Frege 1953, pp. 99–101).

  33. Frege (1979, p. 45) = Frege (1969, p. 51).

  34. This is assuming his solution is corrected as per footnote 42 below; his own version has only twelve premises.

  35. Frege (1979, p. 45) = Frege (1969, p. 51).

  36. For a quick introduction to Frege’s Begriffsschrift notation, see for instance von Plato (2017, ch. 4) or Schlimm (2018, pp. 54–65).

  37. Frege (1993a, pp. 11–12) = Frege (1972a, pp. 121–122); see also Schlimm (2018).

  38. Frege (1993a, p. 5) = Frege (1972a, pp. 114–115). Note that we are discussing the Begriffsschrift here; in the later system of the Grundgesetze, Frege is able to define his conditional directly in terms of truth and falsity (Frege 1893, §12).

  39. Frege (1979, p. 36) = Frege (1969, p. 40).

  40. Frege (1993a, pp. 10–11) = Frege (1972a, p. 121).

  41. Note that this is only true because of the specific form of the nested conditionals Frege uses here; if there were, say, negation signs anywhere else on the top line than just before the letter, this would cease to hold.

  42. This is assuming that Frege’s mistakes are corrected. For the record, here is how this should be done. The editors (see Frege 1979, note 1 p. 41) suggest adding a premise (10)\(^\prime \) and replacing Frege’s premise (12) by their (12)\(^\prime \) (shown below). Additionally, the following amendments are required. First, one should introduce equivalent variants of (10)\(^\prime \) and (12)\(^\prime \), namely (10)\(^{\prime \prime }\) and (12)\(^{\prime \prime }\):

    Second, in Frege’s solution of the first question, one should check that combining either of (10)\(^{\prime \prime }\) or (12)\(^{\prime \prime }\) with either of (8) or (9) only produces tautologies. Third, in the list at the top of p. 44, all occurences of ‘(17)’ should be replaced by ‘(19)’.

  43. In fact, Frege notices that a further simplification is possible: \(B\) can be eliminated by cut from (7) and (16), yielding

    so that (6) and (17) together contain the full solution to Boole’s first question.

  44. Frege (1979, p. 44) = Frege (1969, p. 49).

  45. Frege (1979, p. 39, translation altered) = Frege (1969, p. 44).

  46. Frege (1979, p. 46) = Frege (1969, p. 52).

  47. See §91; Frege (1884, p. 103) = Frege (1953, p. 103), translation from Beaney (1997, p. 124).

  48. In Aristotelian logic, ‘converting’ means inverting subject and predicate, e.g., going from ‘Some \(A\) is \(B\)’ to ‘Some \(B\) is \(A\)’ or from ‘All \(A\) are \(B\)’ to ‘Some \(B\) are \(A\)’.

  49. Boole (1854, pp. 10–11). (Emphasis in the original.)

  50. The idea to use these phrases to describe distinct traditions in logic goes back, as far as we know, to Philip Jourdain in his preface to Couturat (1914); it was sharpened and popularized by Van Heijenoort (1967), then taken up by various authors to shed light on other aspects of the history of logic (for further references, see for instance Kusch 1989, notes 5 and 6 p. 289). A further complication is that already in Frege’s time, the phrases (which ultimately come from Leibniz through the reconstruction by Trendelenburg 1856) were used in senses quite different from his, most notably by Schröder in his review of the Begriffsschrift. For discussion, see Sluga (1987) and Peckhaus (2004).

  51. The two papers on Boole (the long, only posthumously-published manuscript containing the solution discussed in Sect. 5, and a much briefer version that Frege managed to get published) are Frege (1979) = Frege (1969) and Frege (1972b) = Frege (1993b); the one on Peano is Frege (1984) = Frege (1897).

  52. Frege (1972b, p. 91, translation altered) = Frege (1993b, p. 98).

  53. Frege (1984, p. 238) = Frege (1897, p. 366). As noted by von Plato (2017, pp. 55–56), one should not overstate this criticism: appropriate rules can easily be supplied. See also Schlimm (2021).

  54. Frege (1984, p. 242, translation altered) = Frege (1897, pp. 370–371).

  55. Frege (1984, p. 237, translation altered) = Frege (1897, pp. 364–365).

  56. Frege (1972a, p. 104) = Frege (1993a, p. IV).

  57. Grattan-Guinness (1997, p. xliv), his emphasis.

  58. Grattan-Guinness (1992, p. 44).

  59. A good reference point here is John Stuart Mill, whom Boole quotes at the beginning of his first logical tract (see below). Mill argues that the language of algebra is prototypically mechanical: ‘The complete or extreme case of the mechanical use of language, is when it is used without any consciousness of a meaning [\(\ldots \)]. This extreme case is nowhere realized except in the figures of arithmetic, and still more, the symbols of algebra [\(\ldots \)]. Its perfection consists in the completeness of its adaptation to a purely mechanical use. The symbols are mere counters [\(\ldots \)]. There is nothing, therefore, to distract the mind from the set of mechanical operations which are to be performed upon the symbols [\(\ldots \)].’ (Mill 1974, pp. 707–708.) But he goes on to argue that such a mechanical language is in fact radically inappropriate outside of arithmetic: ‘On all other subjects, instead of contrivances to prevent our attention from being distracted by thinking of the meaning of our signs, we ought to wish for contrivances to make it impossible that we should ever lose sight of that meaning even for an instant.’ (Ibid, p. 710.)

  60. Mill (1974, p. 707), quoted in Boole (1847, p. 2).

  61. Boole (1847, p. 2).

  62. As Grattan-Guinness points out, Boole credits the mind with a capacity to grasp ‘general laws from particular cases’, for instance, which appears to be outside the scope of his system (Grattan-Guinness 1997, p. xliv).

  63. See Machale (2018, pp. 182–184).

  64. See Tappenden (2020, 2021).

  65. Frege (1884, p. iii) = Frege (1953, p. xv, translation altered).

  66. Frege (1884, p. iv) = Frege (1953, p. xvi, translation altered).

  67. Frege (1979, pp. 34–35) = Frege (1969, p. 39).

  68. For further discussion on this, see Rohr (2020, section 1.5).

  69. Letter to Hilbert, dated 1 October 1895 (Frege 1980, p. 33 = Frege 1976, pp. 58–59).

  70. Boole (1854, p. 11).

  71. See for instance Landy et al. (2014), which also surveys some of the relevant experimental literature.

  72. See for instance Vold and Schlimm (2020).

  73. See Schröder (1895).

  74. See Brady (2000), in particular ch. 8 and 9.

  75. See Schröder (1895), in particular the fifth lecture; for a synopsis, see Brady (2000, pp. 152–153).

  76. On Peirce’s view of analysis as the main task of logic, see for instance Pietarinen (2016).

  77. Incidentally, Peirce also developed technical criticisms of Schröeder’s approach of the topic, on which see Brady (2000, pp. 153–155).

  78. Peirce (1897, pp. 193–194).

  79. Peirce (1902, p. 24).

  80. Ibid.

References

  • Beaney, M. (Ed.). (1997). The Frege reader. Blackwell.

  • Bellucci, F., & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2016). Existential graphs as an instrument of logical analysis: Part I. Alpha. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 9(2), 209–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boole, G. (1847). The mathematical analysis of logic. Being an essay towards a calculus of deductive reasoning. Macmillan and George Bell.

  • Boole, G. (1854). An investigation of the laws of thought. Walton and Maberly.

  • Brady, G. (2000). From Peirce to Skolem. A neglected chapter in the history of logic. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics 4. Elsevier.

  • Couturat, L. (1914). The Algebra of Logic. Trans. by Lydia Gillingham Robinson. With a forew. by Philip E. B. Jourdain. Open Court.

  • Durand-Richard, M.-J. (2000) Logic versus algebra: English debates and Boole‘s mediation. In J. Gasser (Ed.), Boole anthology. Recent and classical studies in the logic of George Boole. Synthese Library 291 (pp. 139–166). Kluwer.

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2012). Formal languages in logic. A philosophical and cognitive analysis. Cambridge University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1884). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung\(\ddot{u}\)ber den Begriff der Zahl. Wilhelm Koebner.

  • Frege, G. (1893). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. Begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet. Vol. I. Hermann Pohle.

  • Frege, G. (1897). Über die Begriffsschrift des Herrn Peano und meine eigene. Berichte über die Verhandlungen der Königlich Sächsischen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig: Mathematisch-physische Klasse, 48, 361–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1953). The foundations of arithmetic. A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. Trans. by J. L. Austin. 2nd, rev. edition. Basil Blackwell & Mott.

  • Frege, G. (1969). Booles rechnende Logik und die Begriffsschrift. In H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, & F. Kaulbach (Eds.), Nachgelassene Schriften (pp. 9–52). Felix Meiner.

  • Frege, G. (1972a). Conceptual notation and related articles. Ed. and trans., with an introd., by Terrell Ward Bynum. Clarendon Press.

  • Frege, G. (1972b). On the aim of the ‘conceptual notation’. In Conceptual notation and related articles. Ed. and trans., with an introd., by Terrell Ward Bynum (pp. 90–100). Clarendon Press.

  • Frege, G. (1976). Wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel. Ed. by Gottfried Gabriel, Hans Hermes, Friedrich Kambartel, Christian Thiel, and Albert Veraart. Felix Meiner.

  • Frege, G. (1979). Boole’s logical calculus and the concept-script. In H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, & F. Kaulbach (Eds.), Posthumous writings (pp. 9–46). In collab. with Gottfried Gabriel and Walburga Rodding. Trans. by Peter Long and Roger White. Basil Blackwell.

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Ed. by Gottfried Gabriel, Hans Hermes, Friedrich Kambartel, Christian Thiel, and Albert Veraart. Abridged for the English ed. by Brian McGuinness and trans. by Hans Kaal. Basil Blackwell.

  • Frege, G. (1984). On Mr. Peano’s conceptual notation and my own. In Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy. Ed. by Brian McGuinness. Trans. by Max Black et al. (pp. 234–248). Basil Blackwell.

  • Frege, G. (1993a). Begriffsschrift und andere Aufsätze. Mit E. Husserls und H. Scholz’ Anmerkungen. Ed. by Ignacio Angelelli. 2nd edn. Georg Olms.

  • Frege, G. (1993b). \(\ddot{U}\)ber den Zweck der Begriffsschrift. In Begriffsschrift und andere Aufs\(\ddot{a}\)tze. Mit E. Husserls und H. Scholz’ Anmerkungen . Ed. by Ignacio Angelelli. 2nd ed. Georg Olms (pp. 97–106). Repr. from Sitzungsberichte der Jenaischen Gesellschaft f\(\ddot{u}\)r Medizin and Naturwissenschaft Jahr 1882 (pp. 1–10).

  • Gabriel, G. (1989). Einleitung des Herausgebers: Lotze und die Entstehung der modernen Logik bei Frege. In H. Lotze (Ed.), Logik. Ed. by Gottfried Gabriel. 3 vols. Felix Meiner (pp. XI–XXXV).

  • Gardner, M. (1958). Logic machines and diagrams. McGraw-Hill.

  • Grattan–Guinness, I. (1992). Charles Babbage as an algorithmic thinker. IEEE Annals of the History of Computing, 14 (3), 34–48.

  • Grattan–Guinness, I. (1997). Boole‘s quest for the foundations of his logic. In I. Grattan-Guinness & G. Bornet (Eds.), George Boole: Selected manuscripts on logic and its philosophy. Science Networks. Historical Studies 20 (pp. xiii–xlvii). Birkh\(\ddot{a}\)user.

  • Heis, J. (2013). Frege, Lotze, and Boole. In E. H. Reck (Ed.), The historical turn in analytic philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Jevons, W. S. (1864). Pure logic. Or the logic of quality apart from quantity: With remarks on Boole‘s system and on the relation of logic and mathematics. Edward Stanford.

  • Jevons, W. S. (1870). On the mechanical performance of logical inference. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 160, 497–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jevons, W. S. (1874). The principles of science. A treatise on logic and scientific method. Macmillan and Co.

  • Jevons, W. S. (1887). The principles of science. A treatise on logic and scientific method(2nd ed.). Macmillan and Co.

  • Kusch, M. (1989). Language as calculus vs. language as universal medium. A study in Husserl, Heidegger and Gadamer. Synthese Library 207. Kluwer.

  • Landy, D., Colin, A., & Zednik, C. (2014). A perceptual account of symbolic reasoning. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lotze, H. (1884) Logic in three books: Of thought, of investigation, and of knowledge. Ed. by Bernard Bosanquet. Clarendon Press.

  • Lotze, H. (1912). Logik. Drei Bücher vom Denken, vom Untersuchen und vom Erkennen. Ed., with an introd., by Georg Misch. Philosophie Bibliotek 141. Felix Meiner.

  • MacHale, D., & Cohen, Y. (2018). New Light on George Boole. Atrium - Cork University Press.

  • McColl, H. (1878). The Calculus of Equivalent Statements (III). Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 10, 16–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1974). Collected works. Vol. VII–VIII: A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive. Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation. Ed. by J. M. Robson. With an intro. by R. F. McRae. University of Toronto Press.

  • Peckhaus, V. (2004). Calculus ratiocinator versus characteristica universalis? The two traditions in logic, revisited. History and Philosophy of Logic, 25(1), 3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1897). The logic of relatives. The Monist, 7(2), 161–217. Reprinted in Peirce (1931–1958, §3.456–552).

  • Peirce, C. S. (1902). Symbolic logic or algebra of logic [passage on existential graphs]. In: Dictionary of philosophy and psychology. Vol. II. Ed. by James Mark Baldwin (pp. 645–650). Macmillan. Reprinted as Peirce (1931–1958, §4.372–392).

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). Collected Papers, 8 vol. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  • Raspe, R. E. (1765). Œuvres philosophiques latines & françoises de feu Mr. de Leibnitz. Jean Schreuder.

  • Rohr, T. (2020). Freges Begriff der Logik. Paderborn: mentis.

  • Schlimm, D. (2018). On Frege’s Begriffsschrift notation for propositional logic: Design principles and trade-offs. History and Philosophy of Logic, 39(1), 53–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlimm, D. (2021). Peano on symbolization, design principles for notations, and the dot notation. Philosophia Scientiæ, 25(1), 95–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schr\(\ddot{o}\)der, E. (1877). Der Operationskreis des Logikkalkuls. B. G. Teubner.

  • Schröder, E. (1895). Algebra und Logik der Relative. Der Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik dritter Band. B. G. Teubner.

  • Sluga, H. (1987). Frege against the Booleans. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 28(1), 80–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. (2020). Frege on computation and deduction: Herbart, Fischer and ’aggregative, mechanical thinking’. Online talk in the CSHPM Colloquium Series (2020).

  • Tappenden, J. (2021). Frege, Carl Snell and romanticism: Fruitful concepts and the ‘organic/mechanical’ distinction. Online talk organized by the SPHERE research team (Paris, France) (2021).

  • Trendelenburg, A. (1856). Leibnizens Entwurf einer allgemeinen Charakteristik. Abhandlungen der Königlischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, 1856(2), 37–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Heijenoort, J. (1967). Logic as calculus and logic as language. Synthese, 17(3), 324–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. (1881). Symbolic logic. Macmillan.

  • Vold, K., & Schlimm, D. (2020). Extended mathematical cognition: External representations with non-derived content. Synthese, 197(9), 3757–3777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Plato, J. (2017). The great formal machinery works. Theories of deduction and computation at the origins of the digital age. Princeton University Press.

  • Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering significance. Clarendon Press.

  • Wundt, W. (1880). Logik. Eine Untersuchung der Principien der Erkenntniss und der Methoden wissenschaftlicher Forschung, 2 vols. Ferdinand Enke.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Tabea Rohr, Nicolas Michel, David Makinson, and an anonymous reviewer, as well as to (virtual) audiences at the ‘Orange County and Inland Empire Seminar in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic’ and at the ‘Mathématiques XIXe-XXIe siècles, histoire et philosophie’ seminar of the SPHere research team (CNRS, Paris). This work was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Waszek.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Waszek, D., Schlimm, D. Calculus as method or calculus as rules? Boole and Frege on the aims of a logical calculus. Synthese 199, 11913–11943 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03318-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03318-x

Keywords

Navigation