Skip to main content
Log in

Are visuomotor representations cognitively penetrable? Biasing action-guiding vision

  • S.I.: Between Vision and Action
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Is action-guiding vision cognitively penetrable? More specifically, is the visual processing that guides our goal-directed actions sensitive to semantic information from cognitive states? This paper critically examines a recent family of arguments whose aim is to challenge a widespread and influential view in philosophy and cognitive science: the view that action-guiding vision is cognitively impenetrable. I argue, in response, that while there may very well be top–down causal influences on action-guiding vision, they should not be taken to be an instance of cognitive penetration. Assuming otherwise is to assign a computational role to the influencing states that they cannot perform. Although questions about cognitive penetrability are ultimately empirical, the issues addressed in this paper are largely philosophical. The discussion here highlights an important set of considerations that help better understand the relations between cognition, vision, and action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Jeannerod (2006) offers an excellent discussion of the notion of visuomotor representation, characterized as the segment of the global representation of fast and automatic actions, such as the action of grasping, which are largely dominated by their visual input (Jeannerod 2006, p. 5). For more recent discussion of the same notion, see e.g. Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2014), Ferretti (2016a, b, c), Mylopoulos and Pacherie (2017), Shepherd (2017) and Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti (forthcoming). This last paper carefully examines the notion of visuomotor representation and its relation to higher cognitive processing.

  2. Sometimes visual agnosics can actually recognise objects or even describe them through other senses, like sound or touch. Colours associated with certain objects can also help identification.

  3. I take perceptual judgments to be what in the literature is known as phenomenal (as opposed to epistemic) “seemings” (Brogaard 2013, 2014; Lyons 2005; Reiland 2014, 2015; Tucker 2010). They are mental episodes with a hybrid phenomenology: the products of interface systems between perception and cognition, sharing phenomenological aspects of both. See Toribio (2015, forthcoming) for a more detailed treatment of this notion.

  4. Visual agnostics like DF can nevertheless perceive colours and textures. Inasmuch as colours could get associated to certain objects, it would be correct to say that DF has a certain residual visual experience of objects. But only in that indirect sense.

  5. See, e.g., Clark (2001, 2009), Dijkerman et al. (2009), Ferretti (2016a, b, 2017, forthcoming), Jacob and Jeannerod (2003), Kozuch (2015), Mole (2009), Wu (2014) and Zipoli Caiani and Ferretti (2017).

  6. This may seem to imply that visuomotor representations are cognitively penetrable—inasmuch as they are influenced by the cognitive processes that drive the selection of types of action, even if in a mediated way. Yet, such cognitive processes do not causally determine the content of the relevant visuomotor representations. Their influence is of a different nature. The cognitive processes that drive the selection of types of action merely bias some already available visuomotor representations over other ones. That’s what I take Clark’s Experience-Based Selection hypothesis to suggest. See Sect. 5 below for further discussion of this crucial distinction.

  7. Jacob and Jeannerod (2003, p. 16) follow Clark in claiming that visual perception “is not geared towards the guidance and control of action. Rather, it is geared towards the ‘selection’ of objects that can be either goals for visually guided actions or food for thought”.

  8. For further empirical discussion of the dorsal stream bifurcation see e.g. Borghi and Riggio (2015), Chinellato and del Pobil (2016), Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia (2008) and Turella and Lingnau (2014). More philosophically oriented discussions of the same topic can be found here: Brogaard (2011b), Ferretti (2016a, b, c) and Gallese (2007).

  9. Just to be clear. The contention here is that, even if ventral representations are cognitively penetrable in the traditional sense captured by IEV, the top–down modulations from ventral to dorsal processes are of a different nature and do not amount to a case of cognitive penetrability—even indirectly. To postulate some indirect mechanism of cognitive penetration of the kind illustrated by e.g. Macpherson’s (2012) mechanism involving mental imagery would not be appropriate in this context. Partially because the content of the alleged penetrable and penetrating states is of a different kind so that ventral representations cannot not alter the information processed by dorsal mechanisms—something to be argued for in the final Section. Furthermore, such an indirect mechanism is (best) designed for capturing changes in phenomenal character, as in e.g. experiences involving perception of colour. Yet, the phenomenological issue plays a very little, if any, role in the discussion of visuomotor representations. I do not claim that they do not have any phenomenal character, but it is not the phenomenology of such action-guiding representations that is the central issue in the present discussion, but the details of the resulting motor actions.

  10. Burnston (2017) calls this the “diversity/specificity problem”. The problem arises whenever we appeal to the tokening of a cognitive state, which despite having a (propositional) content that might correspond to a range of sensorimotor representations with different particular contents, is meant to explain the tokening of a specific one through a unidirectional and deterministic process of content-causation.

  11. The issue here is similar to the one I raised in Sect. 4 against Nanay’s appeal to the existence of top–down influences from the ventral stream onto the ventro-dorsal and dorsal-dorsal regions in favour of the idea of cognitive penetrability of visuomotor representations.

References

  • Aglioti, S., Goodale, M., & DeSouza, J. F. X. (1995). Size contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5, 679–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arstila, V. (2016). Perceptual learning explains two candidates for cognitive penetration. Erkenntnis, 81(6), 1151–1172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binkosfski, F., & Buxbaum, L. J. (2013). Two action systems in the human brain. Brain and Language, 127(2), 222–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. M., & Riggio, L. (2015). Stable and variable affordances are both automatic and flexible. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 9(351), 32–47. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. (2008). Another look at the two visual systems hypothesis. Journal of Conscious Studies, 15, 35–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011a). Are there unconscious perceptual processes? Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 449–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011b). Conscious vision for action versus unconscious vision for action? Cognitive Science, 35(6), 1076–1104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2013). Phenomenal seemings and sensible dogmatism. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism (pp. 270–289). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014). Seeing as a mon-experiential mental state: The case from synesthesia and visual imagery. In R. Brown (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience (pp. 377–394). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D. (2016). Cognitive penetration and the cognition–perception interface. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1116-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D. (2017). Interface problems in the explanation of action. Philosophical Explorations, 20(2), 242–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D., & Cohen, J. (2015). Perceptual integration, modularity, and cognitive penetration. In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chinellato, E., & del Pobil, A. (2016). The visual neuroscience of robotic grasping. Achieving sensorimotor skills through dorsal-ventral stream integration. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, A., Borchers, S., & Himmelbach, M. (2013). Effects of pictorial cues on reaching depend on the distinctiveness of target objects. PLOS One, 8(1), e54230. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0054230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Visual experience and motor action: Are the bonds too tight? Philosophical Review, 110(4), 495–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2009). Perception, action, and experience: Unraveling the golden braid. Neuropsychologia, 47(6), 1460–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, K. (2014). Perceptual learning and the contents of perception. Erkenntnis, 79(6), 1407–1418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culham, J. C., Danckert, S. L., DeSouza, J. F. X., Gati, J. S., Menon, R. S., & Goodale, M. A. (2003). Visually guided grasping produces fMRI activation in dorsal but not ventral stream brain areas. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 180–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deroy, O. (2015). Multisensory perception and cognitive penetration. In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijkerman, H. C., McIntosh, R. D., Schindler, I., Nijboer, T. C. W., & Milner, A. D. (2009). Choosing between alternative wrist postures: Action planning needs perception. Neuropsyschologia, 47, 1476–1483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drayson, Z. (forthcoming). Direct perception and the predictive mind. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0999-x.

  • Dretske, A. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, R., Flanagan, J., & Lederman, S. (1999). The influence of visual illusions on grasp position. Experimental Brain Research, 125, 109–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016a). Through the forest of motor representations. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 177–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016b). Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99(S1), 112–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016c). Pictures, action properties and motor related effects. Synthese, 193(12), 3787–3817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2017). Two visual systems in Molyneux Subjects. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9533-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (forthcoming). The neural dynamics of seeing-in. Erkenntnis.

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2007). The “conscious” dorsal stream: Embodied simulation and its role in space and action conscious awareness. Psyche, 13(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A. (2011). Transforming vision into action. Vision Research, 51, 1567–1587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (2004). Sights unseen. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S., & Carey, D. P. (1991). A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature, 349, 154–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Wolf, M. (2009). Vision for action. In D. Dedrick & L. Trick (Eds.), Computation, cognition, and pylyshyn. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grill-Spector, K., Kushnir, T., Hendler, T., & Malach, R. (2000). The dynamics of object-selective activation correlate with recognition performance in humans. Nature Neuroscience, 3, 837–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the “space of reasons”. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2017). Priors in perception: Top–down modulation, bayesian perceptual learning rate, and prediction error minimization. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 75–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2005). Grasping and perceiving an object. In A. Brooks & K. Akins (Eds.), Cognition and the Brain. Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of seeing: The scope and limits of visual cognition. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition. What actions tell the self. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kozuch, B. (2015). Dislocation, not dissociation: The neuroanatomical argument against visual experience driving motor action. Mind and Language, 30(5), 572–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kravitz, D. J., Kadharbatcha, S., Saleem, S., Baker, C. I., & Mishkin, M. (2011). A new neural framework for visuospatial processing. Nature Neuroscience, 12, 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lima, C. F., Krishnan, S., & Scott, S. K. (2016). Roles of supplementary motor areas in auditory processing and auditory image. Trends in Neuroscience, 39(8), 527–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lupyan, G. (2015). Cognitive penetrability of perception in the age of prediction: Predictive systems are penetrable systems. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(4), 547–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (2005). Perceptual belief and nonexperiential looks. Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 237–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2015). Cognitive penetration and nonconceptual content. In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. (2017). The relationship between cognitive penetration and predictive coding. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 6–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B., & Wu, W. (2015). Cognitive penetration of the dorsal visual stream? In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 200–217). Oxford: OUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. D., & Lashleya, G. (2008). Matching boxes: Familiar size influences action programming. Neuropsychologia, 46, 2441–2444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D. (2008). Conscious and unconscious visual processing in the human brain. In L. Weiskrantz & M. Davies (Eds.), Frontiers of consciousness. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2008). Two visual systems re-visited. Neuropsychologia, 46, 774–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mole, C. (2009). Illusions, demonstratives and the zombie action hypothesis. Mind, 118, 995–1011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mylopoulos, M., & Pacherie, E. (2017). Intentions and motor representations: The interface challenge. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(2), 317–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013a). Between perception and action. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013b). Is action-guiding vision cognitively impenetrable? In Proceedings of the 35th annual conference of the cognitive science society (CogSci 2013) (pp. 1055–1060). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

  • Norman, J. (2002). Two visual systems and two theories of perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 73–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pisella, L., Gréa, H., Tilikete, H. C., Vighetto, A., Desmurget, M., Rode, G., et al. (2000). An ‘automatic pilot’ for the hand in human posterior parietal cortex: Toward reinterpreting optic ataxia. Nature Neuroscience, 3, 729–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2001). Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theory-ladenness of perception. Cognitive Science, 25, 423–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2005). Perceptual systems and a viable form of realism. In A. Raftopoulos (Ed.), Cognitive penetrability of perception. Nova Science: Hauppauge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2009). Cognition and perception: How do psychology and neural science inform philosophy?. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2017). Timing time: Why early vision is cognitively impenetrable. In Proceedings of the annual meeting of the cognitive science society (COGSI, 2017) (pp. 974–979).

  • Reiland, I. (2014). On experiencing high-level properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51, 177–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiland, I. (2015). Experience, seemings, and evidence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96, 510–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Matelli, M. (2003). Two different streams form the dorsal visual system: Anatomy and functions. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 146–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions, emotions, and experience. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossetti, Y., McIntosh, R. D., Revol, P., Pisella, L., Rode, G., Danckert, J., et al. (2005). Visually guided reaching: Bilateral posterior parietal lesions cause a switch from fast visuomotor to slow cognitive control. Neuropsychologia, 43, 162–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rossetti, Y., Pisella, L., & Vighetto, A. (2003). Optic ataxia revisited: Visually guided action versus immediate visuomotor control. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 171–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T., & McIntosh, R. D. (2010). Do we have independent visual streams for perception and action? Cognitive Neuroscience, 1(1), 52–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2017). Skilled action and the double life of intention. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, D. (2013). Cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophy Compass, 8(7), 646–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toribio, J. (2015). Visual experience: Rich but impenetrable. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0889-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toribio, J. (forthcoming). Visual categorization. In B. Glenney & J. F. Pereira da Silva (Eds.) The senses and the history of philosophy. Oxford: Routledge.

  • Tovée, M. J. (1994). How fast is the speed of thought? Neuronal Processing, 4(12), 1125–1127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, C. (2010). Why open-minded people should endorse dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 529–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turella, L., & Lingnau, A. (2014). Neural correlates of grasping. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. (2014). Against division: Consciousness, information and the visual systems. Mind and Language, 29(4), 383–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zipoli Caiani, S., & Ferretti, G. (2017). Semantic and pragmatic integration in vision for action. Consciousness and Cognition, 48, 40–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zipoli Caiani, S., & Ferretti, G. (forthcoming). Solving the interface problem without translation: The same format thesis. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research for this paper was supported by the MINECO (Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad) via research Grant MCINN FFI2014-51811, by the EC, Project: 675415—DIAPHORA, H2020-MSCA-ITN-2015, and by AGAUR (Agència de Gestió d’Ajuts Universitaris i de Recerca) via research Grant 2017-SGR-63.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Josefa Toribio.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Toribio, J. Are visuomotor representations cognitively penetrable? Biasing action-guiding vision. Synthese 198 (Suppl 17), 4163–4181 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1854-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1854-0

Keywords

Navigation