Skip to main content
Log in

Models, models, models: a deflationary view

  • S.I.: Modeling and Representation
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“Few terms are used in popular and scientific discourse more promiscuously than ‘model’.” (Goodman 1976, 171).

Abstract

In this essay, I first consider a popular view of models and modeling, the similarity view. Second, I contend that arguments for it fail and it suffers from what I call “Hughes’ worry.” Third, I offer a deflationary approach to models and modeling that avoids Hughes’ worry and shows how scientific representations are of apiece with other types of representations. Finally, I consider an objection that the similarity view can deal with approximations better than the deflationary view and show that this is not so.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Notoriously, Nelson Goodman argued that this proposal was “useless” (Goodman 1972). For any two objects, there is at least one set of which they are both members. Hence, the claim that similarity can be understood in terms of shared properties is universal and thus useless. The same is true if we say that a and b are more similar than c and d if, and only if, the former have more properties in common than the latter. For any two things, they will have exactly the same number properties in common. If the number of objects is n, then the number of shared properties is \(2^{n-2}\) and if the number of objects is infinite, the number of properties shared is infinite. But, Goodman assumes properties simply are sets. Many would argue this is false because there are sets for which there is no property (or as Lewis puts it, no “natural” property for every set) (Lewis 1983).

  2. Weisberg includes weights given to terms in the equation, but I ignore those for simplicity; i.e. including them would not make a difference to the arguments presented below.

  3. I am not making a historical claim of influence (though I think there is such a chain of influence). Rather, the type of view articulated by Hesse, Giere, and Weisberg are all developing similar thoughts on the matter. By emphasizing similarity, we are locating the model-world relation as one of analogy with positive (the intersections), negative (the differences), and neutral analogies. Additionally, scientists select the respects in which a model and target are thought to be similar.

  4. Chakravartty (2001) provides similar worries to the ones Hughes provided.

  5. As we will see, my own view is that concrete objects like inscriptions and utterances do represent the world. However, they don’t do so, or least don’t generally do so, by being similar to it. My name represents me but doesn’t do so by being similar to me.

  6. This is true even if we restrict our mathematics to that utilized in scientific theories insofar as they employ the real numbers. Hartry Field proposes a very large number of spacetime points and their relations as truthmakers for Newtonian classical mechanics. But these seem as recondite as pure mathematical objects. Likewise, Kitcher understands mathematical claims as made true by idealized constructors who group and permute. These constructors are also as recondite as the objects they replace.

  7. Of course, if mathematical realism is correct, one might correctly claim there are “Cambridge properties” they share; I am thinking about \(\pi \) and a beer right now. Both share the property being thought of by Jay. But those are not relevant to our purposes.

  8. Incidentally, I am inclined to think that Weisberg could reformulate his view to avoid Hughes’ worry. First, Weisberg’s models and target systems can be construed as relational structures. Second, we can formulate whatever morphism we like between an abstract object and a concrete one construed as relational structures. For example, sets A and B have the same cardinality, if there is a bijection from A to B. Two sets having the same cardinality is a property they can share regardless of the ontology of their members of the respective sets. This presumes that the model and target system have both been construed as mathematical objects. But now we have a problem of how a mathematical object can denote a concrete one. Bas van Fraassen (2010) has argued that we model phenomena of the world with data models or what he calls appearances. We then determine the fit of our theory to the appearances. That is, we evaluate how one model fits another another model. But you ask, how does something abstract like a mathematical structure represent something concrete? van Fraassen suggests we ignore this question since it engages in metaphysics. As a naturalist, I do not think we can reasonably avoid this question.

  9. Giere (1999, Chap. 6) utilizes psychological work on categorization involving prototypes and exemplars to understand how models form families with great insight. However, I would argue that the similarity view per se is not driven by findings in cognitive science.

  10. To be fair, one might ask what my own view of mathematics is. If pressed, I am inclined to adopt a structuralist philosophy of mathematics (Resnik 1997; Shapiro 1997). Mathematics describes patterns with positions. For example, the natural number system is the pattern shared by any system of objects that has a specific initial object and a successor relation that satisfies the induction principle. However, I am inclined to accept in rem rather than ante rem structuralism. Ante rem structuralists claim that mathematical structures exist independently of their exemplifications whereas the in re structuralist thinks that the structures exist in virtue of their exemplifications. A different way of putting the view is that there are no mathematical objects but only mathematical properties.

  11. The logistic model assumes a constant carrying capacity, linear density-dependence, no time lags, no migration, no genetic variation, or age structure in the population.

  12. My view is not that all successful models are approximately true. Rather, it is that models which are accurate representations are approximately true. Models can be successful and not approximately true provided that satisfy other scientifically relevant aims (Odenbaugh 2005).

References

  • Balaguer, M. (2001). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press on Demand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (1980). Optimal-design models and the strategy of model building in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 47(4), 532–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. (1982). What’s wrong with the received view of evolutionary theory? In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 1982, pp. 397–426). Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2006). There is no special problem about scientific representation. Theoria. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 21(1), 67–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1994). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2001). The semantic or model-theoretic view of theories and scientific realism. Synthese, 127(3), 325–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes, S. M. (1992). The importance of models in theorizing: A deflationary semantic view. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 1992, pp. 142–153). Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Dretske, F. (1997). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2004). True enough. Philosophical Issues, 14(1), 113–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2017). True enough. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2016). Science without numbers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Fiction and scientific representation. In R. Frigg & M. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention. Boston studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 262). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2009). Why scientific models should not be regarded as works of fiction. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modelling and idealisation (pp. 248–258). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1972). Seven strictures on similarity. In N. Goodman (Ed.), Problems and projects (pp. 23–32). Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1991). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1966). Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64, S325–S336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). The nature of mathematical knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1999). Pragmatic halos. Language, 75(3), 522–551.

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 16(3), 247–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality: Models, mathematics, and simulations. Oxford: Oxford Studies in Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2005). Idealized, inaccurate but successful: A pragmatic approach to evaluating models in theoretical ecology. Biology and Philosophy, 20(2–3), 231–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2011). True lies: Realism, robustness, and models. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1177–1188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2015). Semblance or similarity? Reflections on simulation and similarity. Biology & Philosophy, 30(2), 277–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perini, L. (2005a). The truth in pictures. Philosophy of Science, 72(1), 262–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perini, L. (2005b). Visual representations and confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 913–926.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Natural kinds. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–38). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. D. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford University Press.

  • Rosenberg, A. (1994). Instrumental biology, or the disunity of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. Oxford University Press.

  • Smith, P. (1998). Explaining chaos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1990). The representational theory of mind: An introduction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Scientific representation. Philosophy Compass, 5(1), 91–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2015). Deflationary representation, inference, and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 49, 36–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. Champaign: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. New York: Van Nostran Reinhold Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (2012). Modeling, truth, and philosophy. Metaphilosophy, 43(3), 257–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. (1989). The structure of biological theories. Albany: Suny Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe: Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (2010). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2012). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2015). Biology and philosophy symposium on simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Biology and Philosophy, 30(2), 299.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jay Odenbaugh.

Additional information

I thank Steve Downes, Catherine Elgin, Melissa Vergara Fernández, Jim Griesemer, Andoni Ibarra, Iñaki San Pedro, and Chris Pinnock for their help with this essay. Additionally, I thank two anonymous referees for the very helpful feedback.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Odenbaugh, J. Models, models, models: a deflationary view. Synthese 198 (Suppl 21), 1–16 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1665-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1665-8

Keywords

Navigation