Skip to main content
Log in

Propositional and credal accuracy in an indeterministic world

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is truism that accuracy is valued. Some deem accuracy to be among the most fundamental values, perhaps the preeminent value, of inquiry. Because of this, accuracy has been the focus of two different, important programs in epistemology. The truthlikeness program (instigated by Popper) pursued the notion of propositional accuracy—an ordering of propositions by closeness to the objective truth of some matter. The epistemic utility program (instigated by Hempel) pursued the notion of credal state accuracy—an ordering of credal states by closeness to the ideal credal state. It may be tempting to think that each question that informs an inquiry must be  determinate of necessity. That is to say, there must be one correct, precise answer to it. That precise, correct answer is not only the maximally accurate answer to the question, but it also singles out the ideal credal state that is the epistemic target of the inquiry. An enormous amount of the effort has been focused on accuracy with respect to necessarily determinate questions. But often the focus of an inquiry is a question that is not necessarily determinate. Those who deem accuracy to be cognitively valuable, and fundamentally so, need an account of accuracy for indeterminate questions. Ideally such an account would cover both propositional accuracy and credal state accuracy. This is a tall order, and it is not clear that the order can be filled.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Belnap and Steel (1976), Kuipers and Wiśniewski (1994) and Groenendijk and Stokhof (1997).

  2. Tichý (1978).

  3. For the intension account see Tichý (1978). It is more fine-grained than the partition account but it is still too coarse-grained, ignoring as it does the hyperintensional dimension. The question Is the sum of seven and five twelve is clearly different from the question is Fermat's last theorem true despite inducing the same (trivial) intension.

  4. The abbreviation [X = x] is fairly standard though a bit misleading. X is known as a "random variable" in probability theory (although it is not a variable and need not be random). Let \({X}_{w}\) be the result of applying the function \(X\) to arbitrary state. w [X = x] is really short for the λ-abstraction of \({[X}_{w}=x]\) w.r.t. variable \(w\): i.e. \(\lambda w[X_{w} = x\)].

  5. More needs to be said about partial questions: the case where \(X\) is a partial function.

  6. This usage is not universal and I take it is as stipulative here. Causal indeterminism is a source of indeterminacy of questions, and the main source to consider. Vagueness is another source of indeterminacy of questions, but one I won't explore. See Wilson (2016) for a defense of metaphysical indeterminacy, and Calosi and Wilson (2019) for a discussion of quantum indeterminacy.

  7. I assume we have settled on a precisifications of the concepts involved. For \(\mathbf{E}\), choose a concept of living such that at each moment it is determinate whether or not a person is alive or not at that moment.

  8. It is narrower because on the intensional account the answers to questions can be of any logical type, not just propositions.

  9. Beginning with Kuipers (1987).

  10. This defect was first detailed in Tichý (1974) and Miller (1974). Another defect is that it deems no false proposition to be closer to the truth than any true propositions. So a tautology is closer to the truth than even the most accurate false proposition.

  11. Kuipers (1992).

  12. See Oddie (2013) for some intuitively plausible constraints of this sort.

  13. When one is trying to determine the cost of a move one generally takes the lowest quote!

  14. EMD has been applied to a wide range of phenomena, perhaps most interesting in this context being the measurement of similarity of images. See Wang and Guibas (2012).

  15. We can extend the account to continuous magnitudes but there will be the usual problems with denumerably infinite sets, over which one cannot have even credal distributions without violating countable additivity.

  16. These could be worlds, or kinds, or more generally precise answers to a question. In the likeness program we start with kinds, or attributive constituents—the simplest examples of which are Carnap's Q-predicates. Suppose we have distances between such kinds. Constituents are collections of attributive constituents. Given the distributive normal form theorem, every first-order sentence is equivalent to a disjunction (collection) of constituents. Hence each expressible proposition can be identified with the class of consistent constituents in its normal form. From here distances between expressible propositions can be derived from distances between constituents. See Niiniluoto (1987).

  17. Oddie (1986, chapter 4). In the terminology of that work, I am going straight to absolutely fair linkages here. Niiniluoto also demonstrated that an intermediate fairness proposal also skewed the distances.

  18. Hájek (unpublished ms) argues that credence stands to chance as belief stands to truth. This is also the verdict of the Principal Principle. See also Pettigrew (2012, 2016).

  19. See Pettigrew (2016).

  20. There is a more general result for credal states corresponding to imprecise incorrect answers: that a decrease in strength is invariably an increase in accuracy. This is the value of the lack of content for falsehoods. This avoids an objection to Popper's theory (the incomparability of falsehoods) but it lacks the sting of a corresponding objection to the symmetric difference measure (the value content for falsehoods).

  21. For various ways of tinkering with the Brier score by weighting certain kinds of propositions see Oddie (2019) and Schoenfield (2020). Dunn (2019) suggests weighting atomic propositions (something already suggested and criticized in Oddie 2019). Schoenfield (2020) contains an extended and nuanced discussion of weighting convex propositions. As noted in Oddie (1987, 2019) there is in fact a close connection between convexity and atomicity so the two remedies are connected. For the relation of convexity to the notion of a natural proposition or genuine property see Gärdenfors (2000), Oddie (1987) and Oddie (2005, chapter 6).

  22. Proximity does not generalize in any obvious way to the indeterminate case. Suppose that the indeterminate truth A is \(\{1,6\}\) and \(B\) is \(\{2,5\}\). The distance of B from A is less than that of either {2} or {5} since it is less costly to shift from B to A than to shift from either {2} or {5} to A. A more plausible candidate for Proximity might be this. Let \({Closest}_{A}(C)\) be class of subsets of B that have the same cardinality as A. Then any \(C\in\) \(\textit{Closest}_{A}(B)\) is no more inaccurate than is \(B\) itself.

  23. There are some interesting exceptions to this but it is a good rule of thumb and the exceptions need not detain us.

  24. I myself endorsed this in Oddie (1997).

  25. Schoenfield (2020).

  26. See Oddie (2013) for an extended discussion of this.

  27. I owe special thanks to the editors and two anonymous referees who made extensive and detailed suggestions which greatly improved the paper.

References

  • Belnap, N. D., & Steel, T. B. (Eds.). (1976). The logic of questions and answers. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calosi, C., & Wilson, J. (2019). Quantum Metaphysical Indeterminacy. Philosophical Studies, 176(10), 2599–2627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. (2019). Accuracy, verisimilitude, and scoring rules. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(1), 151–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces: the geometry of thought. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1997). Questions. In J. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 1055–1124). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. l. (unpublished). A puzzle about degree of belief. Unpublished manuscript, Australian National University. http://fitelson.org/coherence/hajek_puzzle.pdf.

  • Kuipers, T. (1987). A structuralist approach to truthlikeness. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 79–99). Rodopi.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. (1992). Naive and refined truth approximation. Synthese, 93, 299–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F., & Wiśniewski, A. (1994). An erotetic approach to explanation by specification. Erkenntnis, 40(3), 377–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 166–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1977). On distance from the truth as a true distance. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 6(1), 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (1986). Likeness to Truth, Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science. Reidel.

  • Oddie, G. (1987). Truthlikeness and the convexity of propositions. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 197–217). Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (1997). Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 533–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2005). Value, reality and desire. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2013). The content, consequence and likeness approaches to verisimilitude: compatibility, trivialization, and underdetermination. Synthese, 190(9), 1647–1687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2019). What accuracy could not be. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(2), 551–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2012). Accuracy, chance and the principal principle. Philosophical Review, 121(2), 241–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the laws of credence. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schoenfield, M. (2020). Accuracy and verisimilitude: The good, the bad, and the ugly. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (forthcoming, published online https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz032).

  • Tichý, P. (1974). On Popper’s definitions of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1976). Verisimilitude redefined. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 27(1), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1978). Questions, answers, and logic. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(4), 275–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, F., & Guibas, L. J., et al. (2012). Supervised earth mover’s distance learning and its computer vision applications. In S. Lazebnik (Ed.), Computer Vision ECCV 2012 (pp. 442–455). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. M. (2016). Are there indeterminate states of affairs? Yes. In E. Barnes (Ed.), Current controversies in metaphysics.Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham Oddie.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the topical collection “Approaching Probabilistic Truths”, edited by Theo Kuipers, Ilkka Niiniluoto, and Gustavo Cevolani.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Oddie, G. Propositional and credal accuracy in an indeterministic world. Synthese 199, 9391–9410 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03207-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03207-3

Keywords

Navigation