Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

US Responsibility for War Crimes in Iraq

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper examines the recent actions by the United States in Iraq in the light of just war principles, and sets forth a program for holding accountable those most responsible for war crimes in Iraq.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a philosophical account of war crimes that emphasizes a humanitarian rather than a justice-oriented approach, see May (2006).

  2. The principle of alternative possibilities states that it is a necessary condition of moral responsibility that an agent have the ability to do otherwise than what she did, failed to do, or attempted to do, as the case may be at the time that she performs the act, omission, or attempt.

  3. George Tenet called the evidence for Iraq’s possession of weapons of mass destruction a ‘slam dunk,’ when in fact it is to this day rather weak at best.

  4. For discussions of these topics, see Corlett (2003, Chaps. 5–6), Honderich (2004), and Wilkins (1991).

  5. As John Rawls states, ‘Decent peoples have a right to war in self-defense’ (Rawls 1999, p. 92).

  6. Rawls argues that ‘Well-ordered peoples, both liberal and decent, do not initiate war against one another; they go to war only when they sincerely and reasonably believe that their safety and security are seriously endangered by the expansionist policies of outlaw states’ (Rawls 1999, pp. 90–91). Rawls also notes that the right to go to war includes the right to defend one’s allies (p. 91). For a statement of general just war doctrine, see Rawls (1999, pp. 94–105). See also Walzer (2000). For an introduction to just war principles as they relate to war crimes, see Ellis (2001).

  7. I owe this point to Tom Weston.

  8. Gewirth’s phrase is ‘resorting to war on wrongful grounds’ (Gewirth 2001, p. 49). Also see Burleigh T. Wilkins’ claim that ‘planning and waging wars’ also constitute war crimes (Wilkins 2001, p. 85).

  9. One of numerous examples here is Hiley (2006). For a discussion of this book, see Corlett (2006b).

  10. For cautions against this position and in favor of states holding their own war crimes trials, see Wilkins (2001, pp. 86f).

  11. See Corlett (2006a, b, Chap. 5) for a discussion of these concepts.

  12. For an analysis of the notion of collective remorse see Gilbert (2001).

  13. This principle of power to effect change is borrowed from French (1984).

  14. These are the main conditions of responsibility as discussed in Corlett (2006a, Chap. 1).

  15. Nicholas Calio served as the assistant to President Bush from 2001 to 2003 and at the President’s request lobbied Congress for approval of the Iraq war resolution.

  16. For discussions of proportional sentencing, see Davis (1992) and von Hirsch and Ashworth (2005).

  17. Recently in San Diego, California, Lance Corporal Pennington and several of his military colleagues were tried for the killing of an Iraqi civilian during wartime. Their defense was in large part that the stress of war caused them to act in ways that clouded their better judgments, and eventuated in the killing. Their defense attorneys argued that they killed the civilian because they thought that the safety of their fellow troops was at stake. They were recently tried but found not guilty of all major charges, and shall serve no time in prison for their killing of the Iraqi civilian, a fact that neither denies. One is reminded here of President Bush’s promise prior to the invasion that no US troops would be punished for their service in Iraq. But one question to ask here is if such troops were rightly convicted of the war crime in question and duly sentenced to life in prison, how much more ought those who placed him there to be punished if duly convicted of war crimes of a much more serious variety, quantitatively speaking?

  18. Indeed, US public support for the invasion and occupation was for a few years just prior to and during the invasion so strong that several of those who even questioned its moral veracity were often angrily charged with anti-patriotism, or treason.

  19. That states can engage in terrorism is argued in Corlett (2003, Chap. 5).

  20. For those who require a sound reason for punishing those who kill others unjustly, there is the Feinbergian one that to kill another is to set back their legitimate vital welfare and ulterior interests in achieving certain morally legitimate goals that constitute our meaning in life. To kill another unjustly is to rob her of her most central interests in pursuing her own projects that in turn largely, if not wholly, define who she is. It is, in short, to extinguish another’s self that is necessary for the fulfillment of her projects that bring meaning to her life. And while death is surely not always or necessarily a harm to the one who dies, it is clearly such a harm in most cases for the reasons just cited. As Thomas Nagel puts it: ‘If death is an evil at all, it cannot be because of its positive features, but only because of what it deprives us of’ (Nagel 1979, p. 1). After all, ‘If death is an evil, it is the loss of life.’ (p. 3). Moreover, ‘life is all we have and the loss of it is the greatest loss we can sustain’ (p. 1). Insofar as punishment and compensatory justice are concerned, it is important to bear in mind that ‘any death is the loss of some life that its victim would have led had he not died at that or any earlier point. We know perfectly well what it would be for him to have had it instead of losing it, and there is no difficulty in identifying the loser’ (pp. 7–8). This is especially true concerning acts of unjust killings such as in Iraq. Thus the unjust killings of hundreds of thousands of Iraqis by the US military surely demands justice, not forgiveness, mercy, or reconciliation!

  21. For a discussion of Feinberg’s analysis, see Corlett (2004). For a social psychological study of evil, see Zimbardo (2007).

  22. For other retributivist analyses, see von Hirsch (1976, 1987, 1993), von Hirsch and Ashworth (1992), and Kleinig (1973).

  23. See Ryberg (2004) for a criticism of proportionalism, and of von Hirsch’s proportionalism in particular.

  24. For philosophical investigations of the concept of patriotism, see Primoratz (2002). Also see the paper collected in The Journal of Ethics 13:4 (2009).

  25. For an analysis of collective responsibility, see Corlett (2006a, Chap. 5).

  26. For a discussion of capital punishment, see Corlett (2006a, Chap. 6). Assumed here is the idea that capital punishment stands among the harshest of state responses to severe war crimes, though one ought to remain mindful of Søren Kierkegaard’s remark that the torment of despair is not being able to die (Kierkegaard 1941, p. 150).

  27. Assumed here is the plausibility of the claim that capital punishment is in some cases morally justified as the objections to it are neutralized or defeated (Corlett 2006a, Chap. 6). Also see Primoratz (1989, Chap. 8).

  28. I borrow this principle from Dworkin (1978). But it is similarly found in von Hirsch and Ashworth (1992).

  29. This point is found in Corlett (2006a, Chap. 4), as well as in von Hirsch and Ashworth (1992, p. 198).

  30. von Hirsch and Ashworth (1992, p. 401).

  31. As Rawls said of one of the conditions of morally justified civil disobedience, it is a ‘practical condition’ (see on this Corlett 2003, pp. 34–35).

  32. The conditions of morally justified terrorism are found and defended in Corlett (2003, Chap. 5).

  33. For an analysis of the concept of forgiveness, see Corlett (2006a, Chap. 6).

References

  • Corlett, J. Angelo. 2003. Terrorism: a philosophical analysis. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. Angelo. 2004. Evil. Analysis 64: 81–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. Angelo. 2006a. Responsibility and punishment, 3rd ed. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. Angelo. 2006b. Review of Hiley, Doubt and the demands of democratic citizenship. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8283.

  • Davis, Michael. 1992. To make the punishment fit the crime. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking rights seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Anthony. 2001. Introduction. In War crimes and collective wrongdoing, ed. Aleksandar Jokic. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1970. Doing and deserving. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 2003. Problems at the roots of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter A. 1984. Corporate and collective responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, Alan. 2001. War crimes and human rights. In War crimes and collective wrongdoing, ed. Aleksandar Jokic. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Margaret. 2001. Collective remorse. In War crimes and collective wrongdoing, ed. Aleksandar Jokic. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiley, D. 2006. Doubt and the demands of democratic citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (ed.). 2004. After the terror. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, Søren. 1941. Fear and trembling and the sickness unto death Walter Lowrie trans. Garden City: Doubleday & Company, Inc.

  • Kleinig, John. 1973. Punishment and desert. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Sanford. 1973. Responsibility for crimes of war. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2: 244–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Larry. 2006. War crimes and just war. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1979. Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primoratz, Igor. 1989. Justifying legal punishment. New Jersey: Humanities Press International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primoratz, Igor (ed.). 2002. Patriotism. Amherst: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. The law of peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryberg, Jesper. 2004. The ethics of proportionate punishment. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew. 1976. Doing justice. Boston: Northeastern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew. 1987. Past or future crimes. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew. 1992. Proportionate punishments. In Principled sentencing, ed. Andrew Ashworth, and Andrew von Hirsch. Boston: Northeastern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew. 1993. Censure and sanctions. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Hirsch, Andrew, and Andrew Ashworth. 2005. Proportionate sentencing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 2000. Just and unjust wars, 2nd ed. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, Burleigh T. 1991. Terrorism and collective responsibility. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, Burleigh T. 2001. Whose trials? Whose reconciliation? In War crimes and collective wrongdoing, ed. Aleksandar Jokić, 85–96. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimbardo, Philip. 2007. The lucifer effect. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented at the Conference on Punishing War Crimes, Genocide, and Crimes Against Humanity, University of Copenhagen, 20–21 September 2007. I am grateful to the conference organizer, Jesper Ryberg and other participants, including an anonymous referee for Res Publica for their insightful comments that assisted in the devising of this draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Angelo Corlett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Corlett, J.A. US Responsibility for War Crimes in Iraq. Res Publica 16, 227–244 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9108-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9108-0

Keywords

Navigation