Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

Too often C. S. Peirce’s theory of signs is used simply as a classificatory scheme rather than primarily as a heuristic framework (that is, a framework designed and modified primarily for the purpose of goading and guiding inquiry in any field in which signifying processes or practices are present). Such deployment of his semeiotic betrays the letter no less than the spirit of Peirce’s writings on signs. In this essay, the author accordingly presents Peirce’s sign theory as a heuristic framework, attending to some of the most important ways that it might serve to facilitate a semeiotic investigation of our legal practices. He pays close attention to the ways the topics of history, formalism, reductionism, and generality become, from a Peircean perspective, salient features of legal studies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The “inquirer more or less vaguely identifies himself in sentiment with the community of which he is a member” (CP 8.101; emphasis added; cf. Colapietro [14]).

  2. The most famous formulation of this maxim was its original enunciation in “How to Make Our Ideas Clear”: “Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object” (CP 5.402; EP 1: 132).

  3. Morality is never merely personal or individual; it is always deeply cultural, even (perhaps especially) when moral skeptics and rebels refuse to acknowledge their vast debt to their cultural inheritance.

  4. In The Will to Believe (1897), James captured the spirit of pragmatic fallibilism when he wrote: “Our errors are surely not such awfully solemn things. In a world where we are so certain to incur them in spite of all our caution, a certain lightness of heart seems healthier than this excessive nervousness on their behalf. At any rate, it seems the fittest thing for the empiricist philosopher” (19)—or the pragmatic fallibilist.

  5. But it does not enable us to obtain “a conception of something independent of all opinion and thought” (CP 7.345; emphasis added). This is but one of Peirce’s many rejections of the Kantian notion an unknowable ding-an-sich.

  6. In “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” Peirce uses reality as his fourth and final example to distinguish the three levels of conceptual clarity (tacit familiarity, abstract definition, and pragmatic clarification).

  7. Peirce appears to be the most paradoxical of pragmatists, exalting theory apart from its benefits to practice (see, e.g., CP 1.75–79; 1.616–48) This is however largely misleading. His point concerns the integrity of theoretical inquiry (a concern rooted in an awareness of how readily such inquiry can be subordinated to, and directed by, external forces).

  8. William James explicitly draws this contrast: “Whenever the option between losing truth and gaining it is not momentous, we can throw the chance of gaining truth away … by not making up our minds at all till objective evidence is in. In scientific questions, this is almost always the case; and even in human affairs in general, the need of acting is seldom so urgent that a false belief to act on is better than no belief at all. Law courts, indeed, have to decide on the best evidence available for the moment, because a judge’s duty is to have them decided on any acceptable principle, and got out of the way” [29, pp. 25–26]. The justice of legal decisions is bound up with their timeliness; and, in turn, their timeliness is bound up with the pressing urgency of rendering an impartial, informed, and principled judgment as speedily as possible.

  9. Near the end of Origin of Species, Charles Darwin underscores one of the decisive benefits of his evolutionary theory: it will relieve biologists of the responsibility of classifying the various shrubbery found in the English countryside: “How much more interesting” does our study of life become “when we regard every production of nature as one which has had a history.” When the views puts forth in this work are taken seriously, “we can dimly foresee that there will be a considerable revolution in natural history. Systematists will be able to pursue their labors as at present; but they will not be incessantly haunted by the shadowy doubt whether this or that form be in essence a species. This I feel sure, and speak after experience, will be no slight relief. The endless disputes whether or not some fifty species of British brambles are true species will cease. Systematists will have only to decide (not that this will be easy) whether any form be sufficiently constant and distinct from other forms to be capable of definition; and if definable, whether the differences be sufficiently important to deserve a specific name” (211–212). What Darwin writes here of the science of life is, at least, equally, true of the doctrine of signs. The “systematists” or formalists are not classing immutable species of signs, but historically emergent and significant functions.

  10. In one place, Peirce stresses: “man [i.e., Homo Sapiens] divines something of the secret principles of the universe because his mind has developed as a part of the universe and under the influence of these same secret principles …” (CP 7.46).

  11. A very fine collection of essays on human practices is The Practice Turn in Contemporary Thought, edited by Theodore Schatzki et al. [54]. The authors of these essays are not (at least not obviously) working in the pragmatic tradition, but their approach is congenial to those committed to advancing the ideas of Peirce, James, Dewey, and other pragmatists.

References

  1. Benson, Robert. 1991. Peirce and critical legal studies. In Peirce and Law, ed. Roberta Kevelson, 15–28. New-York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bergson, Henri. 1944. Creative Evolution (trans: Mitchell, Arthur). New York: Random House.

  3. Bernstein, Richard J. 1971. Praxis and Action. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bernstein, Richard J. 1991. The Lure of the Ideal. In Peirce and Law, ed. Roberta Kevelson, 29–43. New-York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Brion, Denis J. 1991. The chaotic law of Tort. In Peirce and Law, ed. Roberta Kevelson 45–77. New-York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cassirer, Ernst 1962. An Essay on Man. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Colapietro, Vincent. 1989. Peirce’s Approach to the Self. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Colapietro, Vincent. 1997. The dynamical object and the deliberative subject. In The Rule of Reason, eds. Jacqueline Brunning and Paul Forster, 262–288. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Colapietro, Vincent. 1998. Natural processes and historical practices. Semiotica 119(1/2): 105–155.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Colapietro, Vincent. 2001. A lantern for the feet of inquirers: the heuristic function of Peircean categories. Semiotica 136(1/4): 201–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Colapietro, Vincent. 2003. The space of signs: Peirce’s critique of psychologism. In Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychologism, ed. Dale Jacquette, 157–180. New-York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Colapietro, Vincent. 2004. Portrait of a historicist: an alternative reading of Peircean semiotic. Semiotiche, 49–68. Turin, Italy: Ananke.

  13. Colapietro, Vincent. 2005. Conjectures concerning an uncertain faculty claimed for humans. Semiotica 153(1/4): 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Colapietro, Vincent. 2006. Toward a pragmatic conception of practical identity. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42(2, Spring): 173–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Darwin, Charles. 1993. The Portable Darwin. In eds. Duncan Porter and Peter Graham. New-York: Viking.

  16. Deacon, Terrence. 1998. The Symbolic Species. New-York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Delaney, C. F. 1973. C. S. Peirce’s critique of foundationalism. The Monist 57: 240–251.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Dewey, John. 1977. The Middle Works of John Dewey. In ed. Jo Ann Boydston, vol 4, Cited as MW 4. Carbondale: SIU Press.

  19. Dewey, John. 1991. The Later Works of John Dewey. In ed. Jo Ann Boydston, vol 14, Cited as LW 14. Carbondale: SIU Press.

  20. Dougherty, Charles. 1980. C. S. Peirce’s critique of psychologism. In Two Centuries of Philosophy in America, ed. Peter Caws, 86–93. Towota, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Eco, Umberto. 1976. A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Emerson, R. W. 1982. Ralph Waldo Emerson: Selected Essays.In ed. Larzer Ziff. New-York: Penguin Books.

  23. Esposito, Joseph. 1977. Schelling’s Idealism and Philosophy of Nature. Lewisburg, PA: Bucknell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Fisch, Max H. 1986. Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism. In eds. K. L. Ketner and Christain Kloesel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  25. Frankl, Viktor. 1969. Reductionism and nihilism. In Beyond Reductionism, eds. Koestler and Smythies. London: MacMillan.

  26. Hoeveler, J. David. 2007. The Evolutionists: American Thinkers Confront Charles Darwin 1860–1920. Rowman & Littlefield.

  27. James, William. 1975. Pragmatism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. James, William. 1977. A Pluralistic Universe. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. James, William. 1979. The Will to Believe and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Kellogg, Frederic R. 1991. A pragmatic theory of legal classification. In Peirce and Law, ed. Roberta Kevelson, 79–98. New-York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Kevelson, Roberta. 1988. The Law as a System of Signs. New-York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Kevelson, Roberta. (ed.) 1991. Peirce and Law. New-York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Koestler, Arthur. and Smythies, J. R. (eds.) 1969. Beyond Reductionism: New Perspectives in the Life Sciences. London: Hutchinson. [1968 Alpbach Symposium].

    Google Scholar 

  34. Kuhn, Thomas. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Langer, Susanne K. 1957. Philosophy in a New Key, 3rd edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Liszka, James J. 1996. A General Introduction to the Semeiotic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Menand, Louis. 2002. The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America. NY: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Nöth, Winfried. 1995. Handbook of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Oehler, Klaus. 1991. An outline of Peirce’s semiotics. In Classics of Semiotics, eds. Martin Krampen, et al., 1–21. New-York: Plenum Press.

  40. Peirce, C. S. 1931–1958. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. In eds. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss vols. 1–6; ed. Arthur W. Burks. vols 7 & 8, Cited as CP. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  41. Peirce, C. S. 1977. Semiotic and Significas: The Correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby. In ed. Charles S. Hardwick. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  42. Peirce, C.S. 1992. The Essential Peirce. In eds. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel, vol 1, Cited as EP 1. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  43. Peirce, C.S. 1998. The Essential Peirce. In ed. Peirce Edition Project, vol 2, Cited as EP 2. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  44. Ransdell, Joseph. 1976. Another interpretation of Peirce’s semiotic. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 12(Spring/2): 97–110.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ransdell, Joseph. 1977. Some leading ideas of Peirce’s semiotic. Semiotica 19: 157–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Ransdell, Joseph. 1980. Semiotic and linguistic. In Signifying Animal: The Grammar of Language and Experience, eds. Irmengard Rauch and Gerald F. Carr, 135–185. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ransdell, Joseph. 2007. T. L. short on Peirce’s semeiotic. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43(Fall/4): 654–662.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Rorty, Richard. 1982. Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Rorty, Richard. 1992. The pragmatist’s progress. In Interpretation and Overinterpretation, ed. Stefano Collini, 89–108. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Russett, Cynthia Eagle. 1976. Darwin in America: The Intellectual Response, 1865–1912. San Francisco: Freeeman.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Santaella-Braga, Lucia. 1999. Methodeutics, the liveliest branch of semiotics. Semiotica 124(3/4): 377–395.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Savan, David. 1987. An Introduction to Peirce’s Full System of Semeiotic. Victoria College in the University of Toronto.

  54. Schatzki, Theodore R., Cetina, Karin Knorr, and von Savigny Eike. (eds.) 2001. The Practice Turn in Contemporary Thought. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Sellars, Wilfrid. 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Shapiro, Michael. 1983. A Sense of Grammar. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Short, T. L. 2007a. Peirce’s Theory of Signs. New-York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Short, T. L. 2007b. Response. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43(Fall/4): 663–693.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Smith, John E. 1969. Time, ‘time,’ and the right time. The Monist 53(1): 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Smolin, Lee. 1999. The Life of the Cosmos. New-York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Sorrell, Kory Spencer. 2004. Representative Practices: Peirce, Pragmatism, and Feminist Epistemology. New-York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Sullivan, Michael. 2007. Legal Pragmatism: Community, Rights, and Democracy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Thayer, H. S. 1981. Meaning and Action: A Critical History of Pragmatism. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Toulmin, Stephen. 1972. Human Understanding. Princeton: Princeton University Press..

    Google Scholar 

  65. Toulmin Stephen, and June Goodfield. 1965. The Discovery of Time. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Weiss Paul, and Arthur Burks. 1945. Peirce’s sixty-six signs. Journal of Philosophy XLII: 383–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Zeman, Jay. 1977. Peirce’s theory of signs. In A Perfusion of Signs, ed. Thomas Sebeok, 22–39. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vincent Colapietro.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Colapietro, V. Peircean Semeiotic and Legal Practices: Rudimentary and “Rhetorical” Considerations. Int J Semiot Law 21, 223–246 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-008-9065-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-008-9065-5

Keywords

Navigation