Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic selectivity, historical threats, and the non-epistemic tenets of scientific realism

  • S.I.: New Thinking about Scientific Realism
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The scientific realism debate has now reached an entirely new level of sophistication. Faced with increasingly focused challenges, epistemic scientific realists have appropriately revised their basic meta-hypothesis that successful scientific theories are approximately true: they have emphasized criteria that render realism far more selective and, so, plausible. As a framework for discussion, I use what I take to be the most influential current variant of selective epistemic realism, deployment realism. Toward the identification of new case studies that challenge this form of realism, I break away from the standard list and look to the history of celestial mechanics, with an emphasis on twentieth century advances. I then articulate two purely deductive arguments that, I argue, properly capture the historical threat to realism. I contend that both the content and form of these novel challenges seriously threaten selective epistemic realism. I conclude on a positive note, however, arguing for selective realism at a higher level. Even in the face of threats to its epistemic tenet, scientific realism need not be rejected outright: concern with belief can be bracketed while nonetheless advocating core realist tenets. I show that, in contrast with epistemic deployment realism, a purely axiological scientific realism can account for key scientific practices made salient in my twentieth century case studies. And embracing the realists favored account of inference, inference to the best explanation, while pointing to a set of the most promising alternative selective realist meta-hypothesis, I show how testing the latter can be immensely valuable to our understanding of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In fact, a recent study suggests we can go back farther in astronomy: due to its largely unrecognized novel successes, the Ptolemaic model deserves much greater attention than realists and non-realists have tended to suppose (Carman and Díez 2015).

  2. Notably, some of these are, rather than highly localized and singular, properly seen as generalizations. See Lyons (2006) where, in agreement with Stathis Psillos (1999), I argue that even more credit must be attributed to those theoretical constituents deployed by scientists towards what come to be accepted generalizations.

  3. An anonymous referee has emphasized that I should express my modus tollens arguments (the second one will be discussed below), not as a proper construal of the historical argument, but as my own repurposing of the same sorts of examples for stronger forms of argument.

  4. Effectively, then, what is meant by the shorthand above that a constituent is “patently false” is that the constituent does not approximate by any reasonable stretch contemporary constituents that replaced it, requiring no specification of where the falsity lies. Also, because the sole justification for epistemic realism requires that the realist posit explains success—and insofar as that which does the explaining must make that which is explained “a matter of course,” as Peirce puts it—realists, despite temptation, cannot radically stretch their notion of approximate truth. See Lyons (2003, 2006, p. 556).

  5. In a recent critique, Psillos (2016) challenges only the first layer of my modus tollens on the grounds that it does not push us to look closely at the history of science. However, this critique, even if it were correct, wholly depends on neglecting the second layer, here explicitly flagged as such.

  6. I use “correlatively precise” here to capture two important factors: the first is the fact that such positive instances connect directly to the correlates themselves, with no intermediary guesswork; the second, is that, nonetheless, “correlatively precise” allows us to fully and appropriately avoid misleading talk of singular instances “confirming” the hypotheses.

  7. For instance, the differentiating correlate of the realist meta-hypothesis has a lower degree of empirical precision.

  8. There is one other way to construe this third point: increasing the evidence against the realist hypothesis permits stronger versions of this second modus tollens, where the content is changed but not the structure. For instance, in Premise 2 the “greater” evidence can shift to “far greater” and “vastly greater” evidence, and the Conclusion, 3, can change accordingly: it is not the case that we are, e.g., “even close to being justified” “have any chance of being justified,” etc., in believing the realist’s meta-hypothesis, given the evidence.

  9. Or at least the first layer of the first modus tollens.

  10. This position promotes the quest for truth without claiming to possess or approximate it. Elsewhere, I’ve dubbed this position, ’Socratic scientific realism’ (Lyons 2015).

  11. For the details of this postulate and its empirically testable consequences, see my (2005).

  12. For instance, one issue that naturally arises is whether construing science as seeking an epistemically utopian goal—as I allow truth, and even an increase in experientially concretized truth, to be—sacrifices one’s ability to construe science as a rational endeavor. Although I set this topic to the side here, I argue in detail in my (2005 and 2011) that it does not.

  13. On the axiological realist account, those components in the accepted system are likewise deployed in the service of inquiry, but, in contrast, remain candidates for truth and hence for its experiential concretization.

  14. Likewise for Newton after his pre-Principia (1684) arrival at his law of universal gravitation mentioned above.

  15. That is, their explicit belief commitments stand in contradiction with any lip-service to “idealizations” they might offer unreflectively.

  16. Though I offer here no articulation of the nature of such inference, the importance of Lipton ’s (2004) is undiminished by its incompleteness.

  17. These are articulated only roughly and only listed roughly in the order of their introduction to the debate.

  18. Since some of these retention hypotheses will pick out deeper constituents while others will pick out fewer constituents, comparisons of logical strength are hardly more obvious than their as-yet untested empirical strength; nonetheless, in want of an example ordering, I offer this illustrative prioritization based on rough conjectures regarding logical strength. Admittedly, it will be surprising that Ramsey sentence retention lands so low on the priority ranking, but see my (forthcoming).

References

  • Carman, C., & Díez, J. (2015). Did Ptolemy make novel predictions? Launching Ptolemaic astronomy into the scientific realism debate. Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 52, 20–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (1993). What’s right the miracles argument: Establishing a taxonomy of natural kinds. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 24(3), 391–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Science, 29, 391–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Sitter, W. (1917). On Einstein’s theory of gravitation, and its astronomical consequences. Third paper. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, 78, 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Sitter, W. (1930). Meeting of the Royal Astronomical Society, Friday, 1930, May 9. The Observatory, 53(673), 161–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sitter, W. (1930b). On the magnitudes, diameters and distances of the extragalactic nebulae, and their apparent radial velocities. Bulletin of the Astronomical Institutes of the Netherlands, 5, 157–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sitter, W. (1932). Kosmos: A course of six lectures on the development of our insight into the structure of the universe. Delivered for the Lowell Institute in Boston, in November 1931, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

  • Eddington, A. S. (1923). Mathematical theory of general relativity. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. S. (1930a). January 10 meeting of the Royal Astronomical Society. The Observatory, 53, 33–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. S. (1930). Meeting of the Royal Astronomical Society, Friday, 1930, May 9. The Observatory, 53(673), 161–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. (1933). Spherical space. In T. Ferris (Ed.), World treasury of physics, astronomy, and mathematics. New York: Back Bay Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein A. (1916). (1920) Relativity: The special and general theory (3rd ed.) (R. W. Lawson, Trans.). New York: Henry Holt and Company.

  • Einstein, A. (1917a). Cosmological considerations arising from the general theory of relativity. In The collected papers of Albert Einstein, Doc 43 volume 6: The Berlin years: Correspondence, 1914–1918 (English translation supplement), pp. 421–432

  • Einstein, A. (1917b). Doc 351 Einstein to de Sitter, June 17. In The collected papers of Albert Einstein, volume 8: The Berlin years: Writings, 1914–1918 (English translation supplement), p. 340.

  • French, S. (1998). On the withering away of physical objects. In E. Castellani (Ed.), Interpreting bodies: Classical and quantum objects in modern physics (pp. 93–113). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harker, D. (2013). How to split a theory: Defending selective realism and convergence without proximity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(1), 79–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S. W., & Ellis, G. F. R. (1975). The large scale structure of space-time. Cambridge monographs on mathematical physics. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubble, E. (1929). A relation between distance and radial velocity among extra-galactic nebulae. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 15, 168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubble, E. (1931). Letter, Hubble to de Sitter 23 Sept 1931, Huntington Library; quoted in Smith, 1979, pg. 151, The Origins of the Velocity-Distance Relation. Journal for the History of Astronomy, 10, 133–164.

  • Kerr, R. (1963). Gravitational field of a spinning mass as an example of algebraically special metrics. Physical Review Letters, 11(5), 237–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruskal, M. D. (1960). Maximal extension of Schwarzschild metric. Physical Review, 119, 1743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., & with Spurrett, D., & Collier, J., (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2003). Explaining the success of a scientific theory. Philosophy of Science, 70, 891–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2005). Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63, 167–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2006). Scientific realism and the strategema de divide et impera. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 537–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. (2011). The problem of deep competitors and the pursuit of unknowable truths. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(2), 317–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, T. D. (2015). Scientific realism. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199368815.013.30.

  • Lyons, T. (forthcoming). Structural realism versus deployment realism: A comparative evaluation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.

  • Michell, J. (1784). “On the means of discovering the distance, magnitude,&c. of the fixed stars, in consequence of the diminution of the velocity of their light.” In a Letter to Henry Cavendish. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 74, 35–57.

  • Newton, I. (1684). De motu corporum in gyrum. In The preliminary manuscripts for Isaac Newton’s 1687 Principia, 1684–1686 (facsimiles), 1989. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Translated in 2008. The Mathematical Papers of Isaac Newton: Volume 6, Edited by DT Whiteside).

  • Peters, D. (2014). What elements of successful scientific theories are the correct targets for ‘selective’ scientific realism? Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 377–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2016). From the evidence of history to the history of evidence: Re-thinking the pessimistic X-duction. In Presented Feb 19 2016 at The History of Science and Contemporary Scientific Realism Conference, Indiana University-Purdue University Indianapolis.

  • Ruttkamp-Bloem, E. (2011). Interactive realism. South African Journal of Philosophy, 30(1), 41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, K. (1916a). On the gravitational field of a point-mass, according to Einstein’s Theory. Translated vol. 1, 2008 The Journal for General Relativity, Gravitation and Cosmology. Translated from the German in 2008 by Larissa Borissova and Dmitri Rabounski.

  • Schwarzschild, K. (1916b). On the gravitational field of a sphere of incompressible liquid, according to Einstein’s Theory. Translated vol. 1, 2008 The Journal for General Relativity, Gravitation and Cosmology. Translated from the German in 2008 by Larissa Borissova and Dmitri Rabounski

  • Szekeres, G. (1960). On the singularities of a Riemannian manifold. Publicationes Mathematicae Debrecen, 7, 285–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, P. (2013). Confrontation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 80, 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Soldner, J. G. (1801). On the deviation of a light ray from its motion along a straight line through the attraction of a celestial body which it passes close by”, in Jaki, S. (1978) Johann Georg von Soldner and the gravitational bending of light, with an English translation of his essay on it published in 1801. Foundations of Physics, 8, 927–950.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J., (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124. (Reprinted from The philosophy of science, pp. 139–165, by D. Papineau, Ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press).

  • Worrall, J. (2011). Underdetermination, realism and empirical equivalence. Synthese, 180, 157–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J., & Zahar, E. (2001). Ramsification and structural realism. Appendix in E. Zahar (Ed.), Poincaré’s philosophy: From conventionalism to phenomenology (pp. 236–251). La Salle: Open Court.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Research for this paper was supported by the AHRC, UK, Grant: Contemporary Scientific Realism and the History of Science. I thank three anonymous referees for their helpful feedback. For conversations and correspondence relevant to the topics in this paper, I am indebted to many including Anjan Chakravartty, Mathias Egg, Steven French, David Harker, James Ladyman, Kerry McKenzie, Tom Pashby, Dean Peters, Emma Ruttkamp-Bloem, Stathis Psillos, and Peter Vickers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy D. Lyons.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lyons, T.D. Epistemic selectivity, historical threats, and the non-epistemic tenets of scientific realism. Synthese 194, 3203–3219 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1103-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1103-3

Keywords

Navigation