Pavel Aleksandrovich Florensky (1882–1937) is gradually being recognised as one of the most remarkable figures of twentieth-century intellectual history. Mathematics, engineering, biology, philosophy, linguistics, art history, aesthetics and theology were all subject areas in which Florensky excelled.Footnote 26 The origins of Pavel Florensky’s antinomism can be traced back to a lecture he gave in 1908, “The Cosmological Antinomies of Immanuel Kant” (Florensky 1996c). Florensky had for a long time expressed an intuitive repulsion to Kantian philosophy. He writes: “The Kantian separation of noumena and phenomena (even when I had no suspicion of the existence of any one of these terms: ‘Kantian’, ‘separation’, ‘noumena’ and ‘phenomena’) I rejected with all my being” (Florensky 2010, p. 9). Indeed, such a separation doesn’t agree with the Russian thinker’s conviction of the real and accessible extra-conceptual world. What Florensky recognised as “the main intuition of the human race” is that “I live in the world and with the world, which implies the being, and the real being, both of me, the human, and of that what is outside me, what exists separately, and more exactly, independently of human consciousness” (Florensky 1996b, p. 283).
In his lecture on Kant, Florensky examines the antinomies found in The Critique of Pure Reason. Florensky first expresses great admiration for Kant’s sensitivity for antinomy: “The idea of the possibility of antinomies of reason is the deepest and most fruitful of all Kant’s ideas” (Florensky 1996c, p. 28). He then went on, however, to claim that Kant’s famous antinomies are not true antinomies, because they can be reduced to mere “functions of consciousness” (Florensky 1996c, p. 27). Kant’s antinomies differ from Florensky’s, since for Kant the antinomy marked the boundary of experience, a frustrating limit to our knowledge, stopping us short of the apprehension of a hidden noumenal truth. As Florensky writes, “At the heart of Kant’s deductions lies his differentiation between the thing-in-itself and the phenomena” (Florensky 1996c, p. 27). The antinomies mark the end of the phenomenal and the start of the noumenal. This means that Kant’s antinomies are already conditioned by a certain epistemology. For Florensky, however, antimony is the unconditioned objective Truth itself. This is a difficult notion which must be elucidated by a closer analysis of Florensky’s monumental work, The Pillar and Ground of the Truth.
Despite its many theological critiques,Footnote 27The Pillar has been hailed as “the most important sustained inquiry into the theology of the Christian Trinity since Chalcedon” (Foltz 2013, p. 6), containing a nuanced and rich philosophical defence of Trinitarian dogma. In the early chapters of the book, Florensky formulates a key distinction between rationality (rassudok) and reason (razum), to which he subordinates previous philosophical distinctions such as διάνοια/νοῦς, ratio/intellectus, and Verstand/Vernunft. Horizontal antinomism characterises the former, while vertical antinomism belongs to the latter. A bold attempt is made to pass from the former to the latter by showing that truth in and of itself is an antinomy (which would make vertical antinomic dogmas necessarily true in virtue of their contradictoriness). This is initially formulated in a turn to symbolic logic, known as the “formal logical theory of antinomy” (Florensky 1914, p. 148).Footnote 28
The ‘Logical’ Theory of Antinomy
Although this theory (as presented in Letter Six of The Pillar, ‘Contradiction’) is now widely discredited, it provides an introduction to the author’s more convincing antinomy between the laws of Identity and Sufficient Reason. Florensky claims that since any thesis presupposes its antithesis (and vice versa) we should not be satisfied with choosing between either thesis or antithesis, but rather should paradoxically accept both the thesis and the antithesis. In other words, any truth presupposes and includes within itself the potential of its negation, and is thus one with its negation.Footnote 29 Here, Florensky has already departed from Solov’ev for whom “the Truth”, as all-unity, “cannot contradict itself” (Solov’ev 1948a, b, p. 84). For Florensky, however, “symbolic logic explains and even justifies a paradoxical method of reasoning” (Florensky 1914, p. 150).Footnote 30 Following the Italian mathematician Giovanni Vailati (1863–1909), Florensky asserts that “the negative of a proposition implies the proposition that it negates” (Florensky 1914, p. 150).Footnote 31
-
(1)
(¬p → p) → p
Florensky then deduces the opposite formula. (That a thesis entails its antithesis):
-
(2)
(p → ¬p) → ¬p
Florensky then proves these respective formulas, which are in fact simple tautologies of classical logic. No real logical conclusion can thus be drawn from the initial opposition, since the tautologies need not have any relation with one another. As Pawel Rojek confirms, “The logical argument is plainly obsolete. Florensky simply proved the principle of reductio ad absurdum in two different forms. The principles are tautologies of propositional calculus and together cannot form a contradiction” (Rojek 2019, p. 124). Although there are obvious problems with Florensky’s reasoning here, we should not underestimate his understanding of symbolic logic. As Biriukov observes, “Although he mastered logical technique, he did not really think through the problem of how to combine the logical calculus with his own theological position” (Biriukov 2010, p. 55). Even though Florensky’s efforts to understand all truths as inherently paradoxical seems to be a failure, this does not invalidate the fact that there might be some necessary logical contradictions. The real question, however, is whether these contradictions are where Florensky says they are, that is, in the antinomy of the two laws (see 2.3) and in the doctrines of the Trinity and the incarnation (see 2.6). In order to accept these contradictions, Florensky would first have us accept that there can be such a thing as a “rationally obligatory” contradiction.
In this respect Florensky aligns himself with dialetheism, or “two-truth logic”, which has over the past 20 years gained an increasingly dominant presence in contemporary philosophy, maintaining that the Law of Non-Contradiction need not be universally necessary for a coherent logic. Graham Priest, the most prominent figure of the movement, has developed such a paraconsistent logic which famously rejects Frege’s insistence that there can be only two truth values,Footnote 32 by allowing for a third value: “true and false”. For this reason, paraconsistency is quite foreign to the Western philosophical community. The first problem with accepting a paraconsistent antinomism like Florensky’s (or any of the following thinkers) is that, according to classical logic, it leaves open the possibility of accepting any contradiction, however obscure. Priest gives the example: “I am a fried egg” and “I am not a fried egg” (Priest 2004, p. 23). This is called the principle of explosion, or: Ex contradictione quodlibet. Priest however makes a sharp distinction between believing in some contradictions, and believing all contradictions. He defends, for example, some contradictions which are “rationally obligatory”, such as the Liar Paradox (‘This sentence is false’) (Priest 2004, p. 23). Priest juxtaposes classical logic with a paraconsistent logic in which truth and falsity by interpretation are no longer “exclusive and exhaustive” but have significant overlap (Priest 2004, p. 26), as he represents in the following diagrams:
Four Possible Readings of Florensky’s Antinomism
Reading Florensky paraconsistently assumes that the above schema is universal and thus antinomies are ubiquitous. This means antinomies are located both on the side of rationality (the horizontal) and higher reason (the vertical) and that, as Rojek writes, “Even in the state of enlightenment, the truths of religion remain inconsistent, only the attitude to them is changed” (Rojek 2019, p. 131). However, three other tendencies have emerged in Florensky scholarship. Some have claimed that horizontal rationality doesn’t contain antinomies because it instinctively and perpetually solves them, and it is only the world of vertical reason (revelation) where antinomies appear. This is known as an L-inconsistent reading (the ‘L’ stands for limit). In other words, there are only vertical antinomies, and no horizontal ones. This reading was championed by Viacheslav Moiseev (2001, pp. 329–39).Footnote 33 Moiseev understands antinomies as “the limits of the infinite sequences of consistent rational formulas” (Rojek 2019, p. 133). Antinomies are constantly being solved by infinite rational solutions. Although antinomies do not exist horizontally, this infinite succession of solutions suggests a final vertical antinomy. In the same way that the infinity of 0.9 recurring “suggests” the completeness of the integer 1.
Contrastingly, some readings suggest that antinomies are only really present in horizontal fallen rationality, but were “resolved” in the vertical (and therefore are no longer present). This is a non-monotonic interpretation. In other words, there are only horizontal antinomies, and no real vertical ones. Since this is a widespread reading, it is worth giving some detail. As the Russian logician Evgenii Sidorenko claimed, “Florensky put forward a number of ideas, which were made explicit in our times in the systems of non-monotonic logics” (Sidorenko 2002, p. 167). Sidorenko and others base their arguments on Florensky’s short addendum in The Pillar, which deals with Lewis Carrol’s famous Barbershop Paradox. The Paradox imagined a hypothetical barbershop with three barbers, Allen, Brown and Carr. We accept the premises: one of them is always in the shop and Brown appears there only with Allen. We then are faced with the following two statements:
-
(1)
If Allen is out, then Brown is out. (since Brown appears only with Allen)
-
(2)
If Carr is out, then, if Allen is out, then Brown is in. (since one of them must be in the shop, this second statement however contradicts the premise that Brown appears only with Allen)
Or:
-
(1)
q → r
-
(2)
p → (q → ¬r)
Florensky expresses this as “q implies r (1), but p implies that q implies not-r (2), what should be concluded from this?”. Florensky concludes that p is a sort of “leap of faith” which modifies the entire worldview. This modification of the entire worldview is identified as “spiritual illumination”. Florensky now reads q as “the contradictions of Holy Scripture and dogma” and reads r as “non-divine origin” (Florensky 1914, p. 504). So the problem is reformulated as:
-
(1)
If the Scripture is contradictory, then the Scripture is not-divine
-
(2)
If there is spiritual illumination, then if the Scripture is contradictory, it must be divine
This unusual paradox is thus read non-monotonically, suggesting that a certain condition (p) can shift the entire logic and resolve its antinomies, in the same way that in monotonic logic “the extension of a set of premises may lead to the rejection of the previous conclusions” (Rojek 2019, p. 135).
Finally, some have even claimed that there are no antinomies in Florensky’s work, and that antinomy and paradox are employed only rhetorically, for example Gerasimova (2012) and Slesinski (1984). These four readings can be summarized in the following table which has been modified from Rojek’s chapter (2019, p. 129):
Type of Interpretation:
|
Rationality (Horizontal):
|
Reason (Vertical):
|
Found in:
|
---|
paraconsistent
|
inconsistent
(antinomies present)
|
inconsistent
(antinomies present)
|
Michael Rhodes (2013)
|
L-inconsistent
|
consistent
(no antinomies present)
|
inconsistent
(antinomies present)
|
Viacheslav Moiseev
|
non-monotonic
|
inconsistent
(antinomies present)
|
consistent
(no antinomies present)
|
Evgenii Sidorenko
|
rhetorical
|
consistent
(no antinomies present)
|
consistent
(no antinomies present)
|
Irina Gerasimova
|
The present study will support paraconsistent readings of antinomy throughout. This is because, as Florensky and many others have shown, antinomies not only occupy vertical theological religious discourse, but also linguistic,Footnote 34 and aesthetic discourse.Footnote 35 Both of the latter can be considered as belonging to the realm of horizontal antinomism. For Florensky therefore, antinomies are present both in the horizontal and in the vertical. A strictly paraconsistent reading of Florensky also makes perfect sense considering the development of Russian logic. Already by 1912, a few years before the publication of The Pillar, Nicolai Vasil’ev (1880–1940) had pioneered his own paraconsistent logic (Vasil’ev 1989),Footnote 36 thus providing the perfect context for Florensky’s work. Rojek himself opts for a combination of the non-monotonic and the L-inconsistent readings. However, despite this original synthesis, Rojek does not factor in the broader horizontal antinomies (aesthetic and linguistic) or, most importantly, Florensky’s central horizontal “antinomy of the two laws” and so understandably rejects a para-consistent reading outright. This latter horizontal antinomy is pivotal. It is more convincing than the “Logical Theory of Antinomy” which has been discussed up till now, and attempts to directly anticipate the doctrine of the Trinity. Like the “Logical Theory of Antinomy”, however, the antinomy of the two laws will likewise prove unsatisfactory, since there is no direct continuity from the laws to the Trinity, and Florensky thus offers no reason why someone like a non-Christian would accept the Trinity. This antinomy will now be considered in detail.
The Law of Identity
For Florensky a genuinely rationalist ontology is exemplified by the formula A = A, known in classical logic as the Law of Identity. As Florensky writes, “That which is rational, which conforms to the measure of rationality and satisfies the demands of rationality, can only be that which is isolated from everything else, which is not mixed with anything else, which is self-contained, in short, which is self-identical” (Florensky 1914, pp. 28–29).Footnote 37 Florensky would continue to reflect on the Law of Identity throughout his life, and by the time of his later lectures he would come to associate the law disparagingly with “western European thought” (Florensky 2014, p. 131). This law is indeed still a pillar of veracity in classical logic, as Paul Tomassi writes:
There is no possible interpretation under which the [Law of Identity] is false. If it’s raining then it’s raining, if the sun is shining then the sun is shining. And so on, ad nauseam. The very form of this formula ensures that no matter how we translate or interpret its constituent sentence-letters it will always be true. Hence, the law of identity is a logical truth. (Tomassi 1999, p. 67)
According to the Russian polymath, however, the law is stagnant and lifeless since it does not account for the real non-identity present in the mutable flux of life itself. The Law of Identity is a ‘hypostasised abstraction’ for Florensky (1914, p. 28).Footnote 38 Most importantly, Florensky believed that A = A was not only an abstraction but was a fundamentally negative definition, which operates according to the exclusion of alterity. Florensky writes:
In excluding all the other elements, every A is excluded by all of them, for if each of these elements is for A only not-A, then A over against not-A is only not–not-A. From the viewpoint of the Law of Identity, all being, in desiring to affirm itself, actually only destroys itself, becoming a combination of elements each of which is a centre of negations, and only negations. Thus all being is a total negation, one great ‘Not’. The Law of Identity is the spirit of death, emptiness, and nothingness. (Florensky 1914, p. 27)Footnote 39
Absolute silence is characteristic of this law, since the sterile A = A cannot be explained any further, for then A would equal a certain ‘not-A’, and the law would already be broken. Furthermore, as Schneider points out, there is no reason as to why we should even accept the law as access to certitude, as it is pure intuition: “The perception of a being in intuition does not provide the human mind with reasons for why it should accept this intuition as an experience of the Truth” (Schneider 2019, p. 6).
Due to the ever-changing nature of the universe, there is for Florensky no real identity in the world of things, only a sort of ‘self-similarity’, which can be understood only by analogy with the identity of the human self. True identity is found only in the self-identity of the subject. As Florensky writes: “Philosophers of the most different orientations have repeated the basic theme that the idea of identity in general is the reflection of the self-identity of the ‘I’… identity in its authentic and primary sense can be perceived only in the self-identity of the person and not in the self-similarity of the thing” (Florensky 1914, p. 82).Footnote 40 The subject is thus that which is most identical with itself. In this respect, Florensky quotes the neo-Kantian philosopher Herman Cohen: “die Selbigkeit des Seins ist ein Reflex der Identität des Denkens” (Florensky 1914, p. 82).Footnote 41 The author of The Pillar is thus justified to translate the Law of Identity, A = A, into Fichtean subjectivist terms: ‘I = I’. This leaves us not just with stagnancy, but an ethically undesirable ‘cry of naked egoism’, a negation of all other ‘I’’s (Florensky 1914, p. 78),Footnote 42 what Bruce Foltz calls a “prison of self-affirmation and self-assertion” (Foltz 2013, p. 8).
All of these problems with the Law of Identity stem from another law which is embedded within human reasoning. This is the perpetual desire to provide an account for some state of affairs ‘from outside’. This is a drive for a final ground or justification which is not identical with that which is being justified. This is The Law of Sufficient Reason.
The Law of Sufficient Reason
The Law of Sufficient Reason, another central feature of classical logic, states the following: “For every x there is a y, such that y is the sufficient reason for x”. This means for Florensky the search for a “grounding judgement” (Florensky 1914, p. 80).Footnote 43 But to avoid pure givenness this judgement must be justified in another which in turn must be justified in another ad infinitum. This ‘never ending fall into infinitude’ is identified with the Hegelian bad infinity of the Verstand.Footnote 44 This type of certitude Florensky names ‘discursive certitude’ in contradistinction to the ‘intuitive certitude’ discussed above. The Russian polymath claims that the whole essence of this discursive certitude, its entire ‘reasonableness’, is contained in the constant transmission from n to (n + 1) (Florensky 1914, p. 81). This sort of certitude “only gives rise in time to the dream of eternity but never makes it possible to touch eternity itself” (Florensky 1914, p. 31).Footnote 45 In defence of this law, Florensky once again turned to his rival Kant, who understood that in order to explain a given phenomenon, we can only use other given phenomena in a continuous successive manner (Schneider 2019, p. 6).
Florensky now contrasts the former Law of Identity with the latter Law of Sufficient Reason. The former is identified with intuition, while the latter is identified with discourse. In an important passage of The Pillar and Ground of the Truth, we read the following: “If the former [Law of Identity] provides non-philosophical satisfaction by its presence and its reliability, the latter [Law of sufficient Reason] is, in fact, not attained reasonableness but only a regulating principle, a law for the activity of reason, a road on which we must walk eternally in order to never reach any goal. A reasonable criterion is a direction, not a goal” (Florensky 1914, p. 32).Footnote 46 The two laws thus contradict each other, are in antinomy with one another, as the “Scylla and Charybdis on the way to certitude” (Florensky 1914, p. 33).Footnote 47
The ‘Perichoretic Reconfiguration’
As an alternative to a violent opposition of the two laws, Florensky endorses a turn to reason (razum), or more precisely “higher reason”, a term which had already become important for other Russian intellectuals, notably Nikolai Berdyaev.Footnote 48 Florensky’s “higher reason” is essentially the vertical antinomism of the Trinity. As Schneider has shown, this is reached through a “perichoretic reconfiguration” of the two laws discussed above. This is an attempt to show that they anticipate the real (vertical) antinomies in the Trinity. Initially, the Law of Identity is reconfigured and A = A (I = I) is now understood as an “act of self-emptying” which allows A to receive itself only through another (B) in virtue of its own (A’s) self–rejection. In other words, the Father kenotically receiving himself in the Son. This now allows for the possibility of B to be included in the relationship of identity. This is an inclusion of the other in the self, and simultaneously the inclusion of the self in the other. As Schneider writes, “Identity is now based on a kenotic and perichoretic act of self-emptying and self-rejection, which at the same time enables a person or being (say A) to receive itself back in its self-rejection from another (say B)” (Schneider 2019, p. 9). The Law of Identity is thus seen as anticipating the Father–Son relationship.
Not only the Law of Identity but also the Law of Sufficient Reason is remarkably reconfigured in the Trinity as a “self-proving subject” (Foltz 2013, p. 16). Florensky begins by reminding us that according to the Law of Sufficient Reason, the reason/principle of A must be found in something else, in another phenomenon (B). However, if B is merely defined as not-A, then B’s own “finding of itself” in another would just lead to not-not-A (which is equal to A), meaning that A has never left itself at all. In trying to find its ground in another, A has not actually managed to escape itself, since its other is only its own negation, and the negation of that negation leads back to itself. So, B must be something more than merely not-A. B can achieve this status of being more that not-A only by being “not- (something else)”, or “not- (some third term)”. B must, therefore, be understood as a not-C. Now since we have arrived at a third term “C”, this C must itself find a ground. It must find a not-C which is not simply B as not-C (as then the ground of that B would lead us to not-not-C, and C would not have escaped itself). C must find B also as a “not- (some third term)”, a role which can be filled by A. A can thus “receive itself mediately from another, but not through the one with which it is equated” (Florensky 1914, p. 48).Footnote 49
By considering discursion based only on three terms A, B, C, which ground each other, Florensky believes, the endless searching of the Law of Sufficient Reason is no more, “through C the circle can be closed”, and here “A receives itself as proved, already established” (Florensky 1914, p. 48).Footnote 50 We now have, in Schneider’s words, an “infinite, dynamic, but circular movement between A, B, and a third (C)” (Schneider 2019, p. 9). A, B, and C must also be subjects, in virtue of their authentic self-identity. Florensky has thus demonstrated “the contemplation of oneself through another in a third: Father, Son and Spirit” (Florensky 1914, p. 48).Footnote 51 The potential, or ‘bad’ infinity which characterised the Law of Sufficient Reason, is now “fully delimited and determinate” (Schneider 2019, p. 11). Although this reconfiguration of the two laws may seem like a rationalist deduction of the Trinity, much in the tradition of Solov’ev, Schneider insists that Florensky is actually constructing an “exposition of the content of the already given Truth”, or more precisely, “a formal anticipation of the Truth”. (Schneider 2019, p. 8)
We could thus read the above antinomy of the two laws as a horizontal antinomy which anticipates a vertical antinomy (the Trinity). However, there are serious problems with this “purely logical” anticipatory path from the horizontal to the vertical. Firstly, as Adam Drozdek points out, there is no real contradiction between the two laws. A = B (the supplying of a reason for A through predication of A) does not have to contradict A = A, because A = B can simply mean that A is just an element in the set B, or that A is a subset of set B (Drozdek 2008, p. 180). Drozdek thus concludes with the following: “If the necessary antinomic nature of reason is a reality, it is not based on the clash between the law of identity and the law of sufficient reason” (Drozdek 2008, p. 180). In other words, Florensky “failed to show the inescapably antinomic nature of reason [and its two laws]” (Drozdek 2008, p. 182).
Florensky, additionally, simply assumes that explicit talk of the doctrine of the Trinity has relevance for logic and thus for human thought, when there is really no “continuity” between the doctrine and the laws of logic. Schneider is aware of this and admits that a certain “discontinuity” is present in the anticipatory leap from the horizontal world of terms, principles and subjects (A, B and C) to the vertical world of the Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit. The Russian philosopher thus relies on a “leap of faith” or (podvig), which is required to pass over to the vertical world of the Trinity. Despite his enthusiasm for the “perichoretic reconfiguration”, Schneider eventually admits that the anticipation leaves us with “no positive evaluation of the laws themselves” (Schneider 2019, p. 16). In other words, the synthesis is “incompatible with normal laws of rationality” (Schneider 2019, p. 16). Schneider admits that the perichoretic reconfiguration is too far removed from rationality (rassudok), and the leap from this horizontal rationality to the vertical reason of the “perichoretic reconfiguration” is too great. Schneider even senses a “tendency to regard univocal logic as something inherently sinful and problematic” (Schneider 2019, p. 15). This tendency would find advocates in later Orthodox theology (Lossky 1991, p. 65).
The anticipation of vertical antinomism within horizontal antinomism is thus ultimately thwarted with discontinuity. Florensky clearly attempted such an anticipation through logic alone, neglecting other horizontal antinomies, such as ontological and aesthetic antinomies, which are only developed by later thinkers (Aleksei Losev in particular) and provide surer foundations for an anticipation of the vertical. Despite the failed horizontal antinomy, and with this, his failed attempt to convince his readers, Florensky nonetheless provided a rich account of the vertical antinomies of dogma and scripture which deserves some attention. These antinomies are those of faith, antinomies isolated from horizontal justification, one either accepts such contradictions or rejects them.
A Defence of Dogmatic Antinomism
Florensky claims that “only genuine religious experience apprehends antinomies and sees how their factual reconciliation is possible” (Florensky 1914, p. 162).Footnote 52 This may cause some concern since surely anyone can “apprehend” antinomic dogma without any experience of it. Of course, one can “apprehend” the dogmas, but this is different from having faith in them, which is what Florensky means here. As has been shown above, Florensky does not justify or sufficiently warrant this faith with his antinomism, and thus falls into fideism – faith arises in personal experience which we cannot explain. These problems should not distract us from the purely theological place of paradox. As Christians, Florensky insists, we must practise an ascetic “taming of rational activity” (Florensky 1914, p. 161),Footnote 53 and it is precisely dogma which nurtures this experience and “tames” the intellect. In Florensky’s view dogmatics must preserve a fundamental paradox in order to elicit freely-willed faith, as opposed to forced deduction. Florensky lists a total of eleven dogmatic antinomies to illustrate this point, including the trinitarian antinomy (God as both “consubstantial”, and “tri-hypostatic”) and the two natures of Christ (both “unmerged” and “indivisible”) (Florensky 1914, p. 164).
Such an antinomian approach to dogmatics is not without criticism. The most famous attack was launched by the philosopher and prince, Evgeniy Trubetskoi (1863–1920) in his essay “The Light of Tabor and the Transfiguration of the Mind” (Trubetskoi 2015). In Trubetskoi’s understanding, dogma is far from antinomic, since only a Solov’evian “whole” and a cohesive Christianity unites all aspects of life in all-unity (vseedinstvo) (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 8). Trubetskoi sees reason itself as participating in the transfiguration of mount Tabor (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 9), and holds that Florensky is a fideist who by separating faith from reason allows for an ‘autonomous reason’ and a wildly irrational faith.
According to Trubetskoi, Florensky has confused contradiction (protivorechie) with opposition (protivopolozhenie) (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 14), and Christian dogmas are marked only by the latter, not the former. Antinomy only arises when one admits “contradictory predicates concerning the same subject according to the same relation” (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 14). Therefore dogmas such as the Trinity are not really antinomies. Here the predication of “unity” applies only to the subject “Ousia”, while the predication of “multiplicity” applies only to the subject “Hypostases”. Similarly, when addressing Christology, Trubetskoi writes that inseparability (nerazdel’nost’) and non-confusability (nesliiannost’) do not logically exclude one another (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 14). Trubetskoi also claims that it is only our own fallen and insufficient intellects which are faced with antinomies. We can, and should, rise above antinomies and aim for their resolution (razreshenie) (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 15). We should aim for the “true and authentic norm of reason”, which is for the Russian prince cohesion and unity (Trubetskoi 2015, p. 15). Trubetskoi can, in this way, be considered as an early adherent of non-monotonic readings of Florensky’s Pillar.
Despite his efforts, Trubetskoi fails to notice Florensky’s overall project in The Pillar (however unsuccessful this may have been) of revealing an antinomy between the two laws of logic which ought to anticipate the higher antinomy of the Trinity. This is itself a cognitive enterprise of reason (however unsuccessful) and can itself be considered as the sort of “transfiguration of the mind” which Trubetskoi sought. More importantly, however, Trubetskoi does not properly consider the paradoxes of Christian dogma. Although he is correct that God is one qua Ousia and three qua Hypostases, Trubetskoi ignores the fact that the Hypostases are numerically identical with the Ousia yet remain in complete non-identity with each other. Simply put: (1) There is only one divine being and (2) there are three divine beings, is indeed a logical contradiction, more precisely an antinomy of identity and difference. This is spelled out in recent philosophy of religion, specifically by James Anderson in his comprehensive Paradox in Christian Theology (2007). Here Anderson distils the historical formulation of the Trinity into 6 consecutive theses, clarifying the antinomy.
-
“(T1) An orthodox doctrine of the Trinity must uphold biblical monotheism: there can only be one absolute, transcendent, indivisible, sovereign God. (Hence, all forms of polytheism should be excluded).
-
(T2) An orthodox doctrine of the Trinity must maintain the full and equal divinity of each of the three persons: the Father is fully God, the Son is fully God, and the Spirit is fully God. (Hence, all forms of ontological subordinationism should be excluded).
-
(T3) An orthodox doctrine of the Trinity must posit genuine distinctions between the three persons: The Father is not the same as the Son or the Spirit, and the Son is not the same as the Spirit. (Hence all forms of modalism should be avoided).
-
(T4) On the one hand, the conjunction of (T1) and (T2) seems to require that the consubstantiality relation between the divine persons be construed in terms of numerical identity rather than generic identity: The Father is identical with, not distinct from, the one divine ousia (essence, substance, Godhead); likewise, for the Son and the Spirit.
-
(T5) On the other hand, (T3) seems to require that each divine person is numerically distinct from (i.e., not numerically identical to) each of the other two persons.
-
(T6) Consequently, any interpretation of the doctrine of the Trinity that seeks to fulfil requirements (T1), (T2), and (T3) will be paradoxical, given our natural intuitions about the concepts employed” (Anderson 2007, p. 30).
Anderson concludes his history of the Trinity with the following: “There appears to be no option for the Christian theologian but to grasp one or the other horn of the dilemma: to abandon orthodoxy or to embrace paradox and thereby face the charge of irrationality” (Anderson 2007, p. 106).
Although there is a clear antinomy in the dogma of the Trinity, many are still hesitant to accept any sort of vertical antinomism. Drozdek, building on Trubetskoi, writes: “If all religious mysteries could only be clothed in contradiction, then we can say that God exists and does not exist” (Drozdek 2008, p. 182). In other words, why are not all dogmas self-contradictions? But in response to such a problem, it seems that the existence of God is not a linguistically defined theological dogma (in the same way that the Trinity and the Incarnation are) but is dependent on the entire dogmatic system of Orthodoxy as a whole. It is therefore not necessary that all religious statements are antinomies. Thus, it would seem that Florensky was right to assert that there are at least some religious vertical antinomies which are properly logically contradictory. These are central and dogmatic antinomies, whose antinomicity emanates as a general “paradoxical pathos”, as witnessed by the many scriptural and liturgical juxtapositions which pervade the life of the Church. Many of these juxtapositions are summarized in the idea, central to Christian life, that glorification arises only through its opposite, humiliation (Matthew 20:16).