Skip to main content
Log in

Renouncing Human Hubris and Reeducating Commonsense

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The thesis of this paper is that we are now in the early stage of a revolution even more transformative than the Copernican. That great upheaval brought about a radical shift in the way men and women conceptualized their place in the universe. The revolution now under way entails a sea change in the way we think about ourselves in relation to the planet we inhabit—itself not a simple matter—and also the reeducation of our attitudes, values, feelings, emotions, patterns of behavior, and modes of living. All of which is to say that it requires us to become very different people from the ones we now are.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kuhn (1957, 2).

  2. Ibid. 190.

  3. Ibid. 199.

  4. Ibid. 44.

  5. Wilson (2012, 49).

  6. Wilson (2014, 50).

  7. Ibid. 50.

  8. Ibid. 51.

  9. Ibid. 51.

  10. Ibid. 82.

  11. Ibid. 83.

  12. Ibid. 84.

  13. Ibid. 84.

  14. Ibid. 92.

  15. On this last point see Whitehead and Rendell (2015, 61–63).

  16. Whitehead and Rendell, Cultural Lives, 21.

  17. See, e.g., Kolbert (2014).

  18. McKibben (2006, 51).

  19. The climate change we have brought about also appears to be responsible for the increasing number of devastating boreal wild fires (New York Times, 5/11/16).

  20. Carson (1962, 297).

  21. Wilson (1996, 191).

  22. L’Osservatore Romano, Weekly Edition in English Jan. 24, 2001, p. 11.

  23. Encyclical Letter Laudato Si’ of the Holy Father Francis, May 2015.

  24. Mckibben, End, 55.

  25. According to Ridley (2003), “defining human uniqueness has been a cottage industry for philosophers for centuries.”

  26. I use the male pronoun deliberately here.

  27. See, e.g. Ridley, Agile; McKibben, End.

  28. McKibben, End, 56.

  29. As anthropologist Ortner (1974, 67–88) once put it.

  30. See McKibben, End, however, for a discussion of some of the possibilities.

  31. Rousseau (1979 (1762), 38).

  32. Dewey (1961 (1916), 4).

  33. Illich (1970).

  34. Rousseau, Emile, 64.

  35. Ridley (2000, 221).

  36. Pinker (1994, 4).

  37. Pinker, Language, 5.

  38. Pinker (2002, 53).

  39. Ridley, Genome, 94.

  40. For a full account of Victor, see Lane (1979).

  41. Rousseau, Emile, 61.

  42. In note (iii) to his Discourse on the Origins and Foundations of Inequality among Men, written in 1754, Rousseau discusses some earlier “wild children.” See Roussseau (2011 (1754)).

  43. Ridley, Genome, 221.

  44. Pinker, Language, 4.

  45. Peters (1972, 1–23).

  46. Pinker, Blank, 24.

  47. Ridley, Agile, 3.

  48. Ibid. 81.

  49. Ibid. 81.

  50. Barker (2015).

  51. Oyama (2000).

  52. Ibid. 40.

  53. Ridley, Agile, 146.

  54. Ibid. 263.

  55. Stein (1980).

  56. See, e.g., Wilson, Search and Social Conquest; Whitehead and Rendell, Cultural Lives.

  57. In what follows I restrict myself to human learning and leave open the question of whether my points apply to the learning of other species.

  58. E.g., Whitehead and Rendell, Cultural Lives, 5.

  59. Martin (2002). Cultural Miseducation.

  60. A culture’s capital clearly falls under my heading of cultural assets. Whether the concept of cultural capital as usually understood embraces all of a culture’s assets or merely a subset I leave to others to decide.

  61. See Mannheim’s (1952, 276–320) formulation of the sociological problem of generations.

  62. Dawkins (1976).

  63. And then developed by Dennett (1995), and elaborated further by Blackmore (1999).

  64. Brooks (2014).

  65. E.g. Pinker (2011).

  66. Wilson, Social Conquest, Ch. 7.

  67. Ibid. 59.

  68. Wilson, Social, 194.

  69. Martin (2002).

  70. Mayer (2016) identifies many of the secret transmitters of anti-climate change messages; describes their methodologies—including the death threats; and estimates their impact.

  71. Tommasini (2016).

  72. Breitman (2016).

  73. De Waal writes that sheep “remember one another’s faces” and investigators speculate that “a flock which to us looks like an anonymous mass, is in fact quite differentiated.” See De Waal (2016, 72).

  74. See De Waal, Smart Enough, for discussions of the “umwelt” of other organisms.

  75. And also from the consciousness-raising groups of second wave feminism.

  76. Julia Roberts, October 5, 2014, Conservation International.

References

  • Barker, Gillian. 2015. Beyond fatalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore, Susan. 1999. The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breitman, Patti. March 29, 2016. All we like sheep. The New York Times, A24.

  • Brooks, David. July 11, 2014. Baseball or soccer? The New York Times, A25.

  • Carson, Rachel. 1962. Silent spring. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, Richard. 1976. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1995. Darwin’s dangerous idea. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, Frans. 2016. Are we smart enough to know how smart animals are? New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1961 (1916). Democracy and education. New York: Macmillan.

  • Illich, Ivan. 1970. Deschooling society. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolbert, Elizabeth. 2014. The sixth extinction. New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. 1957. The copernican revolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, Harlan. 1979. The wild boy of averyron. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim, Karl. 1952. The problem of generations. In Essays in the sociology of knowledge, ed. Paul Keckskemti, 276–329. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Jane Roland. 2002. Cultural miseducation. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Jane Roland. 2007. Educational metamorphoses. Latham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Martin, Jane Roland. 2011. Education reconfigured. New York: Routledge.

  • Mayer, Jane. 2016. Dark money. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKibben, Bill. 2006. The end of nature. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortner, Sherry. 1974. Is female to male as nature is to culture? In Women, culture & society, ed. Michelle Zimbalist Rosaldo, and Louise Lamphere, 67–88. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, Susan. 2000. The ontogeny of information, 2nd ed. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R.S. 1972. Education and the educated man. In A critique of current educational aims, ed. R.F. Dearden, Paul H. Hirst, and R.S. Peters, 1–23. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, Steven. 1994. The language instinct. New York: Harper.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, Steven. 2002. The blank slate. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, Steven. 2011. The better angels of our nature. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, Matt. 2000. Genome. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, Matt. 2003. The agile gene. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roussseau, Jean-Jacques. 2011. Discourse on the origins and foundations of inequality among men. In The basic political writings, second edition, ed. Donald A. Cress, 93–120. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1979 (1762). Emile. New York: Basic Books.

  • Stein, Jess. (Ed.). 1980. The random house dictionary. New York: Ballantine Books.

  • Tommasini, Anthony. March 23, 2016. Review: ‘De Materie,’ of Matter, spirit, and sheep. The New York Times, A1.

  • Whitehead, Hal, and Luke Rendell. 2015. The cultural lives of whales and dolphins. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Edward O. 1996. Search of nature. Washington, DC: Island Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Edward O. 2012. The social conquest of the earth. New York: Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Edward O. 2014. The meaning of human existence. New York: Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jane Roland Martin.

Additional information

I wish to thank Ann Diller, Susan Franzosa, Barbara Houston, Beebe Nelson, Jennifer Radden, E.O. Wilson, and the editors of this special issue for helpful comments on an early draft of this essay.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Martin, J. Renouncing Human Hubris and Reeducating Commonsense. Stud Philos Educ 36, 283–298 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-016-9559-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-016-9559-7

Keywords

Navigation