Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Why Machine-Information Metaphors are Bad for Science and Science Education

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Genes are often described by biologists using metaphors derived from computational science: they are thought of as carriers of information, as being the equivalent of “blueprints” for the construction of organisms. Likewise, cells are often characterized as “factories” and organisms themselves become analogous to machines. Accordingly, when the human genome project was initially announced, the promise was that we would soon know how a human being is made, just as we know how to make airplanes and buildings. Importantly, modern proponents of Intelligent Design, the latest version of creationism, have exploited biologists’ use of the language of information and blueprints to make their spurious case, based on pseudoscientific concepts such as “irreducible complexity” and on flawed analogies between living cells and mechanical factories. However, the living organism = machine analogy was criticized already by David Hume in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. In line with Hume’s criticism, over the past several years a more nuanced and accurate understanding of what genes are and how they operate has emerged, ironically in part from the work of computational scientists who take biology, and in particular developmental biology, more seriously than some biologists seem to do. In this article we connect Hume’s original criticism of the living organism = machine analogy with the modern ID movement, and illustrate how the use of misleading and outdated metaphors in science can play into the hands of pseudoscientists. Thus, we argue that dropping the blueprint and similar metaphors will improve both the science of biology and its understanding by the general public.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See http://www.genome.gov/11006943.

  2. Paley was not the first to pursue the analogy with a pocket watch. In fact, Paley borrowed the famous paragraph in the first chapter of his work from the book Regt gebruik der werelt beschouwingen (1715) by the Dutch physician Bernard Nieuwentijt, who was himself probably influenced by thinkers like William Derham, John Ray and Robert Boyle.

  3. Philo says that “it is a palpable and egregious partiality to confine our view entirely to that principle by which our own minds operate” (Hume 1998 [1779], p. 46).

  4. A survey by Condit et al. about the perception of the blueprint and recipe metaphor suggests that deeply religious people prefer the blueprint metaphor precisely because of its theistic connotations (Condit et al. 2002, p. 312).

  5. Thanks to Stefaan Blancke for this suggestion.

  6. See http://www.journeyinsidethecell.com/.

  7. Methylation is a simple form of chemical alteration of DNA that affects gene expression; chromatin structure refers to alteration in the spatial distribution of the DNA-proteins ensemble that makes up chromosomes; interference RNAs (iRNAs) are small molecules of ribonucleic acid that also affect gene expression.

  8. See also the online video demonstration of origami embryology by Kathryn Tosney and Diana Darnell: http://www.origamiembryo.cba.arizona.edu/.

References

  • Alberts, B. (1998). The cell as a collection overview of protein machines: Preparing the next generation of molecular biologists. Cell, 92, 291–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amanzio, M., Geminiani, G., Leotta, D., & Cappa, S. (2008). Metaphor comprehension in Alzheimer’s disease: Novelty matters. Brain and Language, 107, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (350BE/1991). De anima. Prometheus Books.

  • Ashworth, W. B. (2003). Christianity and the mechanistic universe. In D. C. Lindberg & R. L. Numbers (Eds.), When science and Christianity meet (pp. 61–84). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (2006). Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution (10th Anniversary Edition). Simon and Schuster.

  • Brown, T. L. (2003). Making truth: Metaphor in science. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ciliberti, S., Martin, O. C., & Wagner, A. (2007). Innovation and robustness in complex regulatory gene networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA, 104, 13591–13596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Condit, C. M., Bates, B. R., Galloway, R., et al. (2002). Recipes or blueprints for our genes? How contexts selectively activate the multiple meanings of metaphors. Quarterly Journal of Speech, 88, 303–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species. http://www.darwin-online.org.uk/.

  • Davis, P. W., Kenyon, D. H., & Thaxton, C. B. (1993). Of pandas and people: The central question of biological origins. Haughton Pub Co.

  • Dawkins, R. (1991). The blind watchmaker. Penguin books.

  • Dawkins, R., & Wong, Y. (2005). The ancestor’s tale: A pilgrimage to the dawn of life. London: Phoenix Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H. & De Smedt, J. (2010). Science as structured imagination. Forthcoming in Journal of Creative Behavior.

  • Descartes, R. (1648/1972). Treatise of man. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Donohue, K., Polisetty, C. R., & Wender, N. J. (2005). Genetic basis and consequences of niche construction: Plasticity-induced genetic constraints on the evolution of seed dispersal in Arabidopsis thaliana. American Naturalist, 165, 537–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. (1995). Refiguring life: Metaphors of twentieth-century biology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, M., Haddow, P. C., & Lehre, P. K. (2007). The genotypic complexity of evolved fault-tolerant and noise-robust circuits. Biosystems, 87, 224–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hassoun, R., Schwartz, P., Feistel, K., Blum, M., & Viebahn, C. (2009). Axial differentiation and early gastrulation stages of the pig embryo. Differentiation: Aug 14 [Epub ahead of print].

  • Hendrikse, J. L., Parsons, T. E., & Hallgrímsson, B. (2007). Evolvability as the proper focus of evolutionary developmental biology. Evolution and Development, 9, 393–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1779/1998). Dialogues concerning natural religion (2nd ed). Hackett.

  • Iimura, T., Denans, N., & Pourquié, O. (2009). Establishment of Hox vertebral identities in the embryonic spine precursors. Current Topics in Developmental Biology, 88, 201–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. (2007). The developmental construction of heredity. Developmental Psychobiology, 49, 808–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2005). Evolution in four dimensions: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral and symbolic variation in the history of life. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaroff, L. (1989). The gene hunt. Time, Mar. 20, pp. 62–67.

  • Johannes, F., Colot, V., & Jansen, R. C. (2008). Epigenome dynamics: A quantitative genetics perspective. Nature Review Genetics, 9, 883–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007/1790). Critique of judgment. Cosimo Books.

  • Kaplan, J. M., & Pigliucci, M. (2001). Genes ‘for’ phenotypes: A modern history view. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 189–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., & Sterelny, K. (2006). Perspective: Seven reasons (not) to neglect niche construction. Evolution, 60(9), 1751–1762.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. S., & Miller, K. R. (1994). Biology: Discovering life. Lexington: Heath Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. C. (2006). Evolutionary morphology and evo-devo: Hierarchy and novelty. Theory in Bioscience, 124, 317–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, E. (1994). Flexible bodies: Tracking immunity in American culture-from the days of polio to the age of AIDS. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E., & Provine, W. B. (1998). The evolutionary synthesis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. R. (2000). Finding Darwin’s god: A scientist’s search for common ground between god and evolution. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. R. (2008). Only a theory: Evolution and the battle for America’s Soul. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli, A., & Fusco, G. (2005). Conserved versus innovative features in animal body organization. Journal of Experimental Zoology, B, Molecular Development and Evolution, 304, 520–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. B. (2007). Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8, 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2001). Molecular metaphors: The gene in popular discourse. Nature Reviews Genetics, 2, 555–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nieuwentyt, B. (1715). Het regt gebruik der werelt beschouwingen, ter overtuiginge van ongodisten en ongelovigen aangetoont. Wolters and Pauli.

  • Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (Eds.). (2003). Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paley, W. (1802). Natural theology, or, evidences of the existence and attributes of the deity, collected from the appearances of nature. London: Gould and Lincoln.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pennock, R. T. (1999). Tower of babel: The evidence against the new creationism, Bradford books. Cambridge (Mass.): MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perakh, M. (2008). Flagella myths. How intelligent design proponents created the myth that bacteria flagella look like man-made machines. Skeptic, 14, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2001). Phenotypic plasticity: Beyond nature and nurture. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2002). Denying evolution: Creationism, scientism, and the nature of science. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2009). An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1168, 218–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roggen, D., Federici, D., & Floreano, D. (2007). Evolutionary morphogenesis for multi-cellular systems. Genetic Programs and Evolvable Machines, 8, 61–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rutka, J. T., Kongkham, P., Northcott, P., Carlotti, C., Guduk, M., Osawa, H., et al. (2009). The evolution and application of techniques in molecular biology to human brain tumors: A 25 year perspective. Journal of Neurooncology, 92, 261–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saminathan, R., Pachiappan, A., Feng, L., Rowan, E. G., & Gopalakrishnakone, P. (2009). Transcriptome profiling of neuronal model cell PC12 from rat pheochromocytoma. Cell and Molecular Neurobiology, 29, 533–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1944/1992). What is life? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Shanks, N. (2004). God, the Devil, and Darwin: A critique of intelligent design theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, N., & Joplin, K. (1999). Redundant complexity: A critical analysis of intelligent design in biochemistry. Philosophy of Science, 66, 268–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slatkin, M. (2009). Epigenetic inheritance and the missing heritability problem. Genetics, 182, 845–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snow, C. P. (1959/1993). The two cultures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Stanley, K. O. (2007). Compositional pattern producing networks: A novel abstraction of development. Genetics Programs and Evolvable Machines, 8, 131–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturm, R. A., & Larsson, M. (2009). Genetics of human iris colour and patterns. Pigment Cell Melanoma Research, 22, 544–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian, C., Gregersen, P. K., & Seldin, M. F. (2008). Accounting for ancestry: Population substructure and genome-wide association studies. Human Molecular Genetics, 17, R143–R150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uttamchandani, M., Lu, C. H., & Yao, S. Q. (2009). Next generation chemical proteomic tools for rapid enzyme profiling. Accounts of Chemical Research, 42, 1183–1192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. D., & Crick, F. H. (1953). Molecular structure of nucleic acids; a structure for deoxyribose nucleic acid. Nature, 171, 737–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1951/2009). Philosophical investigations. In P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte (Eds.). New York: Wiley.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1972). The blue and brown books. Preliminary studies for the ‘philosophical investigations’. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L., & Skinner, D. (1993). The triumph of the embryo. New York: Oxford University press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, Z., & Zhao, H. (2009). Statistical power of model selection strategies for genome-wide association studies. PLoS Genetics, 5, e1000582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, M. (2004). Grand designs and facile analogies. Exposing Behe’s mousetrap and Dembski’s arrow. In M. Young & T. Edis (Eds.), Why intelligent design fails: A scientific critique of the new creationism (pp. 20–31). New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

The research of Maarten Boudry was supported by the Flemish Fund for Scientific Research (FWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Massimo Pigliucci.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pigliucci, M., Boudry, M. Why Machine-Information Metaphors are Bad for Science and Science Education. Sci & Educ 20, 453–471 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-010-9267-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-010-9267-6

Keywords

Navigation