Skip to main content
Log in

Higher Education, Knowledge for Its Own Sake, and an African Moral Theory

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I seek to answer the question of whether publicly funded higher education ought to aim intrinsically to promote certain kinds of “blue-sky” knowledge, knowledge that is unlikely to result in “tangible” or “concrete” social benefits such as health, wealth and liberty. I approach this question in light of an African moral theory, which contrasts with dominant Western philosophies and has not yet been applied to pedagogical issues. According to this communitarian theory, grounded on salient sub-Saharan beliefs and practices, actions are right insofar as they respect relationships in which people both share a way of life, or identify with one another, and care for others’ quality of life, or are in solidarity with each other. I argue that while considerations of identity and solidarity each provide some reason for a state university to pursue blue-sky knowledge as a final end, they do not provide conclusive reason for it to do so. I abstain from drawing any further conclusion about whether this provides reason to reject the Afro-communitarian moral theory or the intuition that blue-sky knowledge is a proper final end of public higher education. I do point out, however, that the dominant Western moral theories on the face of it do no better than the African one at accounting for this intuition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Stanley Fish’s (2008a, b) recent reflection on the value of the humanities. As I point out below, however, there is much natural scientific reflection that appears to be equally ‘useless’.

  2. In other work I cite more than 50 books, chapters and articles that address the final ends of Africanist higher education (Metz 2009a); only the handful of authors discussed below take up the issue of knowledge for its own sake.

  3. Touré (1963), Nyerere (1964), Yesufu (1973), Makgoba (1998), Dowling and Seepe (2003), Mthembu (2004), Adams (2005, p. 144), Nabudere (2006). Although the following do not explicitly reject knowledge for its own sake, their heavy emphasis on the need for knowledge to be relevant suggests that they would: Mazrui (1978), Lumumba-Kasongo (2000), Lebakeng (2004).

  4. Beyond the rejections of the very concept of knowledge for its own sake, rebutted in the previous section.

  5. The rest of this paragraph invokes some statements from Metz (2009a, p. 191).

  6. And perhaps even to support them in doing so. If the final end of a state university did not include blue-sky knowledge, then an individual academic would do wrong if she pursued it with university resources. However, it would not follow that an administrator would be doing wrong if he actively supported this researcher’s blue-sky projects, so long as it were known to be a necessary part of a plan to do what is likely to realize the university’s final ends in the long run. To think otherwise is to neglect the tricky, but definitive, role that institutional factors can play in moral choice.

  7. The next several paragraphs borrow from Metz (2009a, pp. 182–184, 2009b, pp. 339–342).

  8. This conception of what makes something African also implies that there could be accounts of morality besides the one I propose below that are also worthy of the title (for two rivals, see Wiredu 1992a; Gyekye 1997, pp. 35–76).

  9. For classic statements of these ubiquitous phrases, see Mbiti (1969, pp. 108–109), Menkiti (1979).

  10. For yet another, representative comment, consider these remarks about the practices of the G/wi people of Botswana: ‘(T)here was another value being pursued, namely the establishing and maintaining of harmonious relationships. Again and again in discussion and in general conversation this stood out as a desired and enjoyed end in itself, often as the ultimate rationale for action’ (Silberbauer 1991, p. 20).

  11. Elsewhere I have spelled out many of the following recurrent facets of sub-Saharan thought and practice, and argued that the present moral principle captures them best (Metz 2007a, b).

  12. This sort of case is normally attributed to John Rawls (1971, p. 432).

  13. Mbiti, the influential scholar of African thought, makes this point (1969), and is echoed by others (e.g., Menkiti 1979; Dzobo 1992, p. 229). Indeed, the standard objection to African ethics is that it grants too much weight to tradition and not enough to individual liberty, on which see Louw (2001, pp. 19–26).

  14. The field of analytical ethics has by and large followed Samuel Scheffler’s (1982) terminology here.

  15. For the most explicit and thorough discussion, see Gyekye (1997, pp. 69–75). An inability to go beyond the call of duty with regard to aiding others is probably implicit in Wiredu’s (1992a) suggestion that the golden rule is central to sub-Saharan morality; treating others the way you would like to be treated entails helping them an awful lot, supposing you would like to be helped an awful lot.

  16. Quite often, the intuition is not thoroughly defended by its most ardent supporters in the West. For example, one encounters little argument for (and virtually no moral theoretic defence of) the claim that a public university ought to pursue knowledge for its own sake in Husserl (1935), Oakeshott (1950), Wolff (1969, pp. 7–8) and Pelikan (1992, pp. 32–43).

  17. Suppose a morally upright, theoretical genius needed a new liver to survive, and the only one available were housed in the body of a malevolent, not-so-bright undergraduate student. Would the ethical imperative to promote human excellence permit the scholar’s university to forcibly extract the liver? Of course, doing so might well constitute a vice, but might that, on a eudaimonist ethic, be outweighed by the imperative to realize superlative intellectual virtue?

References

  • Adams, N. D. (2005). Reshaping some of the conceptual orientations of lifelong learning in South Africa through an African philosophy of education. In Y. Waghid (Ed.), African(a) philosophy of education: Reconstructions and deconstructions (pp. 140–163). Department of Education Policy Studies: Stellenbosch University.

  • Biko, S. (1971). Some African cultural concepts. Reprinted in S. Biko, I write what I like (pp. 44–53). Johannesburg: Picador Africa, 2004.

  • Dowling, D., & Seepe, S. (2003). Towards a responsive curriculum. In P. Naudé & N. Cloete (Eds.), A tale of three countries: Social sciences curriculum transformations in Southern Africa (pp. 41–53). Lansdowne: Juta and Co Pty Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dzobo, N. K. (1992). Values in a changing society: Man, ancestors and God. In K. Wiredu & K. Gyekye (Eds.), Person and community: Ghanaian philosophical studies (pp. 223–240). Washington, DC: The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, S. (2008a, January 6). Will the humanities save us? New York Times. http://fish.blogs.nytimes.com/2008/01/06/will-the-humanities-save-us/. Accessed 24 June 2009.

  • Fish, S. (2008b, January 13). The uses of the humanities, part two. New York Times. http://fish.blogs.nytimes.com/2008/01/13/the-uses-of-the-humanities-part-two/. Accessed 24 June 2009.

  • Gyekye, K. (1997). Tradition and modernity: Philosophical reflections on the African experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1935). Philosophy and the crisis of European man (trans: Lauer, Q.). http://www.users.cloud9.net/~bradmcc/husserl_philcris.html. Accessed 30 Apr 2009.

  • Lebakeng, T. (2004). Towards a relevant higher education epistemology. In S. Seepe (Ed.), Towards an African identity of higher education (pp. 109–119). Pretoria: Vista University and Skotaville Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louw, D. (2001). Ubuntu and the challenges of multiculturalism in post-apartheid South Africa. Quest, 15(1–2), 15–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumumba-Kasongo, T. (2000). Rethinking educational paradigms in Africa: Imperatives for social progress in the new millennium. In P. Higgs et al. (Eds.), African voices in education (pp. 139–157). Lansdowne: Juta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makgoba, M. W. (1998). South African universities in transformation: An opportunity to Africanise education. In S. Seepe (Ed.), Black perspective(s) on tertiary institutional transformation (pp. 42–62). Florida Hills: Vivlia Publishers and the University of Venda.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazrui, A. (1978). Political values and the educated class in Africa. London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mbiti, J. (1969). African religions and philosophy. Oxford: Heinemann Educational Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, I. (1979). Person and community in African traditional thought. Reprinted in R. Wright (Ed.), African philosophy: An introduction, 3rd ed. (pp. 171–181). New York: University Press of America, 1984.

  • Metz, T. (2007a). Toward an African moral theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 15(3), 321–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2007b). The motivation for ‘Toward an African moral theory’. South African Journal of Philosophy, 26(4), 331–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2009a). The final ends of higher education in light of an African moral theory. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 43(2), 179–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2009b). African moral theory and public governance. In M. F. Murove (Ed.), African ethics: An anthology of comparative and applied ethics (pp. 335–356). Pietermaritzburg: University of KwaZulu-Natal Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mthembu, T. (2004). Creating a niche in internationalization for (South) African higher education institutions. In S. Seepe (Ed.), Towards an African identity of higher education (pp. 77–92). Pretoria: Vista University and Skotaville Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nabudere, D. (2006). Towards an Afrokology of knowledge production and African regeneration. International Journal of African Renaissance Studies, 1(1), 7–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, J. (1852). The idea of the university. http://www.newmanreader.org/works/idea/. Accessed 30 Apr 2009.

  • Nyerere, J. (1964). An address by the president of the Republic of Tanganyika at the inauguration of the University of East Africa. Reprinted in L. G. Cowan et al. (Eds.), Education and nation-building in Africa (pp. 309–313). London: Pall Mall Press, 1965.

  • Oakeshott, M. (1950). The idea of a university. Reprinted in M. Oakeshott, The voice of liberal learning (pp. 105–118). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2001.

  • Pelikan, J. (1992). The idea of the university: A reexamination. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (1982). The rejection of consequentialism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberbauer, G. (1991). Ethics in small-scale societies. In P. Singer (Ed.), A companion to ethics (pp. 14–28). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Touré, S. (1963). Education and social progress. Reprinted in L. G. Cowan et al. (Eds.), Education and nation-building in Africa (pp. 125–139). London: Pall Mall Press, 1965.

  • Tutu, D. (1999). No future without forgiveness. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhoef, H., & Michel, C. (1997). Studying morality within the African context. Journal of Moral Education, 26(4), 389–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wandira, A. (1977). The African university in development. Johannesburg: Ravan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (1992a). Moral foundations of an African culture. In K. Wiredu & K. Gyekye (Eds.), Person and community: Ghanaian philosophical studies (pp. 193–206). Washington, DC: The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (1992b). The African concept of personhood. In H. E. Flack & E. E. Pellegrino (Eds.), African–American perspectives on biomedical ethics (pp. 104–117). Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, R. P. (1969). The ideal of the university. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yesufu, T. M. (1973). The role and priorities of the university in development. In T. M. Yesufu (Ed.), Creating the African university (pp. 37–45). Ibadan: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This article has been improved as a result of: discussion with Pedro Tabensky and the students in his African philosophy class at Rhodes University; written comments from Stephen Kershnar and Ward Jones; questions from members of the African Moral Education Network at their inaugural meeting in Cape Town and from participants in a staff seminar sponsored by the University of the Witwatersrand School of Education; and reports received from two thoughtful, anonymous referees for this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thaddeus Metz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Metz, T. Higher Education, Knowledge for Its Own Sake, and an African Moral Theory. Stud Philos Educ 28, 517–536 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-009-9141-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-009-9141-7

Keywords

Navigation