Skip to main content
Log in

What impacts the impact of rare events

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Kahneman and Tversky (Econometrica 47:263–291, 1979) argued that “unlikely events are either neglected or overweighted,” but left the task of identifying factors that determine which of these contradicting biases occur to future research. We present four studies designed to tackle this issue in the context of decisions from incomplete descriptions. Our findings suggest that the impact of unlikely events increases when they become more similar to their comparison stimuli, and when they are explicitly presented. Using these factors we reversed the findings in variants of classic gambles in the history of decision research, the Allais and the St. Petersburg gambles.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In a recent meta-analysis of all studies involving decisions between a two-outcome risky prospect and a sure thing (with equal expected value), Weber, Shafir, and Blais (2004) found that all 226 choice situations called for decisions from descriptions.

  2. This observation does not imply that studies that use the certainty equivalence lead to biased results. Rather, it implies that the observed results (the implied deviation from optimal weighting of rare events) can be safely generalized to similar contexts, but not to any other contexts.

  3. Because the means are biased by the limited range in the AS-Rare-context, we focus on the medians.

  4. As a consequence, participants in the mere-presentation condition had more information (they knew the outcomes). In our view this fact is not an experimental artifact. Rather we suspect that in many real-world domains (e.g., purchase of insurance) people are aware of the possible outcomes but hold little information about their probabilities. In Study 3 we consider an environment in which presentation of the possible outcomes does not add information.

  5. As noted by Blavatskyy (2005), influential models, like cumulative prospect theory, cannot capture behavior in the Allais and St. Petersburg problems with the same set of parameters.

  6. This rule is similar but not identical to the priority rule in the priority heuristic (Brandstätter et al. 2006). According to this rule, reasons are considered in the order: minimum gain, probability of minimum gain and maximum gain. Because there are no explicit probabilities available, the priority-tie-breaking rule skips the second reason.

References

  • Allais, Maurice. (1953). “Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine,” Econometrica 21, 503–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barron, Gregory M. and Ido Erev. (2003). “Small Feedback-Based Decisions and Their Limited Correspondence to Description-Based Decisions,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 16, 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, Daniel. (1738). “Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk,” Comentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae. Translated and reprinted in Econometrica 22, 23–36, (1954).

  • Birnbaum, Michael H. (1992). “Violations of Monotonicity and Contextual Effects in Choice-Based Certainty Equivalents,” Psychological Science 3, 310–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael H. and Teresa Martin. (2003). “Generalization across People, Procedures, and Predictions: Violations of Stochastic Dominance and Coalescing.” In Sandra L. Schneider and James Shanteau (eds), Emerging Perspectives on Decision Research. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2005). “Back to the St. Petersburg Paradox?” Management Science 51, 677–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandstätter, Eduard, Gerd Gigerenzer, and Ralph Hertwig. (2006). “The Priority Heuristic: Making Choices Without Trade-offs,” Psychological Review 113, 409–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, Alain and Peter Wakker. (1999). “An Axiomatization of Cumulative Prospect Theory for Decision Under Risk,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 18(2), 137–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erev, Ido, Thomas S. Wallsten, and David V. Budescu. (1994). “Simultaneous Over- and Underconfidence: The Role of Error in Judgment Processes,” Psychological Review 101, 519–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erev, Ido, Dvorit Shimonowitch, Amos Schurr, and Ralph Hertwig. (2008). “Base Rates: How to Make the Intuitive Mind Appreciate or Neglect Them.” In Henning Plessner, Cornelia Betsch and Tilmann Betsch (eds), Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, Klaus. (2000). “Beware of Samples! A Cognitive-Ecological Sampling Approach to Judgment Biases,” Psychological Review 107, 659–676.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, Klaus, Thomas Armbruster, Stefanie Nickel, Eva Walther, and Judith Asbeck. (1996). “Constructive Biases in Social Judgment: Experiments on the Self-Verification of Question Contents,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71, 861–873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Craig R. and Amos Tversky. (1998). “A Belief-Based Account of Decision Under Uncertainty,” Management Science 44, 879–895.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garner, Wendell R. (1954). “Context Effects and the Validity of Loudness Scales,” Journal of Experimental Psychology 48, 218–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, Gerd, Zeno Swijtink, Theodore Porter, Lorraine Daston, John Beatty, and Lorenz Kriiger. (1989). The Empire of Chance. How Probability Changed Science and Everyday Life. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, Larry W., Robert B. Cialdini, and Kathleen M. Carpenter. (1982). “Self-Relevant Scenarios as Mediators of Likelihood Estimates and Compliance: Does Imagining Make it So?” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 43, 89–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, Robin, Sarah Lichtenstein, and Paul Slovic. (1993). “Valuing Environmental Resources: A Constructive Approach,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 7, 177–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert P. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasher, Lynn, David Goldstein, and Thomas Toppino. (1977). “Frequency and the Conference of Referential Validity,” Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 16, 107–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbaugh, William T., Kate Krause, and Lise Vesterlund. (2004). “Prospect Theory in Choice and Pricing Tasks,” EconPapers (No. 2002-2), University of Oregon Economics Department Working Papers, available at: http://econpapers.repec.org/paper/oreuoecwp/2002-02.htm.

  • Hertwig, Ralph, Gregory M. Barron, Elke Weber, and Ido Erev. (2004). “Decisions from Experience and the Effect of Rare Events in Risky Choice,” Psychological Science 15, 534–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, Ralph, Gregory M. Barron, Elke Weber, and Ido Erev. (2006). “The Role of Information Sampling in Risky Choice.” In Klaus Fiedler and Peter Juslin (eds), Information Sampling and Adaptive Cognition. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, Ralph, Gerd Gigerenzer, and Ulrich Hoffrage. (1997). “The Reiteration Effect in Hindsight Bias,” Psychological Review 104, 194–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haruvy, Ernan, Ido Erev, and Doron Sonsino. (2001). “The Medium Prizes Paradox: Evidence from a Simulated Casino,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 22, 251–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ish Shalom, Taly. (2004). “Rats, Humans, and the Common Ratio Effect.” M.Sc. Thesis, Haifa, Israel: Technion Israel Institute of Technology.

  • Jorland, Gérard. (1987). “The Saint Petersburg Paradox 1713–1937.” In Lorenz Krüger, Lorraine J. Daston, and Michael Heidelberger (eds), The Probabilistic Revolution Vol. I: Ideas in History. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kareev, Yaakov. (2000). “Seven (Indeed, Plus or Minus Two) and the Detection of Correlations,” Psychological Review 107, 397–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, Gordon D. (1988). “Toward an Instance Theory of Automatization,” Psychological Review 95, 492–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. Duncan and Howard Raiffa. (1957). Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, Craig R.M., Victor S. Ferreira, Laurie A. Mikkelsen, Kristine J. McDermott, and Ryan P. Skrable. (2001). “Do Conditional Hypotheses Target Rare Events?” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 85, 291–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, Martin J. and Ariel Rubinstein. (1998). “Games with Procedurally Rational Players,” American Economic Review 88, 834–847.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prelec, Drazen. (2000). “Compound Invariant Weighting Functions in Prospect Theory.” In Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (eds), Choices, Values, and Frames. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Neil, Nick Chater, and Gordon D.A. Brown. (2006). “Decision by Sampling,” Cognitive Psychology 53, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman. (1992). “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 9, 195–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos and Derek J. Koehler. (1994). “Support Theory: A Nonextensional Representation of Subjective Probability,” Psychological Review 101, 547–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. Kip. (1989). “Prospective Reference Theory: Toward an Explanation of the Paradoxes,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 2, 235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, Peter P. and Amos Tversky. (1993). “An Axiomatization of Cumulative Prospect Theory,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 7, 147–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Elke U. and Britt Kirsner. (1996). “Reasons for Rank-dependent Utility Evaluation,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 14, 41–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Elke U., Sharoni Shafir, and Ann-Renée Blais. (2004). “Predicting Risk Sensitivity in Humans and Lower Animals: Risk as Variance or Coefficient of Variation,” Psychological Review 111, 430–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, George and Richard Gonzalez. (1998). “Common Consequence Conditions in Decision Making under Risk,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 16, 115–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, George and Richard Gonzalez. (1999). “Nonlinear Decision Weights in Choice Under Uncertainty,” Management Science 45, 74–85.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ido Erev.

Additional information

*We are grateful to Valerie M. Chase and Laura Wiles for editing the manuscript. We also thank the Jewish Communities of Germany Research Fund for a grant to the first author (Technion V.P.R. fund), and the Swiss National Science Foundation for their support of the third author (Grants 100013-107741/1 and 100014-118283/1). Part of this research was conducted while Ido Erev was a Marvin Bower Fellow at the Harvard Business School.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Erev, I., Glozman, I. & Hertwig, R. What impacts the impact of rare events. J Risk Uncertainty 36, 153–177 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9035-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-008-9035-z

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation