Skip to main content
Log in

An analysis of disposition concepts by the Ramsey test

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This is an essay on the understanding of disposition concepts, which exploits the Ramsey test semantics of conditionals for a refined conditional analysis of dispositions. I will show that this semantics allows for a more accurate account of disposition concepts than the standard semantics of conditionals by David Lewis. This includes dealing with the counterexamples to the conditional analysis, which are known as finks, antidotes, and mimics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are multiple ways of striking and breaking, which respectively give rise to a distinct canonical disposition. For the purpose of the present investigation, however, the binary distinction between conventional and canonical dispositions is sufficiently fine-grained.

  2. Writing down these axioms, I tacitly extend the system of Lewis (1973) to conditional predicate logic, as is done in many applications of this system.

  3. Langton and Lewis (1998) have dismissed Kim’s original definition in view of subtle problems with disjunctive properties. It remains to be seen whether these problems carry over to the present analysis. At least apparently, they do not. For, the peculiar disjunctive properties used by Lewis to criticise the above explanation scheme are not relevant for the ascription of dispositions. For a criticism of the general approach used by Langton and Lewis (1998) to refine Kim’s original definition, see Marshall (2009).

  4. Gärdenfors himself has viewed the Ramsey test, later on, with suspicion in light of a triviality theorem, according to which this test is inconsistent with a fundamental principle of the AGM theory called Consistency Preservation (Gärdenfors 1988, Ch. 7.4). (This principle says that, if \(\beta \) is accepted in K and \(\alpha \) consistent with K, then \(\beta \in K *\alpha \).) Recently, however, there have been various, apparently successful attempts at defending the Ramsey test. Leitgeb (2010) and Rott (2011) have shown, in different ways, that the Ramsey test is reconcilable with Preservation for “flat”, i.e., non-nested conditionals. Rott (2011) has shown, moreover, that Preservation is not a sensible requirement for nested conditionals. Bradley (2007) has devised a general argument against Consistency Preservation in the context of the Ramsey test.

  5. The present introduction of negation of conditionals accords with Stalnaker (1968) and is endorsed by Bradley (2007). The more common alternative \(\lnot (\alpha> \gamma ) \in K_>(E) \text { if and only if } \gamma \notin K(E) *\alpha \) has counterintuitive consequences if used for the analysis of reasoning about dispositions. For, it implies that an object a does (determinately) not have a certain disposition D if we are indeterminate as to whether or not a exhibits the D-specific manifestation under the D-specific stimulus S.

  6. Belief change models using belief bases or possible worlds typically work with such a definition of contractions.

  7. In a similar vein, Lewis (1979) has argued that the semantics of counterfactuals should account for the vagueness and context-relativity of counterfactual statements.

  8. There is a close connection between nonmonotonic and default reasoning. To keep technicalities to a minimum, we have not included a section on this type of reasoning. The reader interested in the connections between nonmonotonic and default reasoning, is referred to Brewka et al. (2008).

  9. See Straßer (2014) for an introduction to adaptive logics.

  10. See van Ditmarsch et al. (2008, Ch. 3) for an introduction.

  11. I should clarify here that by the standard semantics of conditionals, I mean the formal framework of a system of spheres of possible worlds under its metaphysical interpretation by Lewis (1973). The formal framework of a possible worlds ordering by itself is consistent with the Ramsey test semantics, as is obvious from Stalnaker (1968) and Rott (2011).

  12. Unlike the present account, the gradable approach does cover “soft” dispositions where the manifestation is exhibited in less than the majority of stimulus cases. Perhaps we should therefore distinguish between soft and hard dispositions, where the latter qualify as dispositions in the narrower, scientifically more respectable sense. The present approach does of course not exclude grades of dispositionality.

References

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D., Dever, J., & Sosa, D. (2006). The conditional fallacy. Philosophical Review, 115(3), 273–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (2007). A defence of the Ramsey test. Mind, 116(461), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewka, G., Niemelä, I., & Truszczyński, M. (2008). Nonmonotonic reasoning. In F. V. Harmelen, V. Lifschitz, & B. Porter (Eds.), Handbook of knowledge representation. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1936a). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1936b). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 4, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S. (2008). Dispositional properties and counterfactual conditionals. Mind, 117, 795–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R. E. (2016). Sortals. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gundersen, L. B. (2002). In defence of the conditional account of dispositions. Synthese, 130(3), 389–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gundersen, L. B. (2004). Outline of a new semantics for counterfactuals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gundersen, L. B. (2018). In defense of a probability based semantics for counterfactuals. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(3), 538–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics. Theory change and database updating. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68(3), 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1997). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics that will be able to present itself as a science: With selections from the critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1982). Psychophysical supervenience. Philosophical Studies, 41(January), 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R., & Lewis, D. (1998). Defining intrinsic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 333–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2010). Ramsey test without triviality. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(1), 21–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(187), 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malzkorn, W. (2000). Realism, functionalism and the conditional analysis of dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 50(201), 452–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2007). A gradable approach to dispositions. Philosophical Quarterly, 57(226), 68–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind, 117(465), 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, D. (2009). Can intrinsic be defined using only broadly logical notions? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 647–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. P. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44(174), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (1996). Are dispositions reducible? The Philosophical Quarterly, 49(194), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rott, H. (2011). Reapproaching Ramsey: Conditionals and iterated belief change in the spirit of AGM. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 40, 155–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (pp. 98–112)., American philosophical quarterly monograph series, no. 2 Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straßer, C. (2014). Adaptive logics for defeasible reasoning. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2008). Dynamic epistemic logic. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B., & Marshall, D. (2017). Intrinsic vs. extrinsic properties. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2017 ed.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Holger Andreas.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andreas, H. An analysis of disposition concepts by the Ramsey test. Synthese 198, 11379–11397 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02794-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02794-x

Keywords

Navigation