Skip to main content
Log in

Why moods change: their appropriateness and connection to beliefs

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There are many more philosophical discussions of emotions than of moods. One key reason for this is that emotions are said to have a robust connection to beliefs while moods are said to lack that connection. I argue that this view, though prevalent, is incorrect. It is motivated by examples that are not representative of how moods typically change. Indeed, once we examine the notion of belief-responsiveness and look at a wider range of examples, we can see that moods are belief-responsive and can be evaluated for appropriateness along a number of dimensions. Moreover, for all cases in which moods seem to be disconnected from beliefs, I argue that there are analogous cases for emotions. In other words, the connection between moods and beliefs on the one hand and the connection between emotions and beliefs on the other are, in fact, very similar. This means that not only should we take belief-responsiveness to be a core feature of moods but also potentially pursue a unified theory for why moods and emotions would have this connection to belief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is not without some precedent. Although they come at the topic from the point of view of psychology and therefore focus on different issues, passages in Parkinson et al. (1996) suggest they take it as a general feature of moods that they respond to changes in belief (p. 7).

  2. Moods in mental health conditions are frequently less stable, more intense, and more motivating than everyday moods. Mental health conditions may also involve moods that differ from everyday moods in their intentionality. For example, clinical anxiety can involve moods that are both more general than a regular anxious mood (as in the case of completely free-floating anxiety) and moods that have a more specific object than a regular anxious mood (as in the case of a social anxiety where anxiety is triggered by very particular types of social circumstances). I want to thank an anonymous referee for this important point.

  3. For a discussion of the various difficulties of trying to introspect our moods, see Haybron (2007), Schwitzgebel (2019) and Ryle (2009, pp. 87–88).

  4. Many use the terms interchangeably. Others, like Schwarz and Clore (2003), take moods and emotions to be distinct but not different in kind. For Schwarz and Clore, both moods and emotions are feelings but emotions are feelings directed at particular objects and moods are undirected.

  5. For a survey of the literature on the differences between emotions and moods, see Beedie et al. (2005).

  6. Moods may also have a long term analog: stable moods that persist in some form or other over years or decades. Ben-Ze’ev (2017) takes happiness to be this kind of enduring mood.

  7. There has been some discussion about how far this analogy can go. Fish (2005), Roberts (2003), and Chomanski (2018) take the analogy very seriously and put forward perceptualist theories of moods. Gallegos (2017) is more skeptical of the lens metaphor, going instead for a nearby view of moods as “interpretive frames.”

  8. There is a vast psychological literature on the myriad effects that moods have on mental functioning. For a particularly helpful discussion of these effects, see Wong (2016).

  9. This holds for the evening of the day of the event. Interestingly, DeLongis et al. (1988) indicated that even though negative events make people’s mood more negative the day of the event, their mood tends to be higher than average the day after.

  10. For some discussion of the complications in determining the rationality of grief, see Gustafson (1989), Price (2010), Wilkinson (2000), Cholbi (2017), and Marušić (2018).

  11. Studies like Diener and Diener (1996), and Diener et al. (2015) give us some reason to think that the most common mood, the one most people default to even when they live in some form of hardship, is a mildly positive one. Ben-Ze’ev (2017) argues this is one of the important mechanisms for cultivating enduring happiness. If this is the case, then it might be an interesting question to ask whether most average situations include a mildly positive mood as an appropriate option. Of course, just because we tend to default to this mood doesn’t mean it’s appropriate to do so. On the other hand, I suspect that the appropriateness of a mood has in part to do with what our expectations are: if our expectations are met or exceeded, better moods are appropriate. Almost by definition, an average day is one where our basic expectations are met: nothing dramatically upsets our day in either direction. So, it seems plausible to suppose that having an average day makes being in a mildly positive mood appropriate. If that’s right, we could explain why even the good moods of those people who live in fairly difficult circumstances are appropriate. This is not to say that just any average day would make a positive mood appropriate. An average day of living in the trenches during World War I would probably not make even a mildly positive mood appropriate, no matter the degree to which the day meets one’s expectations.

  12. Thank you to an anonymous referee for this extremely helpful observation.

References

  • Beedie, C., Terry, P., & Lane, A. (2005). Distinctions between emotion and mood. Cognition and Emotion, 19(6), 847–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Ze’ev, A. (2017). Does loving longer mean loving more? On the nature of enduring affective attitudes. Philosophia, 45(4), 1541–1562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, L. (2000). Causes and consequences of feelings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bollnow, O. F. (2017). The nature of stimmungen. Philosophia, 45(4), 1399–1418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R. (1965). Moods and motives. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 43(3), 277–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (2003). Art and mood: Preliminary notes and conjectures. The Monist, 84(4), 521–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caspi, A., Bolger, N., & Eckenrode, J. (1987). Linking person and context in the daily stress process. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52(1), 184–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi, M. (2017). Grief’s rationality, backward and forward. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 94(2), 255–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomanski, B. (2018). Moods, colored lenses, and emotional disconnection: A comment on Gallegos. Philosophia, 46(3), 625–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens. London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The moralistic fallacy: On the ‘appropriateness’ of emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(1), 65–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, J. P., Green, P. J., Martin, R., & Suls, J. (1997). Differential roles of neuroticism, extraversion, and event desirability for mood in daily life: An integrative model of top-down and bottom-up influences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73(1), 149–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delancey, C. (2006). Basic moods. Philosophical Psychology, 19(4), 527–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeLongis, A., Folkman, S., & Lazarus, R. S. (1988). The impact of daily stress on health and mood: Psychological and social resources as mediators. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54(3), 486–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2009). Taking affective explanations to heart. Social Science Information, 48(3), 359–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., & Diener, C. (1996). Most people are happy. Psychological Science, 7(3), 181–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Kanazawa, S., Suh, E. M., & Oishi, S. (2015). Why people are in a generally good mood. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 19(3), 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2005). Emotions, moods, and intentionality. In G. Forrai & G. Kampis (Eds.), Intentionality: Past and future (pp. 25–35). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallegos, F. (2017). Moods are not colored lenses: Perceptualism and the phenomenology of moods. Philosophia, 45(4), 1497–1513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2000). The emotions: A philosophical exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gustafson, D. (1989). Grief. Noûs, 23(4), 457–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatzimoysis, A. (2019). In search for the rationality of moods. In L. Candiotto (Ed.), The value of emotions for knowledge (pp. 281–296). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2007). Do we know how happy we are? On some limits of affective introspection and recall. Nous, 41(3), 394–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. G. (2012). Solving Frege’s puzzle. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(1/2), 132–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Being and Time. (Stambaugh, Trans.). Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Kind, A. (2014). The case against representationalism about moods. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of mind (pp. 113–134). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krebs, A. (2017). Stimmung: From mood to atmosphere. Philosophia, 45(4), 1419–1436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2019). The intentional structure of moods. Philosophers’ Imprint, 19(49), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, A. M., & Terry, P. C. (2000). The nature of mood: Development of a conceptual model. Journal of Applied Sport Psychology, 12, 16–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lang, P. J. (1988). What are the data of emotion? In V. Hamilton, G. H. Bower, & N. H. Frijda (Eds.), Cognitive perspectives on emotion and motivation (pp. 173–191). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lavallee, L. F., & Campbell, J. D. (1995). Impact of personal goals on self-regulation processes elicited by daily negative events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69(2), 341–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lormand, E. (1985). Toward a theory of moods. Philosophical Studies, 47(3), 385–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madva, A. (2017). Implicit bias, moods, and moral responsibility. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(S1), 53–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marušić, B. (2018). Do reasons expire?: An essay on grief. Philosophers’ Imprint, 18(25), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici, A. (2013). Intentionalism about moods: Intentionalism about moods. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 2(2), 126–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, J. (2019). The intentionality and intelligibility of moods. European Journal of Philosophy, 27, 118–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, B., Totterdell, P., Briner, R. B., & Reynolds, S. (1996). Changing moods: The psychology of mood and mood regulation. Boston, MA: Addison Wesley Longman Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, C. (2010). The rationality of grief. Inquiry, 53(1), 20–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition?: The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(3), 341–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. C. (2003). Emotions: An essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rossi, M. (2019). A perceptual theory of moods. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02513-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009). The concept of mind. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sauchelli, A. (2014). Horror and mood. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51(1), 39–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (2003). Mood as information: 20 years later. Psychological Inquiry, 14(3/4), 296–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2019, December 5). Self-knowledge by looking at others. The Splintered Mind. Retrieved December 6, 2019, from http://schwitzsplinters.blogspot.com/2019/12/self-knowledge-by-looking-at-others.html.

  • Searle, J. (2004). Mind: A brief introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siemer, M. (2005). Moods as multiple-object directed and as objectless affective states: An examination of the dispositional theory of moods. Cognition and Emotion, 19(6), 815–845.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siemer, M. (2009). Mood experience: Implications of a dispositional theory of moods. Emotion Review, 1(3), 256–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sizer, L. (2000). Towards a computational theory of mood. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51(4), 743–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1984). The passions: The myth and nature of human emotions. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stark, S. (2015). Ordinary virtue. Res Philosophica, 92(4), 765–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1979). Desiring the bad: An essay in moral psychology. The Journal of Philosophy, 76(12), 738–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2018). Attention and the cognitive penetrability of perception. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(2), 303–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, S. (2000). Is “normal grief” a mental disorder? The Philosophical Quarterly, 50(200), 290–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, M. Y. (2016). Towards a theory of mood function. Philosophical Psychology, 29(2), 179–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2017). Shaking up the mind’s ground floor: The cognitive penetration of visual attention. Journal of Philosophy, 114(1), 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Kevin Craven, Maegan Fairchild, Stephen Finlay, August Gorman, Gabbrielle Johnson, Janet Levin, Lori Meeks, Mark Schroeder, Ralph Wedgwood, and Ben Winokur, as well as the audiences of the Rocky Mountain Ethics Congress (2018) and the Tokyo Forum for Analytic Philosophy (June 2018) for their very thoughtful comments on various versions of this paper. I am also grateful to Rima Basu, Renée Jorgensen Bolinger, Amber Kavka-Warren, Nicola Kemp, and Kevin Lande for helpful discussion. Finally, I would like to thank the anonymous referees at Synthese whose kind and constructive feedback was integral to this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tatyana A. Kostochka.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kostochka, T.A. Why moods change: their appropriateness and connection to beliefs. Synthese 198, 11399–11420 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02795-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02795-w

Keywords

Navigation