Skip to main content
Log in

Revelation and the intuition of dualism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent literature on the metaphysics of consciousness, and in particular on the prospects of physicalism, there are two interesting strands of discussion. One strand concerns the so-called ‘thesis of revelation’, the claim that the essences of phenomenal properties are revealed in experience. The other strand concerns the intuition of dualism, the intuition that consciousness is nonphysical. With a particular focus on the former, this paper advances two main arguments. First, it argues that the thesis of revelation is intuitive; it is part of our ordinary, implicit conception of experience. Second, it brings the two strands of discussion together and puts forward a rational explanation of the intuition of dualism in terms of the intuitiveness of the thesis of revelation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A note on terminology: while I have used the term ‘intuition of dualism’ here, others have used different terminologies to refer to the same idea, e.g. ‘dualist intuitions’ in Chalmers (2018), ‘the intuition of distinctness’ in Papineau (2002, 2008, 2011, 2020).

  2. In comparison, the proposition ‘Being a sister is being a sibling’ does not define being a sister. It only describes part of the essence of being a sister.

  3. Throughout the paper, ‘physical’ is understood broadly to include functional properties.

  4. Note that ‘C-fibres firing’ is merely a placeholder for whatever physical properties, including functional properties, turn out to be the essence of the painfulness of pain, assuming physicalism is true.

  5. 121 responses were gathered from Amazon Mechanical Turk. Participants, who were fluent English speakers, were first presented with a vignette which explained the task and contained the following example:

    A triangle is, by definition, a closed shape with three sides. Consider the sentence ‘I know that a triangle is a closed shape with three sides, but I don’t know what a triangle really is.’ Although it makes no grammatical errors, this sentence sounds very strange, because if one knows that a triangle is a closed shape with three sides, then one knows what a triangle really is.

    After passing trial questions about the vignette, participants were then asked to judge a list of sentences, including (1) and (2), on a scale from 1 to 7, where ‘1’ is ‘This sentence is not strange’ and ‘7’ is ‘This sentence is very strange’. The average ratings for (1) and (2) were 2.98 (SD = 1.79) and 5.69 (SD = 1.64). 70.3% gave (2) a score of 5 or above with 40.5% responding ‘7’. In contrast, only 26.6% gave (1) a score of 5 or above and 57.9% gave it a score of 3 or below.

  6. Participants were also asked about (3) and (4) in the same experiment reported in fn5. The average ratings for (3) and (4) were 2.20 (SD = 1.54) and 5.11 (SD = 1.80). 66% gave (4) a score of 5 or above. In contrast, only 16.6% gave (3) a score of 5 or above and 74.4% gave it a score of 3 or below.

  7. In saying that there is a particular reading of sentence (2), I mean that it is possible to interpret or understand (2) in a particular way.

  8. Instead of ‘really’, other adverbial phrases, such as ‘essentially’, ‘actually’, ‘in fact’, can also be used. Adverbial phrases are not necessary for making claims about something’s essence. Sometimes we can just use the copula ‘is’, as in ‘heat is mean kinetic energy’.

  9. Note also that in the experiment reported in fn5, participants were presented with a vignette which contained an example that explicitly deployed the essential reading of ‘know what X really is’. Given this cueing, the essential reading was likely to be in force when participants judged the relevant sentences.

  10. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on examples of this sort.

  11. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection.

  12. Indeed, it does not seem particularly plausible to insist that the general idea of neuroscience is not familiar to us in everyday contexts whereas the idea of an atomistic reality is.

  13. Given both (1) and (2) contrast what X is like, where X is ‘gold’ in (1) and ‘the feeling of an itch’ in (2), with what X really is, and given non-essential readings of the sentences seem cognitively demanding, requiring the interpreter to come up with hypothetical scenarios, it is plausible that the essential reading is the default interpretation of these sentences. Note again that given the vignette reported in fn5, participants likely deployed the essential reading of ‘know what X really is’ when interpreting the relevant sentences.

  14. Note that the explanation for the intuition of dualism put forward here only depends on an implicit appreciation of an alleged incompatibility between revelation and physicalism. Such an implicit appreciation can exist even if revelation turns out to be compatible with physicalism. In other words, the explanation at issue does not depend on whether the argument put forward in Sect. 2 is strictly speaking correct, only that the subject implicitly takes it to be correct. Furthermore, it seems plausible that there is such an implicit appreciation. After all, many philosophers, including physicalists, explicitly endorse the incompatibility between revelation and physicalism (e.g. Braddon-Mitchell 2007; Chalmers 2016, 2018; Goff 2015, 2017; Hill 2014; Lewis 1995; McLaughlin 2001, 2003; Papineau 2020). So, it would seem that the argument from revelation against the claim that phenomenal properties are physical properties, whether or not it is ultimately correct, is certainly compelling enough to be tacitly appreciated by a rational person.

References

  • Balog, K. (2012). Acquaintance and the mind-body problem. In S. Gozzano & C. S. Hill (Eds.), New perspectives on type identity: the mental and the physical (pp. 16–42). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2007). Against ontologically emergent consciousness. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 287–299). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogardus, T. (2013). Undefeated Dualism. Philosophical Studies, 165, 445–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2016). The combination problem for panpsychism. In G. Brüntrup & J. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 179–214). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2018). The meta-problem of consciousness. Journal of Conscious Studies, 25(9–10), 6–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damnjanovic, N. (2012). Revelation and physicalism. Dialectica, 66(1), 69–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2015). Knowledge (explicit, implicit and tacit): philosophical aspects. In J. D. Wright (Ed.), International encyclopedia of social and behavioral sciences. Elsevier Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiala, B., Arico, A., & Nichols, S. (2011). On the psychological origins of dualism: Dual-process cognition and the explanatory gap. In E. Slingerland & M. Collard (Eds.), Creating consilience: Issues and case studies in the integration of the sciences and humanities (pp. 88–106). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. (2014). The possibility of inquiry: Meno’s paradox from socrates to sextus. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). Senses of Essence. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman, & N. Asher (Eds.), Modality, morality and belief: Essays in honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (pp. 53–73). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2011). A posteriori physicalists get our phenomenal concepts wrong. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(2), 191–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2015). Real acquaintance and physicalism. In P. Coates & S. Coleman (Eds.), Phenomenal qualities: Sense, perception, and consciousness (pp. 121–143). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. (2014). Meaning, mind, and knowledge. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2001). Deconstructing new wave materialism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 307–318). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, M. B. (2018). Intuitions as inferential judgments. Philosophical Issues, 28(1), 7–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1995). Should a materialist believe in qualia? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73(1), 140–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, M. (2019). Phenomenal experience and the thesis of revelation. In D. Shottenkirk, M. Curado, & S. Gouveia (Eds.), Perception (pp. 227–251). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, M. (2020). Explaining the intuition of revelation. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(5–6), 99–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majeed, R. (2017). Ramsey humility: The response from revelation and panpsychism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 47(1), 75–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (2001). In defense of new wave materialism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 319–330). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (2003). Color, consciousness, and color consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 97–154). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D. L., & Ortony, A. (1989). Psychological essentialism. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 179–195). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nida-Rümelin, M. (2007). Grasping phenomenal properties. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism (pp. 307–336). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007). Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism (pp. 111–144). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2008). Explanatory gaps and dualistic intuitions. In L. Weiskrantz & M. Davies (Eds.), Frontiers of consciousness (pp. 55–62). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2011). What exactly is the explanatory gap? Philosophia, 39, 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2020). The problem of consciousness. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of consciousness (pp. 14–38).

  • Peacocke, C. (2008). Truly understood. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility, and consciousness. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2000). Intuitions as evidence. Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pust, J. (2017). ‘Intuition’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/intuition/.

  • Robinson, H. (2015). Phenomenal qualities: What they must be, and what they cannot be. In P. Coates & S. Coleman (Eds.), Phenomenal qualities: Sense, perception, and consciousness (pp. 103–120). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2006). Ignorance and imagination: The epistemic origin of the problem of consciousness. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2009). The argument from revelation. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 113–138). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2018). 'Review of Philip Goff, “Consciousness and Fundamental Reality”’, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, [Online] https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/consciousness-and-fundamental-reality/.

  • Sundström, P. (2008). Is the mystery an illusion? Papineau on the problem of consciousness. Synthese, 163, 133–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundström, P. (2017). How physicalists can—And cannot—Explain the seeming “absurdity” of physicalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151(2), 299–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trogdon, K. (2017). Revelation and physicalism. Synthese, 194, 2345–2366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. (2007). How to change intuitions empirically without risking scepticism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 318–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (2010). Experience, evidence, and sense: The hidden cultural legacy of English. OUP.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of the paper were presented at the philosophy of mind work in progress group at the Australian National University, Dualism in the Twenty-First Century Conference at the Central European University, the Phenomenal Consciousness and Self-Awareness Workshop at the University of Fribourg, and the Phenomenality and Self-Consciousness Workshop and the Mind Readings group at the University of Hertfordshire. I’d like to thank the audiences on these occasions. Thanks also to Sam Coleman, Martin Davies, Jakub Mihalik, and Daniel Stoljar for their valuable written comments on earlier versions of this paper. Finally, I am grateful to helpful and detailed comments from four anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michelle Liu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Liu, M. Revelation and the intuition of dualism. Synthese 199, 11491–11515 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03299-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03299-x

Keywords

Navigation