Skip to main content
Log in

Risk aversion in the small and in the large: Calibration results for betweenness functionals

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A reasonable level of risk aversion with respect to small gambles leads to a high, and absurd, level of risk aversion with respect to large gambles. This was demonstrated by Rabin (Econometrica 68:1281–1292, 2000) for expected utility theory. Later, Safra and Segal (Econometrica, 2008) extended this result by showing that similar arguments apply to many non-expected utility theories, provided they are Gâteaux differentiable. In this paper we drop the differentiability assumption and by restricting attention to betweenness theories we show that much weaker conditions are sufficient for the derivation of similar calibration results.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This version of B3 requires that for every lottery X, the decision maker prefers X to an even chance lottery of playing X − ℓ and X + g.

  2. See Foster and Hart (2007).

  3. Note that differentiability of the local utilities and differentiability of the functional are two different issues. The rank dependent model (Quiggin 1982) is Gâteaux differentiable but its local utilities are not, hence it does not satisfy H1, H2, or their opposites. At the end of Appendix 2 we show that H1 and H2 do not imply even Gâteaux differentiability.

  4. Rabin and Thaler (2001) on the other hand seem to claim that a rejection of a small lottery is likely only when the decision maker is unaware of the fact that he is exposed to many other risks.

  5. In Safra and Segal (1998) we wrongly claimed that when u is linear, Gul’s functional is Gâteaux differentiable.

References

  • Chew, S. H. (1983). A generalization of the quasilinear mean with applications to the measurement of income inequality and decision theory resolving the Allais paradox. Econometrica, 51, 1065–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S. H. (1989). Axiomatic utility theories with the betweenness property. Annals of Operations Research, 19, 273–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S. H., Epstein, L. G., & Segal, U. (1991). Mixture symmetry and quadratic utility. Econometrica, 59, 139–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, J. C., & Sadiraj, V. (2006). Small-and large-stakes risk aversion: Implications of concavity calibration for decision theory. Games and Economic Behavior, 56, 45–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E. (1986). An axiomatic characterization of preferences under uncertainty: Weakening the independence axiom. Journal of Economic Theory, 40, 304–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G. (1992). Behavior under risk: Recent developments in theory and applications. In J. J. Laffont (Ed.), Advances in economic theory (Vol. II, pp. 1–63). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1983). Transitive measurable utility. Journal of Economic Theory, 31, 293–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster, D. P., & Hart, S. (2007). An operational measure of riskiness. The Hebrew University of Jerusalem

  • Guiso, L., Jappelli, T., & Terlizzese, D. (1996). Income risk, borrowing constraints, and portfolio choice. American Economic Review, 86, 158–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F. (1991). A theory of disappointment aversion. Econometrica, 59, 667–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hochguertel, S. (2003). Precautionary motives and protfolio decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 18, 61–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M. J. (1982). ‘Expected utility’ analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica, 50, 277–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paiella, M., & Guiso, L. (2001). Risk aversion, wealth and background risk. Mimeo.

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected utility theory: A calibration result. Econometrica, 68, 1281–1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M., & Thaler, R. H. (2001). Risk aversion. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15, 219–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (2006). Dilemmas of an economic theorist. Econometrica, 74, 865–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Safra, Z., & Segal, U. (1998). Constant risk aversion. Journal of Economic Theory, 83, 19–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Safra, Z., & Segal, U. (2008). Calibration results for non expected utility preferences. Econometrica, 76, 1143–1166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smorodinsky, R. (2000). The reflection effect for constant risk averse agents. Mathematical Social Sciences, 40, 265–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Uzi Segal.

Additional information

We thank Larry Epstein, Aaron Fix, the editor, and a referee for their help and suggestions. Uzi Segal thanks the NSF for its financial support (Award #0617359).

Appendices

Appendix 1

Proof of Theorems 1 and 2

Let \(\mathcal{I}\) be the indifference set of V through δ w and let u(·;δ w ) be one of the increasing vNM utilities obtained from \(\mathcal I\) (note that all these utilities are related by positive affine transformations). Obviously, \(\mathcal{I}\) is also an indifference set of the expected utility functional defined by \(U(F)=\int u(x;\delta_w)dF(x)\). By monotonicity, V and U increase in the same direction relative to the indifference set \(\mathcal{I}\).

We show first that u(·;δ w ) is concave. Suppose not. Then there exist z and H such that z = E[H] and U(H) > u(z;δ w ). By monotonicity and continuity, there exist p and z′ such that (z − w)(z′ − w) < 0 and \((z,p;z',1-p)\in \mathcal{I}\). As U(H) > u(z;δ w ), it follows that (H,p;z′,1 − p) is above \(\mathcal{I}\) with respect to the expected utility functional U. Therefore, (H,p;z′,1 − p) is also above \(\mathcal{I}\) with respect to V, which is a violation of risk aversion, since (H,p;z′,1 − p) is a mean preserving spread of (z,p;z′,1 − p).

By betweenness, \(V(x,1) > V(x-\ell,\frac12; x+g,\frac12)\) implies that, for all ε > 0, \(V(x,1) > V(x,1-\varepsilon; x-\ell,\frac\varepsilon 2; x+g,\frac\varepsilon 2)\). Using the local utility at δ x we obtain

$$ \label{e:31.1} {\textstyle u(x;\delta_x) > \displaystyle\frac12u(x-\ell;\delta_x) + \frac12 u(x+g;\delta_x)} $$
(3)

Theorem 1

Assume \(\neg\)H1 or \(\neg\)H2. We show that for every x ∈ [a,b], \(u(x;\delta_a) > \frac12u(x- \ell;\delta_a) + \frac12 u(x+ g;\delta_a)\). Equation 3 holds for x = a, and \(\neg\)H1 implies

$$ \label{e:33.1} {\textstyle u(x;\delta_a) > \displaystyle\frac12u(x-\ell;\delta_a) + \frac12 u(x+g;\delta_a)} $$
(4)

Also, since \(x\geqslant a\), \(\neg\)H2 implies that the local utility u(·;δ a ) is more concave than the local utility u(·;δ x ) and hence (4).

By Fact 1, it now follows that the expected utility decision maker with the vNM function u(·;δ a ) satisfies u(a;δ a ) > pu(a − L;δ a ) + (1 − p) u(a + G;δ a ) and the lottery (a − L,p;a + G,1 − p) lies below the indifference set \(\mathcal{I}\). Therefore,

$$ {\textstyle V(a,1)> V(a-L,p;a+ G,1-p)} $$

Theorem 2

Assume H1 or H2. Here we show that for every x ∈ [a,b], \(u(x;\delta_b) > \frac12u(x-\ell;\delta_b) + \frac12 u(x+g;\delta_b)\). Equation 3 holds in particular for x = b, and therefore H1 implies that for \(x \leqslant b\),

$$ \label{e:31.2} {\textstyle u(x;\delta_b) > \displaystyle\frac12u(x-\ell;\delta_b) + \frac12 u(x+g;\delta_b)} $$
(5)

Also, since \(x \leqslant b\), H2 implies that the local utility u(·;δ b ) is more concave than the local utility u(·;δ x ). Hence starting at (3) and moving from δ x to δ b , H2 implies (5).

By Fact 2 it now follows that the expected utility decision maker with the vNM function u(·;δ b ) satisfies u(b;δ b ) > pu(b − L;δ b ) + (1 − p) u(b + G;δ b ) and the lottery (b − L,p;b + G,1 − p) lies below the indifference set \(\mathcal{I}\). Therefore,

$$ {\textstyle V(b,1)> V(b-L,p;b+G,1-p)}\quad \quad \square $$

Proof of Theorem 3

For every x and z such that \(w+c \geqslant x > w > z \geqslant w-\bar L\) there is a probability q such that X = (x,q;z,1 − q) satisfies V(X) = V(w,1). By (ℓ,g) bi-stochastic B3,

$$ \label{e:7.2} {\textstyle V(x,q;z,1-q) > V\left(x-\ell,\displaystyle\frac q2; x+g, \frac q2; z-\ell,\frac{1-q}2; z+g,\frac{1-q}2\right)} $$
(6)

Denote the distribution functions of the two lotteries in (6) by F and F′, respectively. Betweenness implies that the local utilities at δ w and at F are the same (up to a positive linear transformation). Hence, by using the local utility u(·;δ w ), we obtain,

$$ \begin{array}{lll} \label{e:7.3} & & { q\left[u(x;\delta_w) - \displaystyle\frac12(u(x-\ell;\delta_w) + u(x+g;\delta_w))\right] }\\ & &{\kern12pt} + { (1-q)\left[u(z;\delta_w) - \displaystyle\frac12(u(z-\ell;\delta_w) + u(z+g;\delta_w))\right] > 0} \end{array} $$
(7)

Suppose there are \(w\!+\!c\! >\! x^*\! >\! w\! >\! z^* \!> \!w\!-\!\bar L\) such that \(u(x^*;\delta_w) \!\leqslant\! \frac12[u(x^*\!-\!\ell;\delta_w) \!+\! u(x^*\!+\!g;\delta_w)]\) and \(u(z^*;\delta_w) \leqslant \frac12[u(z^*\!-\!\ell;\delta_w) \!+\! u(z^*\!+\!g;\delta_w)]\). Then inequality (7) is reversed, and by betweenness, the inequality at (6) is reversed; a contradiction to bi-stochastic B3. Therefore, at least one of the following holds.

  1. 1.

    For all x ∈ [w,w + c],

    $$ {\displaystyle u(x;\delta_w) > \frac12[u(x-\ell;\delta_w) + u(x+g;\delta_w)]} $$

    and, similarly to the Proof of Theorem 1 (replace a with w in (4)), betweenness implies that V(w,1) > V(w − L,p;w + G,1 − p) and the first claim of the theorem is satisfied.

  2. 2.

    For all \(x \in [w-\bar L,w]\),

    $$ {\displaystyle u(x;\delta_w) > \frac12[u(x-\ell;\delta_w) + u(x+g;\delta_w)]} $$

    and, using an argument similar to that of the Proof of Theorem 2 (replace b with w in (5)), betweenness implies \(V(w,1)> V(w-g-\bar L,\bar p;w-g+\bar G,1-\bar p)\) and the second claim of the theorem is satisfied. □

Appendix 2

We first show that Gul’s (1991) disappointment aversion functional is not Gâteaux differentiable.Footnote 5 Consider lotteries of the form (x,p;y,1 − p − q;z,q) where x < y < z are constant and a disappointment aversion functional V(p,q) with u(x) = 0 and u(z) = 1. From (1) and (2) in Gul (1991) it follows that

$$ V(p,q) = \left \{ \begin{array}{ll} \displaystyle\frac{(1-p-q)u(y)+q}{1+\beta p} & q \leqslant \displaystyle\frac{(1+\beta) p u(y)}{1-u(y)}\\\\ \displaystyle\frac{(1+\beta)(1-p-q)u(y)+q}{1+ \beta - \beta q} & q > \displaystyle\frac{(1+\beta) p u(y)}{1-u(y)} \end{array} \right. $$

Along the line p + q = 1 we obtain

$$ V(p,q)=\frac{1-p}{1+\beta p} $$

hence along this line, V is differentiable. In particular, the derivatives at \(\left(\frac{1-u(y)}{1+\beta u(y)}, 1- \frac{1-u(y)}{1+\beta u(y)} \right)\) in the directions (1,0) and (0,1) have the same absolute value and opposite signs. However, along the line \(p+q=\frac12\), we obtain

$$ V(p,q)=\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \displaystyle\frac{u(y)+1-2p}{2+2\beta p} & p \geqslant \displaystyle\frac{1-u(y)}{2+2\beta u(y)}\\\\ \displaystyle\frac{(1+\beta)u(y)+1-2p}{2+2\beta p+\beta} & p < \displaystyle\frac{1-u(y)}{2+2\beta u(y)} \end{array} \right. $$

It is easy to verify that the derivatives of V at \(\left(\frac{1-u(y)}{2+2\beta u(y)}, \frac12- \frac{1-u(y)}{2+2\beta u(y)} \right)\) in the directions \((\frac12,0)\) and \((0,\frac12)\) do not have the same absolute value. As V is differentiable along the line p + q = 1 but not along the line \(p+q=\frac12\), it follows that neither V, nor any increasing transformation of V is Gâteaux differentiable.

Next we show that hypotheses H1, H2, and their opposites do not imply Gâteaux differentiability. It is easy to construct a weighted utility functional W (Chew 1983) satisfying H1 and H2. Define a functional V which is equal to W above indifference curve \(\cal I\), and below \(\cal I\) it is expected utility with \(\cal I\) being one of its indifference curves. Similarly to the above analysis, this functional is not Gâteaux differentiable, but as expected utility and W satisfy H1 and H2, so does V.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Safra, Z., Segal, U. Risk aversion in the small and in the large: Calibration results for betweenness functionals. J Risk Uncertain 38, 27–37 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9057-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9057-6

Keywords

Navigation