A conjunctive conception of paraconsistency consists of claiming that there can be non-explosive contradictions but contradictories cannot be separately true.Footnote 1 So the ‘and’ that joins ‘p and not p’ in case of true contradiction is not simplifiable: ‘p’ and ‘not p’, separately taken, are untrue. The aim of the article is to present a version of this view, which is not so much studied in the current literature. It is suggested that if one wants to acknowledge the existence of true contradictions (or to admit the possibility of contradictions) there could be reasons to adopt such a perspective. More specifically, the article shows that conjunctivism in paraconsistency relies on a conception of truth that preserves the exclusion constraint classically involved in the use of the concept (whereby if ‘p’ is true ‘not p’ cannot be true), while acknowledging the possibility of true state descriptions of the form ‘p and not p’. That such a conception is to be held preferable to other options will not be dealt with here. The aim is to show that the conjunctive view is plausible, and its consequences are interesting for anyone who is concerned with the notion of ‘true contradiction’.

In the first section, three ways of interpreting the conjunction problem (the joined subsistence of incompatibles in case of true contradictions) are presented: dialetheism, non-adjunctivism and conjunctivism. Three examples of a conjunctive treatment of paradoxes are suggested in the second section; in the third section some objections and open problems are explored, and the last section explains the underlying conception of truth. The development of a consequent semantics will be the concern of another paper, though some anticipations are given in the last section (Sect. 4.3).

1 Three ‘and’

A contradiction is a contradictory object. It is the joined subsistence of what in principle cannot jointly subsist. If we accept that there are true contradictions, we are committed to explain—among other things—what we mean by ‘joined subsistence’. As ‘and’ normally stands for joined subsistence (joined truth), one may think there is something special in the postulated ‘and’. In the literature about inconsistency the conjunction problem is treated by three basic positions: dialetheism, non-adjunctivism and conjunctivism. They all accept that there can be true contradictions but differ in the interpretation of the ‘and’ joining ‘p’ and ‘not p’. For dialetheists (see for the most well-known versions Priest 19872, 2006, Priest et al., 2004; Beall, 2009), it is a perfectly normal ‘and’, classically defined by the Conjunction Thesis:

CT:p and q is true iffp is true andqis true.Footnote 2

The acceptance of this classical bi-conditional implies that the two basic rules of Simplification (from left to right), and Adjunction (from right to left) both hold, so if ‘p and not p’ is true, the two contradictories are both separately and jointly true. For non-adjunctivists, there are cases in which ‘p’ and ‘not p’ are acceptable, but in those cases the conjunction ‘p and not p’ is untrue, Adjunction fails. Non-Adjunctivism dates back to Jaśkowski (1948, 1999), and has been developed by many authors, in different ways. The third position is symmetrically opposed to non-adjunctivism, and it is the idea that there can be non-explosive true contradictions of conjunctive form, so some ‘p and not p’ can be true, but in this case, ‘p’ and ‘not p’ cannot be said separately true: the left to right direction of CT does not hold; Simplification fails.

While dialetheism and non-adjunctivism are well-known approaches to paraconsistency, there is no clear and definite position of the third kind in recent literatureFootnote 3 but there are reasons to believe it was not unknown in the tradition.Footnote 4

1.1 Asymmetries

In the account here proposed, the three positions share the basic dialetheic postulate, that:

D: there are some true contradictions

But they differ in saying what is meant by D. Conjunctivists and dialetheists believe a true contradiction has a conjunctive form, so D implies:

D1: there are some true propositions of the form ‘p and not p’

This is namely what non-adjunctivists do not accept: they hold there is no true conjunction of contradictories. Dialetheists also believe that:

D2: there are some true propositions whose negation is true

A dialetheia is held to be a proposition of this kind, and on the understanding that ‘falsity’ is the truth of negation, a true contradiction is a true and false proposition. D2 is accepted by non-adjunctivists, while conjunctivists reject it. So Non-Adjunctivism (Non-Adj) and Conjunctivism (Conj) can be seen as forms of anomalous or asymmetrical Dialetheism. The latter rejecting D2 and accepting D1, the former accepting D2 and rejecting D1.

On normal conditions, D1 and D2 are equivalent. But contradictions cannot be said to be ‘normal’ facts. The basic aim of Conj and Non-Adj, as dialetheically asymmetrical and reciprocally dual positions, is the will to save something of the traditional enmity between truth (the use of the concept of truth) and contradiction. In both cases, this is attempted by focusing on the conjunction (the ‘joined subsistence’) problem.

1.2 Non-adjunctivism

The basic idea of non-adjunctive strategies is that the simultaneous being (believed or considered) true of some ‘p’ and ‘not p’ is possible, if the two propositions belong to different logical or epistemic systems, situations, or worlds, so that contradictions may occur distributively but not conjunctively (see Berto, 2007: pp. 131–150). The paradigmatic situation of Jaśkowski’s discussive logic is the case of ‘theses advanced by several participants in a discourse’ that are ‘combined into a single system’ (Jaśkowski, 1948: p. 149). In Rescher and Brandom’s semantics, ‘p’ and ‘not p’ might both be true, but in distinct possible worlds, and there is no world in which ‘p and not p’ is true (Rescher & Brandom, 1980). Non-Adj can be justified by appealing to doxastic states, as in Lewis (1982): an ideal epistemic agent S believes that p and believes that not p, but does not believe ‘p and not p’, and this happens because our systems of beliefs are ‘broken into fragments’, and ‘different fragments came into action in different situations’ (p. 103). A good example of non-Adjunctive treatment of contradictions is given by Varzi (2004: p. 95), building on Belnap (1977). Consider a computer programmed to answer ‘yes’ or ‘no’ to queries, and used by two different agents, of which one enters ‘p’ and the other enters ‘not p’. The computer separately answers ‘yes’ to ‘p?’ and ‘yes’ to ‘not p?’ but ‘no’ to ‘p and not p?’. It accepts each conjunct, but not their conjunction, Adjunction fails.

A first objection commonly addressed to non-adjunctivists is that their postulated ‘and’ does not seem to be an ‘and’, actually, so they ‘change the subject’: they refer to another operator, different from ‘and’, and maybe different from our common intuitions about ‘and’. In fact, conjunction is a weird operator, it often betrays our ‘common intuitions’ as captured by CT.Footnote 5 In particular, the failure of the Adjunction rule can be justified in a variety of ways, say, by noting that a rational agent may accept each ‘p’ and ‘q’, separately, while rejecting ‘p and q’. Suppose |p|= 0.8 and |q|= 0.9, and S’s epistemic standard is Tp ↔|p|≥ 0.8; now S is perfectly entitled to accept ‘p’ and ‘q’, but not ‘p and q’, whose value (if ‘p’ and ‘q’ are independent) will be 0.72.Footnote 6 To see how this solution may work in the case of presumably true contradiction, consider an example frequently mentioned by Priest (19872: 100; Priest, 2006: pp. 105, 133): S believes that p and believes that q, but she comes to know that they cannot be jointly true. As a rational agent, S acknowledges that her beliefs are not so sure in this case, thus, she feels entitled to accept ‘p’ and ‘q’, while accepting that at least one of them might be untrue, thus rejecting ‘p and q’. Priest (2006: p. 105) believes this is a rational contradiction, but it is a controversial question. Sorensen (2003a) speaks of ‘paradoxes of rationality’, while Smith (2016) holds in these cases there is a certain amount of irrationality.

A second objection is that the challenge of the ‘joined subsistence’ is not faced but dodged by non-adjunctivists. This may be intended first as meaning that non-adjunctive contradictions are not ‘contradictions’, eventually, as they do not satisfy Aristotle’s Fundamental Condition: that for a contradiction to occur, the two terms must obtain ‘at the same time and under the same respect’. As Rescher and Brandom state (1980: p. 58): ‘The present approach […] dispenses entirely with any need to modify the principles of classical logic’. So that Priest and Routley comment ‘This strategy has only the appearance of paraconsistency. In essence it is just a revisionist classical logic’ (Priest & Routley, 1989: p. 161).

Another way of interpreting the objection is that non-Adjunctive contradictions are ‘contradictions’ in a loose sense (pairs of propositions such that one is the negation of the other), but they cannot be said ‘true’. The truth postulated by the non-adjunctive interpretation of D is transitory, or fictional, fragmented or merely possible truth. In this sense, one may contend that non-adjunctivists ‘do not take the dialetheic motivation (that there are true contradictions) seriously’ (Priest & Routley, 1989: p. 162). As Jaśkowski suggests: ‘it would not be correct to formulate Aristotle’s principle of contradiction as “two contradictory sentences are not both true”. We have namely to add: “in the same language”, or “if the words occurring in those sentences have the same meaning”’ (Jaśkowski, 1948: p. 144). In Jaśkowski’s discussive logic, ‘p’ and ‘not p’ are only ‘possibly true’, or ‘true in accordance with the opinion of one of the participants’ (p. 149), so one would say the two propositions are contrary and not contradictories (which explains the affinity of Non-Adj with truth-value-gap or T-free logics). In the same line, one may note that Varzi’s computer is ‘neutral’, it is not committed to alethic evaluations. So for the computer, ‘p’ and ‘not p’ are neither true nor false. Not unlike, in Lewis’ picture, S is not aware of the inconsistency. Presumably, if she were aware, she would try to reduce the cognitive dissonance in some way, and if she could not, she would acknowledge, honestly, that she does not have a clear idea about the issue (so again, the apparent glut is in fact a gap, an epistemic lacuna).

In conclusion, one would say that in non-adjunctive cases there is, or there appears to be, a contradiction, but whether the contradiction is (can be said) true seems to be another question (see Sect. 4).

1.3 Dialetheism

The distinctive aspect of the dialetheic perspective is the focus on truth. In this sense, dialetheism can also be seen as the claim that the use of the concept of truth does not exclude (rather implies) the occurrence of true contradictions, and this is most frequently intended, by dialetheists, in terms of both D1 and D2.Footnote 7

The Liar paradox is the best-known case advanced by dialetheists to support D2, and D1 via D2. Given the Liar’s sentence ‘μ’, which says: ‘μ’ is not true, you will have that if ‘μ’ is true then it must be untrue, and if it is untrue then it is true, so the sentence appears to be true and untrue at the same time. There are different ways of presenting the argumentFootnote 8; the standard way relies on the naïve truth theory, better known as the T-schema (Tarski, 1944):

T〈μ〉 ↔ μ (Df.T),

which implies release:

T〈μ〉 → μ (Rel.)

And capture:

μ → T〈μ〉 (Capt.)

The Liar says that what she is saying is untrue, and thus we have the Inclosure Schema (Priest, 1995: pp. 147–149):

T〈μ〉 ↔ ¬T〈μ〉

which by Rel. means

μ ↔ ¬μ.

The bi-conditional contradiction becomes conjunctive (i.e. μ ∧ ¬ μ) in virtue of the Excluded Middle: from μ you draw ¬μ, then μ ∧ ¬μ; from ¬μ you draw μ, and hence μ ∧ ¬μ; so given μ ∨ ¬μ, unquestionably: μ ∧ ¬μ.

As mentioned, that there is a contradiction (in a generic unrestricted sense of ‘there being’) does not mean that the contradiction is true. Dialetheists embrace the latter position: the contradiction is true, and we should accept it; if ‘solving’ a paradox means to eliminate the contradiction, then there is no solution (as Priest colourfully says, trying to ‘solve’ the Liar is ‘barking up the wrong tree’). This is justified at first by considering that alternative strategies fail (the Liar revenges in a variety of ways) or imply abstract restrictions of the expressiveness of language. Besides that, if we want to have a theory of truth, we must admit that some sort of self-reference, reflexivity, or closure, is inevitable (Beall, 2009); and if we have closure, we inevitably have contradictions (or triviality, as in the case of Curry-Löb paradox). Finally, as it is well synthetized by Priest (2004: pp. 29–32), the main reason why we are so worried about contradictions is that contradictions are held to be worrying phenomena, which is deontic (vicious) circularity: we think we cannot because we think we cannot. But the developments of non-classical logic have shown that in believing this we are wrong, as we have systems, such as LP and FDE, in which the acceptance of D1 and especially D2 is perfectly plausible.

In keeping to the T-schema, and the normal meaning of conjunction and negation, dialetheists assume that each of the two ‘sides’ of a dialetheia is true, and their conjunction is true too, so they are (in principle) anti-non-adjunctivist and anti-conjunctivist.Footnote 9 The ‘and’ that joins contradictories behaves as it is intended to behave in any other occurrence. The interesting consequence is a third thesis:

D3: a true contradiction is true and false

So if ‘p and not p’ is true, this means that ‘not(p and not p)’ is true too. D3 is a natural consequence of D2, as long as one keeps to the T-schema and the standard meaning of the operators. If we have p ∧ ¬p, by Simpl. we have p (hence ¬¬p) and ¬p (so ¬¬¬p), which means ¬(p ∧ ¬p). The ‘truth’ that we ascribe to contradictions is thus double double truth. As Priest clearly explains (2002b: p. 654), if A is both true and false at a world, ‘given that the conjunction behaves normally, it follows that A ∧ ¬A is false; and so ¬(A ∧ ¬A) is true at the world as well’ (the emphasis is mine). The noteworthy consequence is that the Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC) is not rejected by dialetheists, rather accepted unrestrictedly, because ‘¬(p ∧ ¬p)’ must hold for any ‘p’.

As it has been frequently noted (see Sainsbury, 1995: pp. 150–159; Shapiro, 2004; Field, 2005, 2008; Berto, 2007, 2008; Beall, 2006a), in accepting D3 dialetheists are faced with some ‘expressive’ problems. One—possibly the most important—is that D3 would affect the (self-)definition of dialetheism: ‘a problem with defining dialetheism as the doctrine that certain sentences are both true and false is that while a dialetheist should certainly assert […] True(〈A〉 False〈A〉) for certain A (e.g. the Liar sentence), he should deny this as well’ (Field, 2005: pp. 24–27). Indeed, in general, the question of what, ultimately, dialetheists rule out remains a crucial topic of discussion. In fact, it could be seen as the crucial topic of discussion for any acceptance of D (Sect. 1.5).

1.4 Conjunctivism

In the version here proposed, Conj is ‘a kind of dialetheism’ as it consists of sharing two important dialetheic claims: that there may be true contradictions of conjunctive form (D1), and that the meaning and use of the concept of truth do not prevent (rather imply) the acceptance of true contradictions. To make things clearer, it can be useful to distinguish dialetheism (some contradiction is true) from di-aletheism (some proposition is true and its negation is true too), and dialetheias (true contradictions) from di-aletheias (true and false propositions). In this sense, one would say that conjunctivists favour a dialetheic but not di-aletheic theory of truth (see Sect. 4). Altogether, Conj presents ‘a way of being glut-theorist’ that does not strictly rival the most common dialetheic way (as defined by D) but offers a different solution to the ‘joined subsistence’ problem.

You may have inconsistent information in a variety of occurrences, and one of them is the case well expressed by non-adjunctivists: two different sources, separately, justify ‘p’ and ‘not p’; you are not in the position to select (exclude) one, so you accept both, but separately. Conjunctivists can easily concede that this treatment of prima facie contradictions may make sense, but they would contend that these cases do not fall under D: ‘p’ and ‘not p’ non-adjunctively considered cannot be said to form a true contradiction, basically (as seen in Sect. 1.2) because the Aristotelian condition is not satisfied (so the case is not a contradiction), and because the ‘truth’ involved is only transitory or probable or possible truth (the state description is not properly true). In the conjunctive hypothesis D is to be intended in terms of D1: there can be positive cases of contradiction, so that ‘p and not p’ is true in classical categorical sense (definitely true in any respect: Sect. 4); but they reject D2, so they assume that the two conjuncts of a true contradictory statement or proposition cannot be said true.Footnote 10

In the way in which they are presented here, Non-Adj and Conj are symmetrically opposed acceptances of the Law of Non-Contradiction (LNC) in its two alethic versions, viz. the two ‘Laws of Non-Dialetheia’:

LND1: There cannot be any true ‘p and not p’

And

LND2: There cannot be any true ‘p’ whose negation is true

Non-Adjunctivists accept LND1 and reject LND2, conjunctivists accept the latter and not the former. Thus, the basic conjunctive thesis is that:

C: there can be true contradictions, but there cannot be any true and false proposition.

While for non-adjunctivists the two contradictories are not strictly ‘joined’ in the metaphysical sense (there is no contradictory truthmaker as such: Sect. 4.1), conjunctivists can accept the Fundamental Condition in the strongest Aristotelian meaning, whereby speaking of ‘true contradiction’ means to imply that there is some state (of affairs) of a conjunctive nature that works as truthmaker for ‘p and not p’. So they can endorse a strong form of paraconsistency.

In a possible formulation, the theory consists of three theses:

C1: there are some states (of affairs) whose state description in terms ofp and not pis true

C2: the two conjuncts of a true contradiction are untrue

Consequently:

C3: the conjunction that joins two contradictory sentences in a true contradiction is not simplifiable: thatp and not p is true does not entail thatp is true andnot pis true.

C1 is a version of D1 that expresses a ‘realistic’ commitment to paraconsistency (there might be some contradictory states, but not any state of affairs is a contradiction). Notably, it does not imply, as such, any specific ontological restriction. Contradictory truthmakers could be physical facts, ideally captured by our sensory experience, but also non-physical, semantic, intentional facts.Footnote 11 C2 presents what seems the most implausible thesis of Conj, that two untrue sentences may make a conjunction true. As will be specified later, this is justified at first by the idea that the two contradictory propositions are partial state descriptions, so they are untrue as unassertable (‘untrue’ here means neither true nor false, which is intended to express a gap for over-determination: see Sect. 4.3). As to C3, it is a logical consequence of C2 and it is supported, metaphysically, by assuming that the contradictory state postulated by C1 consists of two inseparable parts of only one state, acting as a truthmaker for ‘p and not p’ (Sect. 3.2).

1.5 Explosion avoided; exclusion preserved

Many things should be specified. For now, let us consider only two noteworthy features of the conjunctive strategy.

A first consequence of accepting D1 without D2 (so admitting C3) is that it provides unusual but very simple a way of disproving the pseudo-Scotus argument (also known as ex contradictione quodlibet, or Lewis’ rule, or explosion principle), which is the typical concern of paraconsistent logicians. The argument shows that accepting just one contradiction everything is proved true, so everything is contradictory. It classically needs three rules: Simplification, ∨Introduction, and Disjunctive Syllogism (or Material Detachment). To block the argument, one should remove at least one of the three rules, and the most shared proposal is to remove DS (which is otherwise a problematic rule). In the conjunctive strategy, the argument immediately fails, as Simplification for contradictions does not hold (C3).Footnote 12

In fact, the most successful attempt to disprove ECQ is by appeal to relevance logic, which provides semantic as well as epistemic reasons. The argument is clearly an irrelevant inference; it can be considered one of the typical paradoxes of classical entailment. As dialetheists repeat, it is irrational to assume that as soon as you acknowledge that, say, the Liar paradox is a true contradiction, you immediately imply that the Earth is not round, or God exists, or whatever (Priest, 2008: pp. 74–77). In fact, relevance logic rejects unrestricted DS, but it also admits both non-adjunctive and conjunctive versions of ‘and’ (Read, 2012: pp. 36–50; Mares, 2004). In particular, ‘fusion’ is an intensional non-simplifiable conjunction. In the situation-sensitive semantics of Mares (2012) fusion works as a ‘premise binder’, so that some ‘p and q’ at some inferential step does not entail ‘p’ (or ‘q’) separately.Footnote 13 One may assume that the ‘and’ joining contradictories in the conjunctive hypothesis is of this kind, which seems to be profitable for a conjunctive interpretation of the Liar (Sect. 4.2).

A second interesting feature of Conj is that it allows us to accept D1 (that a contradiction of conjunctive form is true) without renouncing the exclusion constraint classically involved in the use of the concept of truth, whereby necessarily, if a proposition is (held) true, then its negation must be (held) untrue. Alethic Exclusion (AE) is actually the conditional version of LND2:

AE: ifp is true thennot pcannot be true

In accepting LND2 (and rejecting D2) Conj automatically preserves AE. It is important to remember that we are speaking of ‘AE’ (i.e. that truth implies the exclusion of falsity) and not of the ‘exclusion principle’ in general (sometimes also known as ‘Frege-Geach principle’), whereby ‘p’ as such excludes ‘not p’. In the conjunctive view, negation is not exclusion, what is exclusive is truth (Sect. 3.1). One may say that (as Beall, 2006a suggests) when you have a true contradiction negation is ‘on holiday’, it loses its property of excluding the opposite.Footnote 14

The basic idea of Conj is that contradictions might occur, and might be truthfully described as such (C1), but this does not require any acceptance of falsity, or any rejection or restriction of AE, because the two conjuncts of a true contradiction are neither true nor false (C2) and cannot be asserted separately (C3). In this way, conjunctivists may dispel at least some of the perplexities traditionally opposed to dialetheism, or to glutty truth-theorists in general. As said in Sect. 1.3, dialetheists accept almost any version of LNC (see Berto, 2008; Martin, 2015); but, in admitting D2 and hence some coincidence or overlapping of truth and falsity as a distinctive character of true contradictions, AE is necessarily dropped (the ‘exclusion constraint […] is (of course) dropped, since some sentences may be gluts’, Beall, 2009: p. 18). For conjunctivists, the acceptance of D1 does not require this, one may peacefully admit that ‘p and not p’ is to be said true, without getting rid of AE. This means that D3 is rejected too, a true contradiction is simply true, its negation is untrue. As mentioned in Sect. 1.3, dialetheism has often been discussed insofar as endorsing D3 (which is a natural consequence of D2).Footnote 15 The main difficulty is possibly related to the discussive role of AE: if you state that a certain ‘p’ is a dialetheia, and someone does not agree with you, then you cannot disagree with her, because in your view it is true that ‘p’ is a dialetheia, but it is also true that it is not. Different solutions have been proposed (a notion of ‘material incompatibility’ is advanced by Berto, 2007: pp. 284–292, 2008). The solution that conjunctivists can provide is that there is no need to renounce (reject or restrict) AE in any form: one can perfectly accept that some contradictory state description is true, without modifying the usual notion of truth; one should simply reject Simplification in case of contradictory statements. You acknowledge that there is a contradiction, and the case is well described by ‘p and not p’ (C1), but in virtue of AE, you exclude that there is not: the case is not describable as ‘not(p and not p)’. The truth that conjunctivists ascribe to ‘p and not p’ is thus ‘simple’, ‘unilateral’ truth, they accept that every true proposition (contradictions included) is just true or true simpliciter (see Sect. 4).Footnote 16

All this does not imply that Conj is to be considered as a sort of ‘true dialetheism’ or the best way of being glut theorist. Simply, the adoption of a conjunctive view seems to provide some new support to the idea of true contradiction, by taking into account the traditional objections concerning the notion of ‘ruling out’ and the exclusionary property of truth (thereby a fundamental and unmissable feature of the concept must be the rejection of falsity). A strict, orthodox dialetheist could oppose that a conjunctive position, so intended, would not be properly dialetheic, as ‘p and not p’ behaves as if it were an atomic sentence, while the challenge is due to the double nature of the dialetheia; so again, ‘the dialetheic motivation is not taken seriously’. They may have some reasons for such a claim (Sect. 3.2).

2 Three paradoxes

To see how the hypothesis may work, let us see three examples of paradoxes that can be legitimately considered (by dialetheists) true contradictions. They will be presented here in the question-and-answer approach suggested for the non-adjunctivist computer of Sect. 1.2, which allows for an epistemic-pragmatic evaluation (concerning what believers or speakers believe or assert).Footnote 17

2.1 Two errors

A quite famous Liar-like paradox (see also Sect. 4.2) is the sentence E, which says:

There are two errors in in this sentence.

At first, E seems to be false, because there is only one error in the sentence, but if it is false, then it must be true, because then there are two errors, the repetition of ‘in’ and the fact that it says there are two errors. However, if there are two errors, then ‘E’ is true, and there is only one error. So we get the typical result: if there is only one error (E1) then there are two (E2), and if there are two there is one. As the errors are at least one and no more than two, we have the Inclosure Schema: E ↔ ¬E. In the dialetheist diagnosis, this means, via Excluded Middle, that E ∧ ¬E is true, and is to be accepted as such (Sect. 1.3).

Suppose now an ideal–typical naïve believer S, who is asked: ‘how many errors are there?’. Very plausibly, S begins by answering ‘only one’ or ‘two’, and then she possibly discovers the trick concealed in E. Now the dialetheic conclusion may make some sense: S may concede that the sentence ‘E’ is a strange case of ‘two-one’ mistaken sentence, which presents only one error and two errors at the same time, and whose description in terms of ‘E and not E’ has some plausibility (C1). However, if questioned about ‘E1?’ or ‘E2?’, S would not accept one or the other option (C2), and she would not be able to go back to her previous view: the possibility of believing (or assuming) separately one or the other is excluded (C3).Footnote 18 The important point is that E1 and E2 are not definitely false for her, because, ultimately, she sees that there is only one error, and there are two errors. They are not false but cannot be said to be true either: as it were, they are two ‘gaps’, whose joined occurrence makes one glut.

In this account, the conjunctive approach does not change the basic dialetheist conclusion: paradoxes of this kind release true contradictions. What changes is how the notion of ‘true contradiction’ is interpreted. While a di-aletheist account of the question-and-answer situation would imply ‘yes’ and ‘yes’ for both the questions ‘E2?’ and ‘E1?’ (see Priest, 19872: 61; and here Sect. 4.1), for conjunctivists the answers are ‘no’ and ‘no’, which are interpretable, if you want, as ‘not exactly’ and ‘not exactly’. The difference is subtle, but the consequences might be interesting.

It should be noted that in this way Conj is able to incorporate the gap-theory intuition (that paradoxes are neither true nor false sentences); but the diagnosis is included in a glutty picture, as E is held to instantiate a contradictory state of affairs. The conclusion (that ‘E and not E’ is true) tells us that truth as such does not fail: S is perfectly able to diagnose the situation, and to describe it in a true (and plausible-acceptable) way. Another noteworthy point is that the ‘gaps’ mentioned by C2 occur for unassertability (Sect. 4.3). S does not like to accept ‘E1’ or ‘E2’ separately, not in virtue of some epistemic under-determinacy (she knows everything about E), or some other hitches (say, category mistakes, failed presuppositions, contingent futures, etc. —see Priest, 2008: pp. 130–133), but because she positively knows that ‘E1’ and ‘E2’ are partial (and specifically instable) state descriptions. Evidently, not any partial truth is untrue (or unassertable) but the particular incompleteness of ‘E1’ and ‘E2’ as separate assertions makes them visibly misleading: in asserting that there is only one error S conveys the idea that there are not two errors, which is untrue, and will be promptly disproved.Footnote 19 Over-determination so makes the two sentences untrue and unassertable, for the same reason why it makes their conjunction assertable and true.

2.2 The frog-tadpole

Another typical dialetheic case is the case of borderline properties. Between frog and tadpole there are infinite stages (Cargile, 1969), so that in the central area of the process we can see there are some points in which there is a frog that is not a frog, and the contradiction becomes (in some dialetheic sense) ‘visible’.Footnote 20 If S is asked about a specific frog-tadpole (and she is willing to accept the contradiction), she will admit that there is a contradictory state of affairs, which deserves the description ‘this is a frog that is not a frog’, so something like ‘Fa and not Fa’ (C1). But now asked about ‘Fa?’ she would not say ‘yes’, without the other part of the story, and would not even believe that Fa (C3). She will honestly acknowledge that the object she is speaking about is not ‘exactly’ a frog, as it lacks having some typical (essential) properties that frogs have in any possible worlds; and it is not ‘exactly’ a tadpole either, for the same reason (C2).

Here we see the weird point of Conj: a true (assertable and acceptable) state description is made of two untrue (unassertable and unacceptable) sentences. Again, there is no ‘failure’ of truth, strictly speaking, because there is a state of affairs positively occurring, which is understandable, and describable, as such. What fails is our will to isolate the property F (being a frog) as applied to a, from not F (in this case, from ‘being a tadpole’). And it is this specific failure by over-determination (see Sect. 4.2) that C2 intends to stress.

Interestingly, experiments about borderline evaluations have shown that the conjunctive interpretation makes sense. In the case of typically vague predicates, such as ‘tall’, naïve speakers generally accept that a certain man b is tall-and-not-tall but are unwilling to accept an instance of the Excluded Middle, that either ‘b is tall’ or ‘b is not tall’ is true.Footnote 21 This does not simply mean that they want ‘a third possibility’. Rather, they are aware that the contradiction is true (is made true by an actually occurring state of affairs), but the two ‘epistemic parties’ separately defending ‘b is tall’ and ‘b is not tall’ are both wrong, simply because they offer an incomplete state description as it were the whole truth.

2.3 Fortunate misfortune

A third case is the paradox of the fortunate misfortune (Smilansky, 1994, 2007). A young girl, Abigail, was born with a combination of unfortunate defects concerning her legs and breathing. To correct them she needed to learn to swim and to continue swimming in an intensive way, which she did, so that, after a certain number of years, her breathing and legs became normal. Meanwhile, she became an excellent swimmer, to the point that she won the women’s world backstroke championship for many years (Smilansky, 2007: p. 12).

What can we say about Abigail? Was she fortunate, or unfortunate? Both? Neither? She was both, in a sense, but we cannot exactly say that she was one thing or the other. The appropriate description of Abigail’s case is that her misfortune has made her fortunate,Footnote 22 and surely, in the end, fortune was dominant, but in our evaluation of the entire case (and similar cases), we cannot honestly say that Abigail has one or the other of the two incompatible properties, taken separately.

Given ‘λ’ for Abigail, and ‘Φx’ for ‘x is fortunate’, we ought to ascribe to λ a complex property, which makes her both fortunate and unfortunate, so ‘Φλ and not Φλ’ will be true (C1). The account in terms of conjunction and negation is justified, ‘not’ marks the anti-extension of a property (see Sect. 3.1), and the ‘and’ conjoins two well-formed sentences that we infer from the evidence of a state of affairs (see Sect. 3.2). But we cannot accept that λ (Abigail) is only one thing or the other, for the same reasons that we cannot accept ‘Fa’ (a is a frog) or ‘not Fa’, and ‘E1’ (that there is only one error in E) or ‘E2’ (C2). Actually, if we accept ‘Φλ’ separately, then we are led to infer for λ what we would infer for any ‘Φx’: for instance, that she does not deserve our compassion and admiration; or, alternatively, if we accept ‘not Φλ’, our compassion would make us forget or underrate what she was able to achieve from her own disadvantage (C3).

One can justify the refusal of separate assertion in this case by appealing to pragmatic as well as metaphysical considerations. From a pragmatic point of view, ‘λ is fortunate’ is unacceptable because it is a partial and misleading state description. In asserting only ‘a is [is not] a frog’ or ‘λ is [is not] fortunate’, I mislead people who may infer from my assertion untrue consequences. So we can say that the conjunctive account aims at observing the maxim of quantity. Notably, the reason why the maxim should not be violated (in contradictory cases as in many other cases) is that incomplete assertions easily convey falsities. Thus, one would say that Conj also respects the maxim of quality (truthfulness). If we adopt instead a metaphysical view, we ought to concede that the two properties are so strictly connected that any separate account seems to misrepresent the situation (Sect. 3.2). They are ‘fused’ together, but in a special way. In Kit Fine’s truthmaker semantics, there is a variety of ways in which states (facts) can be combined or joined: ‘We must allow, for example, that one state may be a part of another, as when the presence of rain is part of the presence of rain and the wind, or that two states may fuse to a single composite state, as when the presence of rain and the presence of wind fuse to the presence of rain and wind view’ (Fine, 2017: p. 559). As to ‘fusion’ as such, for Fine the most natural sense is not properly ‘conjunctive’: ‘there is a natural sense in which facts may be fused. So for example given the fact f that this ball is red and the fact g that it is round, there will be a fused fact f. g’ (Fine, 2012: p. 72). This ‘natural sense’ of fusion admits of simplification: having a red ball, we can truthfully say ‘it is red’ and separately ‘it is round’. But the fusion of redness and roundness does not seem comparable to the joint occurrence of Φ and not Φ in λ’s case. The two properties mutually interact in a way that is sensibly different from the ordered and disciplined way in which forms interact with colors (Sect. 3.2).

Briefly, what we can see in these three cases is that the properties we ascribe to objects do not always have well-defined borders, sometimes we cannot distinguish the extension and the anti-extension of a given property. And this may hold for any sort of property: for semantic properties (being a sentence with two errors) as well as for natural properties (being a frog), or for value properties (being a fortunate girl). The idea implicit in C2 is namely that contradictions may occur, and we have ‘good evidence’ of their occurring (Sect. 1.5), but they occur as a failure of our will to believe that p or to believe that not p; and an honest speaker or believer should acknowledge this failure (C3). In this sense, the conjunctive treatment of paradoxes, implying a combination of two epistemic gaps for one glutty state, seems to introduce a new way of being glut theorists.

3 Open problems and possible solutions

The conjunctivist view seems to be plausible in the framework of an informal and epistemic-pragmatic account of paradoxes, but the benefits of the theory (for instance, the possibility of recapturing AE) might not exceed the logical costs.Footnote 23 As mentioned in the opening, the aim of the article is not to show the ‘superiority’ of Conj with respect to other positions, but to explore its plausibility as a rational theory of non-explosive true contradictions. The approach is thus mainly ‘pre-logical’; it is focused on the reasons we may have in interpreting the possible occurrence of contradictions in the way intended by C1, C2 and C3.Footnote 24

In the following, I will propose only some ideas for further inquiries, focusing on the three main questions: what is the meaning of ‘not’ for a conjunctive conception of true contradictions? is the conjunctive ‘and’ still an ‘and’? what is the postulated meaning of ‘truth’? Negation and conjunction will be dealt with in this section, truth in the next one.

3.1 Yes, but not exactly

Conjunctivists can accept the dialetheic conception of negation in all its basic features. ‘Not’ is meant to be a contradiction operator (as in classical logic); it has ‘partial’ and ‘positive’ content (so is not metaphorically comparable to complementation or cancellation); and it is pragmatically distinct from ‘rejection’ (accepting ‘p and not p’ does not mean accepting and rejecting ‘p’ at the same time). The difference appears as soon as truth is involved.

As Priest states (19872: p. 61), ‘it well may be that if a person is asked whether A or not A, she can of course say “yes and no” without meaning that she both accepts and rejects A, rather that she accepts both A and not A’. Conjunctivists can approve of such a picture. What they specify is the not exactly idea suggested in Sect. 2.1: when ‘yes’ means ‘yes, this is true’, the speaker or believer has an alethic commitment, which implies exclusion.Footnote 25 ‘Not exactly’ is to some extent equivalent to ‘yes, but…’, both are ways in which one expresses partial truths, but more specifically, one ought to say ‘yes, there are two errors in E, but not exactly two’; ‘yes, Abigail is a fortunate girl but not only this’; and ‘yes, a is a frog, but not exactly a frog in all respects’ (the reference to ‘exactness’ is especially important, as it may recall the conception of truth that is involved in Conj: Sect. 4). An honest and informed speaker or believer who faces some ‘p and not p’ would not reject ‘p’ or ‘not p’ but would be unwilling to assert or to assume each separately.

The arguments in favor of this view mainly concern the pragmatics of ‘yes and no’ (Ripley, 2011), but the idea may also have some metaphysical groundings. In the conjunctive view, ‘not’ works classically as a border operator, it marks the extension and the anti-extension of a property (see Sect. 2.2). In most cases, borders are uncontroversially exclusive, and so falsity, with its exclusive import, is equivalent to negation. In some other (rare) cases instead, we have a complex object-fact, endowed with a complex (internally contradictory) property, and we cannot describe it otherwise than by ‘p and not p’, so we have a dialetheia: ‘p and not p’ is held true. Now negation is no longer exclusive, but the metaphysical correlate of ‘not’ is always the same: it still ‘names’ or ‘describes’ the border of the property. If conjunctivists are willing to accept this approach, they may find some support in David Armstrong’s late treatment of negatives (Armstrong, 2010: p. 79 ss.), whereby ‘not’ is ‘the cutter’, as it marks the limits of properties or states of affairs. They would thus say that contradictory states are situations in which negation plays its usual role, but does not have any alethic autonomy: the truthmaker is the ‘total fact’, joining p and not p. Such a view is nicely adaptable to Beall’s idea mentioned in Sect. 1.5: that in the case of dialetheias, negation is ‘on holiday’, it forgets its task of excluding the opposite. Because in this sense, the determining role of negation is preserved (as border operator), but the exclusionary role of truth is preserved too.

3.2 And?

In proposing the failure of Simplification, Conj encounters at first the objection already seen for Non-Adjunctivism: is the ‘and’ still an ‘and’? Non-adjunctivists can support their view by appealing to plausible cases in which non-adjunctive ‘ands’ are used without betraying the ordinary meaning of the operator. Conjunctivists should adopt a similar strategy, and one may suppose the research is not so difficult, as in natural language there are many cases of unreducible ‘and’ that ‘cannot be anything else than an “and”’.Footnote 26 A classic case of divorce between distributive and collective predication (Oliver & Smiley, 2013: pp. 25–28) is mentioned in Plato’s Hippias Major. Hippias asserts that ‘whatever is true of two together is also true of each’ (302b); Socrates counters that if so, then ‘if two is what we together are, then two is what each of us must be as well’ (301e), which is absurd. Traditionally, it is a simple fallacy of division. But Socrates’s example involves the case of numerical predicates, which do not express simple empirical properties such as ‘being red’ or ‘being round’ (Sect. 2.3), but special (second order) properties. Now we can note that ‘true’ is a predicate-property of this kind. So there are reasons to postulate that the same holds for T: if you and I are two, this does not mean I am two and so are you, and similarly, that a collection of truthbearers is true does not necessarily mean its members are (to be equally said) true as well.

The thesis seems odd, prima facie, but reasonable accounts of truth can support it. In a semantics of exact truthmaking the CT mentioned at the beginning of this paper does not hold unrestrictedly, and it may fail namely in the left-to-right (only if) direction: an ‘exactly’ true conjunction does not necessarily entail the exact truth of its conjuncts. The example mentioned by Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006) is simple. A proposition is true in virtue of the state of affairs or fact that makes it true. Suppose ‘Peter is a man and Saturn is a planet’, which is true: it is made true by the fact that Peter is a man and Saturn is a planet. But ‘it is not the case that 〈Peter is a man〉 is true in virtue of the fact that Peter is a man and Saturn is a planet; it is simply true in virtue of the fact that Peter is a man’ (Rodriguez-Pereyra, 2006: p. 970). The Conjunctive Thesis, whereby ‘e is a truthmaker for 〈P & Q〉 if and only if e is a truthmaker for 〈P〉 and e is a truthmaker for 〈Q〉, does not hold’.Footnote 27 This confirms that ‘and’, when seen from a metaphysical point of view, does not always satisfy Simplification. Clearly, in the example mentioned by Rodriguez-Pereyra the entailment fails because there is no semantic or metaphysical ‘proximity’ between the conjuncts, while what is postulated by Conj is the opposite: Simplification fails because the conjuncts are strictly connected; so strictly, that they cannot be separated. What, then, is the structure of the contradictory truthmaker postulated by Conj?

A reasonable objection addressed to conjunctivists (see Sect. 1.5) is that in virtue of the Fundamental Condition, the joined incompatibles must be two distinct terms (propositions, beliefs, states of affairs), while their ‘fusional’ view seems to imply that there is in fact only one term. The problem of ‘two or one fact?’ for the metaphysics of contradiction has been raised by Armstrong (2004: pp. 107–108). If we decide to accept that a contradiction is true, should we postulate one fact (‘the very same entity or collection of entities’), simultaneously working as a truthmaker and falsemaker of ‘p’? Are there instead two distinct facts, p and ¬p, both acting as truthmakers for ‘p ∧ ¬p’, and each simultaneously as falsemaker for the other conjunct? If we adopt the latter option, ‘should it be said that the two sets of truthmakers are identical, or merely overlap, or are disjoint?’.Footnote 28 Dialetheists generally prefer the two-fact account, and if they are truthmaker maximalist (thus thinking that every truth must have a truthmaker), they assume that there are specifically negative facts or states of affairs. In fact, the subsistence of negative facts is controversial in truthmaker semantics, some believe that truthmaker maximalism is unconceivable namely because there cannot be negative truthmakers (see Tallant, 2018).Footnote 29 Conjunctivists would favor the one-fact option, but without overlapping of truth and falsity. They say that a contradictory state (of affairs) consists of only one (positive) state, made of two contradictory parts, and acting as a simple truthmaker for the conjunctive state description. The solution seems quite intuitive. Let us reconsider the three cases suggested in Sect. 2. We have three single states, concerning three single objects: the sentence E whose odd property is to be a ‘two-one’ mistaken sentence; the frog-tadpole object whose particular status makes the sentence ‘Fa ∧ ¬Fa’ true; and Abigail, who is a fortunate unfortunate girl in virtue of some particular adventures and misadventures that have occurred in her life. So, the two propositions ‘E’ and ‘¬E’ are intended to describe two ‘parts’ of the single object E, just like ‘Fa’ and ‘¬Fa’ describe two parts of the frog-tadpole, and the double evaluation of Abigail’s case is ascribed to a collection of occurrences concerning the fact-event of her life. In all these cases, the ‘and’ clause is in order, because there are two properties instantiated in one object, and ‘not’ plays its natural role of describing the limit of a property, but the entailment by T-distribution fails.

In practice, the adoption of Conj postulates that what is glutty (excessive) is the contradictory case, as it involves the joint occurrence of opposite properties (in stratified, combined or otherwise joined form), but there is no glut for truth: truth and falsity do not overlap. Clearly, this must involve a particular conception of truth.

4 The underlying conception of truth: preliminaries

The basic motivation for conjunctivism, in the version here proposed (see especially Sect. 1.5), is the need of an honest admittance of contradictory facts (and pieces of evidence), while maintaining—discussively, expressively and epistemically—the conditions of AE, intended as a grounding rule of reason (and thus of logic). Different approaches to inconsistency may satisfy these (or similar) needs. What is typically shared by dialetheism and conjunctivism, as suggested (Sect. 1.4), is the idea that a rational use of the notion of truth does not prevent, but rather implies, the acceptance of ‘true contradictions’ in the conjunctive form. What Conj adds to this picture is that the putatively ‘contradictory truth’ can be perfectly respectful of AE. So the decisive point is how the predicate-property T is to be conceived, and how such a conception can be justified.

In Priest’s version (see Priest, 2006: pp. 43–55), dialetheism is in principle compatible with any theory of truth. Correspondence, pragmatic, and coherence theories (the classically ‘robust’ theories), as well as minimalism, redundancy, and deflationism in general, may contemplate the occurrence of dialetheias. ‘In talking of true contradictions no particular notion of truth is presupposed. Interpreters of the term “dialetheism” may interpret the notion of truth concerned in their own preferred fashion’ (Priest, 2007: p. 131). A deflationary truth theory is proposed by Beall (2009); his ‘transparent truth’ implies that the ‘only T’ or ‘just T’ value, satisfying AE, holds for any non-paradoxical sentence (see Beall, 2009: p. 48). In Cobreros et al. (2012), a similar dualism is interpreted within a semantic-pragmatic approach to borderline contradictions, which is not far from what has been advanced informally here (Sect. 2). The authors assume that ‘T’ is to be used in a strict or tolerant way, and the evaluation of contradictory state descriptions involves tolerant truth.

In the view presented here, one would rather speak of intolerant truth, as the use and meaning of the truth predicate is ruled by the unrestricted exclusion of falsity. There is only one meaning-use of ‘T’, and it is ‘just T’, satisfying AE; what—for some reason—is not ‘just T’ cannot deserve truth ascription. The conjunctive T-theory is not explosive (as the ECQ does not hold: Sect. 1.5), but it is perfectly ‘classical’ in this respect: it can be labelled as a ‘classical glut theory’, following Scharp’s taxonomy (2013: p. 23).Footnote 30

4.1 Truth in disagreement

For Conj (as it is here intended) contradictory propositions are state descriptions (C1), and they are said true insofar as describing an effectively occurring fact or state of affairs of a contradictory nature (so being made true by special, glutty facts: Sect. 3.2). The meaning of the truth predicate is thus not far from what was intended by Plato or Aristotle: a proposition is (can be said) T iff it ‘says how things stand’ (Plato, Cratilus, 385c: ta onta legei os estin).Footnote 31 The commitment to the ta onta principle (as traditionally intended) postulates that the action of ‘saying’ in assertive cases (when truth is formally required) is ruled by actuality (true ‘in the actual world’)Footnote 32 and completeness (‘the whole truth’). It is assumed, in practice, that in saying/believing that ‘p’ is true the speaker or believer implies that she accepts/believes that p, and everyone should accept/believe it, because ‘things stand in that way’. All of this is only formally, or ritually, required, which means S might lie (she asserts ‘p’ but does not believe-accept that p) and/or might be wrong (things do not stand in that way), but this is the special commitment conveyed by the use of the predicate.

Tested against this notion of truth, Non-Adj and di-aletheism reveal some explanatory and interpretative limits, while Conj seems preferable. Paradigmatic non-adjunctive cases belong to three situations: the impersonal system (Varzi’s computer), possible worlds semantics (Rescher & Brandom, 1980), and the discussive scenario postulated by Jaśkowski or other authors. In the first case, the system perfectly satisfies completeness, but it is not entitled to evaluate the contents involved (‘the things’); one would say the system is analetheic, or T-free. In the second case, we speak of ‘true-in-two-worlds’, and so the actuality restriction does not hold. In the third case, there are different options, but the most easily adaptable to concrete non-adjunctive cases is the interpretation of the situation as involving perspectival truth, or T ‘according to the story told by an epistemic agent’. When we face a discussive situation in which X says that p and Y says that not p, non-adjunctivists as well as di-aletheists postulate they might both be right. However, if by ‘being right’ we mean that they tell the truth (in the intended sense), then Non-Adj is out of the question, as it regards truths in different worlds or stories. Dialetheism seems preferable, as we can speak of ‘T’ in the traditional sense: there is a contradictory state that makes ‘p and not p’ true, and X and Y are discussing about it. But if it is so, then we can see that ‘p’ and ‘not p’ are partial accounts of facts, and we cannot say that X and Y are ‘both right’ (as di-aletheists would postulate). Rather, they are both wrong, as they would present their partial view as the whole truth. Actuality is respected; completeness is violated. So, if ‘T’ is meant to be the complete-actual truth, then there is no possible—conjunctive or distributed—di-aletheic case.Footnote 33

In contrast, Conj seems more adaptable to the ancient (exact, intolerant) truth theory. The conjunctive view simply adds to the dialetheic treatment the idea that if you take ‘this is T’ as ruled by completeness and actuality, then neither X’s nor Y’s position is tenable. They cannot both be right, as long as they intend to present their thesis as the whole truth in our world, because this is simply untrue. ‘Fa’ or ‘E1’ or ‘Φλ’, as well as their negative counterparts, separately taken, do violate the ta onta principle in both requirements of completeness and actuality: things in our world do not stand exactly in that way.

4.2 The Liar’s challenge

For conjunctivists truth is indefectibly marked by AE, and LND2 holds unrestrictedly. In this respect, they ought to face an important challenge: the Liar paradox seems to provide a strong justification for di-aletheism and a clear counter-example to LND2 and AE.Footnote 34 At first, the epistemic-pragmatic account proposed for the three paradoxes (Sect. 2) can be applied to the Liar. Given ‘μ’ (the sentence which says of itself it is false or untrue), an ideal agent questioned about ‘μ’ would not answer ‘yes’ to ‘μ?’ or ‘not μ?’ without adding any further specifications (C3), as she knows that if ‘μ’ is true then it must be untrue, and if it is untrue, it must be true, so both ‘μ’ and ‘not μ’ as such are for her unassertable and untrue (C2). However, this does not necessarily mean that the Liar’s assertion is (for her) a truth-value gap. She can acknowledge, along with dialetheists, that the sentence instantiates a weird and self-contradictory state, whose description ‘μ and not μ’ is simply (only) true: it is an adequate state description, made true by some (semantic) state of affairs (C1).

To make the account a bit more technical, one may begin by postulating that ‘μ’ is to be considered as an assertion. Normally, assertion-sensitive treatments of the Liar (Goldstein, 2000, 2006; Jago, 2018, Ch. 10) are intended to show that there is no (true) contradiction. It is claimed that the sentence ‘μ’ fails its assertive aim, namely in virtue of AE. ‘The function of an assertion ¬A is to reject A’, so ‘the dialetheist who asserts a contradiction A, ¬A will be both accepting and rejecting the content of A, and this is surely rationally impermissible’ (Jago, 2018: p. 288). In fact, as we have seen (Sect. 3.1) negation for both dialetheists and conjunctivists is not rejection, rather, for conjunctivists it has no ‘excluding’ property as such, if it is not accompanied by truth. Conjunctivists can perfectly accept that asserting ‘p’ means excluding ‘not p’, but this is because asserting that p means to imply that ‘p’ is (believed/assumed as) true, with consequent commitment to AE. As seen, this does not prevent them from acknowledging that ‘μ and not μ’ is true and can be asserted as such.

To see how this may work, let’s see a version of the Liar argument that is not far from what is normally proposed by dialetheists (see Priest, 2006: pp. 107–108), but makes the hypothesis more clearly visible (especially for its affinity with the cases mentioned in Sect. 2). If assertions are truth-implying,Footnote 35 then what the Liar conveys in an assertive context is that it is true that what she is saying is untrue (or false). The form of ‘μ’ which deserves alethic analysis (and therefore can be said true, or false, or neither or both) is thus:

(*) T〈¬Tμ〉.

Now the argument that draws the contradiction may run in this way:

C4

  

1

T〈¬T〈μ〉〉

 

2

T〈μ〉

Df. μ 1

3

μ

T-Out 2 (Rel.)

4

¬T〈μ〉

T-Out 1

5

¬μ

T-Out 4

6

μ ∧ ¬μ

∧I 3,5

Notably, to get μ ∧ ¬μ there is no need for the Excluded Middle, nor does one need to discharge the hypothesis, as (*) is given by the Liar herself, in her same asserting ‘μ’. Note also that such an account of the Liar corresponds to a quite traditional way of working with the paradox. It is in line with the old idea, widely shared in traditional researches about paradoxes, that Liar-like contradictions involve complex predicates or concepts, related to properties whose stratification (material iteration, diagonalization, indefinite extensibility, etc.) may produce (or seems to produce) the joined occurrence of what in principle cannot jointly occur.Footnote 36 But what is relevant for the conjunctive hypothesis is that here ‘μ’ results an object endowed with a complex, internally contradictory, property-predicate, in line with what has been proposed in Sect. 2 for E, a, and λ: they all are weird objects, instantiating contradictory properties.

However, the properties of ubiquity (capture) and factivity (release) typical of truth (if the T-schema holds unrestrictedly) have consequences that conjunctivists may judge problematic. The same occurrence of the paradox apparently legitimates T-distribution, in some di-aletheic form, as it conveys both D1 and D2, and the former in virtue of the latter. In C4, we get μ ∧ ¬μ, and then we assume the dialetheic non-di-aletheic conclusion T〈μ ∧ ¬μ〉, but to arrive at this from (*), we first get T〈μ〉 (Df. μ), then ¬T〈μ〉 (T-Out), so we can also conclude with the obvious intuition that ‘μ’, ultimately, is true and untrue, as T〈μ〉 and ¬T〈μ〉 both hold, so D2 is confirmed.

To avoid this difficulty, conjunctivists essentially have two options. They can claim that the property-predicate which the Liar’s sentence ascribes to itself is not ‘truth’, actually; or at least it is not that sort of truth we use in epistemology, and in the pragmatics of language, as a feature of beliefs and assertions. Thus, conjunctivists would be committed to distinguish ‘logical truth’ (transparent truth) from other alethic devices (a hypothesis that is to be found in Beall, 2019), so stating that the conjunctive treatment only holds for extra-logical conceptions of truth. Perhaps this is not a good solution, particularly if conjunctivists want to keep to the idea that there must be only one ‘truth’, the above seen actual and complete (exact and intolerant: Sect. 4.3) truth, which must hold for any T-ascription, and for logic as well as for any other sector or area of concern. Another strategy is to assume a relevance semantics, whereby the conjunction of step 6 in C4 is a ‘fusion’. This means that ‘and’ works as a premise binder, so that 2 and 4 are ‘inseparable’: once you obtain ‘p and not p’ in a relevant proof you cannot go back to ‘p’ or ‘not p’. In this sense, the conjunction is to be held an intensional—content-sensitive—operator.Footnote 37 In line with this solution, one would say that the true sentence, in the Liar’s case, is not ‘μ’, but ‘μ and not μ’, so it is rather admitted a distinction between μ (in Italic) as the fact of the Liar’s assertion (which is the special glutty fact we have seen, similar to the other contradictory facts mentioned in Sect. 2) and ‘μ’ as the sentence uttered by the Liar. This would be in accordance with what has been suggested in Sect. 3.2: the truthmaker is one (Sect. 3.2), the best description we can give of it is ‘μ and not μ’ (which would justify the di-aletheists’ counter-objection, seen at the end of Sect. 1.5).

4.3 Exact and intolerant truth

The aim of this article is to explore the plausibility of Conj as a rational theory of non-explosive true contradictions, giving a preliminary (and mainly pre-logical) account of the hypothesis. A semantics for conjunctivism, and a formal development of the consequent truth theory, will be dealt with in other papers, but some ideas for future work can be anticipated.Footnote 38 To keep to what has been here suggested, a consequent logic for Conj ought to be a natural deduction whereby assumptions (premises) belong to the class of assertives, and so have ‘a word-to-world direction of fit’. Propositions—as required by C1—are state descriptions, they intend to capture an occurring or occurred fact or state of affairs, and this holds for any proposition, contradictions included. The T-schema would work, quite traditionally, as an inter-substitutivity rule so that, in an inference, if you have ‘p’ you are in the condition of inferring that T〈p〉 and if you have T〈p〉 you infer ‘p’, and you will have Release or T-Out: T〈p〉 → p, and Capture, or T-In: p → T〈p〉, simply because T ascriptions require that the truthmaker subsists, and if the truthmaker subsists, the state description is T.Footnote 39

By accepting the schema, one is normally committed to exclude exhaustion, i.e. the possibility of untrue but not false statements, so there would not be gaps (rather, any gap is a glut)Footnote 40—if anything, the largely realistic commitment to the ta onta (actuality—completeness) implies that if it is not true that a state of affair subsists, then it is true that it does not subsist. In fact, this does not represent a real difficulty, for the endorsement of C2 (that the conjuncts of a true contradiction are untrue), as the two postulated ‘gaps’ are not failures of T as such, but of the assertability rules governing truth (see Sect. 2). These rules imply the mentioned intolerance of the theory, expressed by the postulate that propositions are assertable (and so can be assumed) only if they are just true (strictly true, or true simpliciter). Now, to be ‘just true’ (jT) means (i) to satisfy the epistemic and pragmatic conditions of assertability (such as being grounded on evidence or other rational sources of justification, and expressing the complete information in the case given and for the Gricean needs); and (ii) to satisfy AE, so that if ‘p’ is T then ‘¬p’ must be untrue, so we have AE1: Tp → ¬T¬p, which contraposes, and hence: AE2: T¬p → ¬Tp.Footnote 41 Notably, the intolerant truth involved in (i) and (ii) is a ritual (formal) feature of assertions. An asserter, evidently, may lie or may present categorically what she does not know for sure, and falsities or untruths can be hypothetically assumed/asserted, but in the special inferential context in which they are asserted/assumed, they must work as they were strictly true. So logical intolerance requires, as formal requisites, categoricalness, and formal commitment to AE, in the case given and for all the inferential needs.Footnote 42 This is what informs C3: it is postulated an intolerant speaker/reasoner, whose assumptions must express exclusive beliefs, well-grounded on perfectly exhaustive (complete) evidence, which evidently is not satisfied by ‘p’ and ‘not p’ separately, in case 〈p and not p〉 is true.

Accordingly, a proposition is unassertable (so cannot be assumed) either because it does not satisfy (i), i.e. the usual features of truth-ascription (it is false, or misleading, or not justified in the admitted ways), or because it does not satisfy (ii): it is a partial description of a contradictory state of affairs. Consequently, there are two different sorts of gaps: gaps for under-determination (‘p’ does not satisfy (i)) and gaps for over-determination (S has contradictory evidence, so ‘p’ does not satisfy (ii)).Footnote 43 Gaps for under-determination are submitted to the natural graduality of epistemic considerations, so that the truth values range from 0 (jF) to 1 (jT), and propositions are untrue if their value does not satisfy a given (contextually determined) epistemic standard, say: |p|= 1 iff P(p|e) ≥ 0.8. Thus, the value of gappy sentences of the first kind (under-determined truths) ranges from 0.2 to less than 0.8; they are neither T nor F, and thus cannot be asserted. (One can also assume a dynamic-adaptive view, to the effect that such sentences become assertable when their T-value increases up to 0.8 or more.) Gappy propositions of the second kind (partial statements about over-determined cases), can never be asserted/assumed as such, but the conjunction with their negation is assertable, as it is simply true.

These conditions can be satisfied in a variety of ways (see note 38). Indicatively, while in the two logics favored by dialetheists, LP and FDE, a contradictory proposition ‘p’ has the value ‘both’ (true-and-false), and in Cobreros et al. (2012) it deserves tolerant truth, so it is ½ or 0.5 true, in the hypothesis here advanced, ‘p’ as such is untrue, and unassertable, because it is an incomplete state description and fails to meet AE. Propositions describing the half of a glutty state are special cases of unassertable partial truth. The consequence for Conj-evaluations is that there is no ‘both’, but the value ‘neither’ splits into indeterminacy (n) and over-determinacy (n+). Thus, there are four possible evaluations: |p|= 1 iff 〈p〉 is jT; |p|= 0 iff 〈¬p〉 is jT; |p|= n iff 〈p〉 is untrue by under-determination; and |p|= n+ iff |p ∧ ¬p|= 1. The two gappy interpretations, respectively, correspond to gaps for ignored (or unproved) truths, and gaps for partial contradictory truths. While n+ sentences are unassertable because they do not satisfy AE, n sentences are unassertable because their truth-value is not enough, so that (for the given standard) their value ranges from 0.2 to less than 0.8. Interpreting the contradictory value not in terms of ‘both’ but in terms of a special sort of ‘neither’, the truth tables change with respect to FDE (see Priest, 2008: pp. 142–162). It is equally assumed that conjunction has the lowest value, and disjunction the greatest:|p ∧ q|= min{|p|, |q|}; |p ∨ q|= max{|p|, |q|}. But values are linearly ordered in this way: 1 > n+  > n  > 0, so that |n ∧ n+|= n and |n ∨ n+|= n+. Evidently, |n+ ∧ n+|= n+, but for the special case ‘p ∧ ¬p’, which is 1, if ‘p’ is a genuine part of a glutty state.Footnote 44 Validity is normally conceived as truth preservation, and the usual rules of natural deduction are preserved. The consequence relation is not ‘explosive’, as ‘p ∧ ¬p’ is not simplifiable, so p ∧ ¬p does not prove q.Footnote 45 In practice, a ‘conjunctivist’ system for natural deduction might be a version of FDE (which contemplates 1, 0, both, neither), though having a special sort of ‘neither’ instead of ‘both’.Footnote 46