Skip to main content
Log in

Political imagination and its limits

  • Imagination and its Limits
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In social and political theory, the imagination is often used in accounting both for creativity, innovation, and change and for sociopolitical stagnation and the inability to promote innovation and change. To what extent, however, can we attribute such seemingly contradictory outcomes to the same mental faculty? To address this question, this paper develops a comprehensive account of the political imagination, one that explains the various roles played by imagination in politics and thus accounts for the promises and limits of the political imagination. This conceptualization of the political imagination allows us to account for the simultaneous presence of its seemingly contradictory roles—such as promoting stability and order on the one hand while generating creativity and critical innovation on the other.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although many have noted the close relationship between imagination and rationality in some cognitive processes, and especially in counterfactual reasoning (Byrne, 2016).

  2. To mention just few examples, Aristotle, Hobbes and Kant all assign important—albeit quite different—epistemological and psychological roles to the imagination and view it as a central aspect of the production of knowledge (Aristotle, 1907, 433b-434a; Hobbes, 2012; Kant, 1998, p. A78). See also Rundell (1984), Schwartz (2020) and Arendt (1992).

  3. For a further defense of the need to focus on the political, rather than the social imagination, see Grant (2014, p. 411).

  4. An example of this is found in the Blackwell Encyclopedia of Political Thought: while the term “reason” appears in tens of pages, there is not a single entry on the “imagination” (Miller et al., 2000). Similarly, 2386 entries in the online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy include the phrases “rationality” and “reason,” whereas only 658 entries include the phrases “imagination” and “imaginary.” This sort of imbalance has led some authors, such as Ezrahi (2012, p. 7) and Bottici & Challand (2011, p. 4), to portray the imagination as the most neglected human faculty in the history of Western philosophy.

  5. In his published work, Ricoeur rarely addresses the question or problem of the imagination directly and tends to focus instead on the dialectic of ideology and utopia (Ricoeur 1986, p. 1). The only occasion where he addresses the problem of imagination explicitly is in his unpublished lectures on the imagination. For an exploration of those, see Taylor (2006) and Geniusas (2016).

  6. Martin, for example, explains that sensory imagining represents “those distinctive episodes of imagining or imaging which correspond to our use of the distinct senses: so we talk of visualizing corresponding to seeing, or listening in one’s head parallel to audition, and so on. Sensory imagining in this sense can be part of wider cognitive projects—imagery can both accompany and also constitute trains of thought” (Martin, 2002, p. 403).

  7. In that sense, the idea of the constitutive imagination adheres to the basic framework of methodological individualism (Arrow, 1994; Elster, 1982).

  8. Importantly, that is not to say that the constitutive imagination defines what kind of imaginary is permissible for a given individual or society. Instead, it limits what one may consider as possible, and thus circumscribes what one may find imaginable. And, as Yablo (1993) argues, the very conceivability of a novel and creative idea normally involves the appearance of its possibility.

  9. In this, the constitutive imagination can be viewed as part of the general phenomena that Currie identifies when he states that “when we imagine a situation and become progressively more ‘immersed’ in it, we start to move from a state that is one of pure imagination to one that is or approaches the condition of belief” (Currie, 2020, p. 17).

  10. For further exploration of the relationship between ideology and imagination, see Thompson (1982) and Lefort (1986).

  11. This point also highlights the possibility that we may find, within a given society, various groups that hold different constitutive imaginations. While I refer here to the constitutive imagination as something that is shared by the society at large, it is certainly likely that various social groups within the state may hold their own, unique constitutive imagination, which allows them to maintain their own identity, institutions, and shared sense of meaning. Such sub-sets of the constitutive imagination would not necessarily conform with the broader constitutive imagination and could actually challenge it in various ways.

  12. For a more systematic account of the relationship between imagination and action, see Joas (1996), Johnson (1993) and van Leeuwen (2016).

  13. Taylor (1986, pp. xxvii–xxx) interprets this function of utopia in terms of productive, instituting, or constituting imagination, and contrast it to the reproductive, instituted, or constituted imagination that is represented by ideology. For an additional account of the deconstructive and utopian aspect of the imagination, see McManus (2005, pp. 167–169).

  14. For an account of such historical process and the gradual infiltration of individual creative imaginaries into the broader social imagination, see Taylor (2003, p. 24).

  15. In this, the idea of the ‘critical imagination’ resembles C.W. Mills’ concept of the ‘sociological imagination.’ According to him, “the sociological imagination enables its possessor to understand the larger historical sense in terms of its meaning for the inner life and the external career of a variety of individuals. It enables him to take into account how individuals, in the welter of their daily experience, often become falsely conscious of their social positions” (Mills, 1959, p. 15). As a form of self-consciousness, the sociological imagination represents a social and political critique and allows for a sense of historical contingency and social relativity.

  16. In this sense, the sub-group constitutive imaginaries mentioned above (fn. 11) can act as forms of collective critical imagination in their relation to the hegemonic constitutive imagination, especially in the case of marginalized groups.

References

  • Adams, S. (2011). Castoriadis’s ontology: Being and creation. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, S., Blokker, P., Doyle, N. J., Krummel, J. W. M., & Smith, J. C. A. (2015). Social imaginaries in debate. Social Imaginaries, 1(1), 15–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1972). Lying in Politics. In Crises of the Republic, by Hannah Arendt. Martiner Books.

  • Arendt, H. (1992). Lectures on Kant’s political philosophy. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (2006). On revolution. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1907). De Anima (E. R. D. Hicks, Ed. and Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Arrow, K. J. (1994). Methodological individualism and social knowledge. The American Economic Review, 84(2), 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. (2004). The creative mind. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottici, C. (2007). A philosophy of political myth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottici, C. (2011). Towards a theory of imaginal politics. In C. Bottici & B. Challand (Eds.), The politics of imagination (pp. 16–37). London: Birkbeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottici, C. (2014). Imaginal politics: Images beyond imagination and the imaginary. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottici, C., & Challand, B. (2011). Introduction. In C. Bottici & B. Challand (Eds.), Politics of imagination (pp. 1–16). Abingdon: Birkbeck Law Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R. M. J. (2016). Imagination and rationality. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 339–352). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (2000). Art and ethical criticism: An overview of recent directions of research. Ethics, 110(2), 350–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (2002). The wheel of virtue: Art, literature, and moral knowledge. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 60(1), 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castoriadis, C. (1987). The imaginary institutions of society. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castoriadis, C. (1997). World in fragments: Writing on politics, society, psychoanalysis, and the imagination (C. D. A. Curtis, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Currie, G. (2020). Imagining and knowing: The shape of fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative minds: Imagination in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debus, D. (2016). Imagination and memory. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 135–148). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2008). Imagination, delusion, and self-deception. In T. Bayne & J. Fernandez (Eds.), Delusion and self-deception: Affective and motivational influences on belief formation. East Sussex: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1982). The case for methodological individualism. Theory and Society, 11(4), 453–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ezrahi, Y. (2012). Imagined democracies: Necessary political fictions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, J. (2010). Constituent moments: Enacting the people in postrevolutionary America. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, J. (2013). Publius and political imagination. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaonkar, D. P. (2002). Toward new imaginaries: An introduction. Public Culture, 14(1), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaut, B. (2003). Creativity and imagination. In B. Gaut & P. Livingston (Eds.), The creation of art (pp. 148–173). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaut, B. (2010). The philosophy of creativity. Philosophy Compass, 5(12), 1034–1046.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2007). Self-deception as pretense. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 231–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2016). Imagination. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/imagination.

  • Geniusas, S. (2016). Against the Sartrean background: Ricoeur’s lectures of imagination. Research in Phenomenology, 46, 98–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gramsci, A. (1992). Prison notebooks. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant, J. (2014). On the critique of political imaginaries. European Journal of Political Theory, 13(4), 408–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (2012). In E. N. Malcolm (Ed.), Leviathan. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isocrates. (1928). Panegyricus. In G. Norlin (Trans.), The speeches of isocrates (Vol. 1). Portsmouth: Willian Heinemann.

  • Joas, H. (1996). The creativity of action (J. Gaines & P. Keast, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Johnson, M. (1993). Moral imagination: Implications of cognitive science for ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (W. P. Guyer & A. W. Wood, Eds. and Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kieran, M. (1996). Art, imagination, and the cultivation of morals. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 54(4), 337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2013). The Heterogeneity of the Imagination. Erkenn, 78, 141–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2016). Introduction: Exploring imagination. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 1–12). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A., & Kung, P. (2016). Introduction: The Puzzle of imaginative use. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lefort, C. (1986). In J. B. Thompson (Ed.), The political forms of modern societies: Bureaucracy, democracy, totalitarianism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17(4), 376–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • McManus, S. (2005). Fictive theories: Towards a deconstructive and utopian political imagination. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D., Coleman, J., Connolly, W., & Ryan, A. (2000). The Blackwell encyclopedia of political thought. Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. W. (1959). The sociological imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74(2), 115–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noordhof, P. (2002). Imagining objects and imagining experiences. Mind and Language, 17(4), 426–455.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ober, J. (2007). “I besieged that man”: Democracy’s revolutionary start. In J. Ober & K. A. Raaflaub (Eds.), Origins of democracy in Ancient Greece (pp. 83–104). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1967). Gorgias (W. R. M. Lamb, Trans.). Harvard: Harvard University Press.

  • Plato. (1997). Republic. In J. M. Cooper (Ed.), & G. M. A. Grube (Trans.), Complete Works, by Plato. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Ricoeur, P. (1986). In G. H. Taylor (Ed.), Lectures on ideology and Utopia. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1991). The Creativity of Language. In M. J. Valdes (Ed.), A ricoeur reader: Reflection and imagination. Buffalo: Toronto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1994). Imagination in discourse and action. In G. Robinson & J. Rundell (Eds.), Rethinking imagination: Culture and creativity (pp. 118–135). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rundell, J. (1984). Creativity and judgement: Kant on reason and imagination. In G. Robinson & J. Rundell (Eds.), Rethinking imagination: Culture and creativity (pp. 87–117). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, A. (2020). The sleeping subject: On the use and abuse of imagination in Hobbes’s Leviathan. Hobbes Studies, 33(2).

  • Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinhababu, N. (2016). Imagination and belief. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 111–123). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2011). Minimally creative thought. Metaphilosophy, 42(5), 658–681.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2016). Imagination and creativity. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 247–261). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, C. (2006). The imaginary. Anthropological Theory, 6(3), 322–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2003). Modern social imaginaries. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. (2006). Ricoeur’s philosophy of imagination. Journal of French Philosophy, 16(1 & 2), 93–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. H. (1986). Editor’s introduction. In G. H. Taylor (Ed.), Lectures on Ideology and Utopia, by Paul Ricoeur. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, J. B. (1982). Ideology and the social imaginary: An appraisal of castoriadis and lefort. Theory and Society, 11(5), 659–681.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thucydides. (1919). History of the Peloponnesian war. Portsmouth: Willian Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeuwen, V. (2016). Imagination and action. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination (pp. 286–299). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (2002). The company of critics: Social criticism and political commitment in the twentieth century. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53(1), 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This essay benefitted from discussions at the Princeton Graduate Student Conference in Political Theory and the Imagination and Social Change conference at Claremont McKenna College. For reading and providing feedback on earlier drafts, thanks go to Natali Levin Schwartz, Hans Lueders, Jade Ngo, Joan O’Brian, Philip Petrov, Rob Reich, Yosef Schwartz, Daniel Slate, Chloe Stowell, and Lauren Sukin. The paper also benefited greatly from the generous feedback and guidance of the Synthese editorial team and anonymous reviewers. Special thanks go to Alison McQueen for providing thoughtful and insightful comments and suggestions on several drafts of this essay. I am enormously grateful to Josiah Ober, who has guided this project from its earliest stages, and whose generous feedback has contributed immensely to the shape and content of the argument present here.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Avshalom M. Schwartz.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schwartz, A.M. Political imagination and its limits. Synthese 199, 3325–3343 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02936-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02936-1

Keywords

Navigation