Skip to main content
Log in

Ethical Economics or Economical Ethics? Considerations out of Carl Menger

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Carl Menger advanced a narrow definition of exact or theoretical economics. Theoretical economics is the study of the self-interested aspect of human efforts made to meet needs. One implication of this definition, Menger argues, is a strict demarcation between ethics and economics. Menger advances this demarcation against what he calls the “ethical orientation” of the German Historical School. A problem with Menger’s demarcation is that one cannot easily define and operationalize the concept of “self-interest” so as to exclude issues reasonably considered “ethical.” Humans are ethical-rule-following beings. Following rules and abiding by social norms is a part of most people’s “interests” as they themselves understand them. From ideas in behavioral and experimental economics, we see that rules can be constitutive of one’s interests, not just constraining. Ethical sensibilities are not only part of the explanadum in economics, but are, in certain instances, an important aspect of the explanation. Insofar as self-interest interrelates with ethical phenomena, economists, even of the theoretical sort, should pay attention (as did a number of early modern political economists and philosophers) to the following: (1) the ways in which contextual norms of propriety and interests interpenetrate; (2) the sociological and psychological mechanisms by which ethical sensibilities and interests are transmitted; and (3) the differences that ethical sensibilities can make for material or economic outcomes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. References to Menger’s works: References to the Investigations into the Method of the Social Sciences, hereafter Investigations, are to Menger (2009). References to the Principles of Economics, hereafter Principles, are to Menger (1994). Throughout this essay, italics in quotes are original to the source unless otherwise indicated.

  2. On this point, see Milford (1990, 227).

  3. Daniel Klein (2012, 55–58) explains why “emergent convention” might be a better descriptor of what Menger describes than “spontaneous order.” “Menger studies the organic basis of the conventions by which the catallaxy works, but does not make a fuss over the catallaxy [the spontaneous order] itself…He never marvels at the division of labor and knowledge that makes a woolen coat, nor expounds on the importance of liberty to the felicity and beauty of such concatenations” (57–58).

  4. For an attempt to construct a unified theory of value, along the lines of Austrian economists and philosophers, see Grassl (2017). Drawing especially from Franz Brentano and Menger, Grassl articulates a theory of value rooted at once in Aristotlean ontology and ethics and the insights of marginal economic analysis. The theory has the virtue of overcoming the division between economics and ethics and could, at least in principle, accommodate some of the difficulties in Menger treated in this article.

  5. In Hayek the demarcation seems to be is overcome. For a relevant discussion see Hayek’s (1961) discussion of the non-sequitur of J.K. Galbraith’s notion of the dependence effect. See also Dold and Lewis (2021), especially their analysis of the social psychology of Hayek’s The Sensory Order. See also the comments on Hayek as spanning the two Austrian value theory traditions in Grassl (2017).

  6. See Sen’s (1977) distinction between “commitment” and “sympathy.”

  7. Following Hobbes, one might maintain that knavery is the norm and that we erect Leviathan to prevent and constructively channel knavish behavior. A problem concerns monitoring costs. Perhaps one might conceive of the origins of conventions of property and political authority in terms of strategic knavery. But maintaining those conventions through external enforcement mechanisms would seem, as Hume recognizes, quite difficult. For discussion along these lines see Hargreaves Heap (2021, 107–12).

  8. Menger of course read Smith, although not always carefully. In a remarkably off-target passage he says:

    "It is [Adam Smith’s and his followers’] defective understanding of the unintentionally created social institutions and their significance for the economy [that constitutes their failure]. It is the opinion appearing chiefly in their writings that the institutions of economy are always the intended product of the common will of society as such, results of expressed agreement of members of society or of positive legislation" (Investigations, 172).

    Especially in his later lectures to Crown Prince Rudolf, Menger was nonetheless quite Smithian. But in his methodology, and in aspects of his analysis of institutions, he would have done well to dwell further in Smith’s ideas, especially his ideas in The Theory of Moral Sentiments.

  9. See also Paganelli (2009; 2011; 2015).

  10. These examples draw from Sugden (2005, 154–55).

  11. For an argument that Smith misrepresents Hume see Matson et al. (2019). Hume, like Smith, recognizes that individuals do not act, in the first instance, because of estimations of usefulness. Hume sees that individuals are ethical-rule-following beings, who learn to associate a certain agreeableness with rule-following. He doesn’t, however, emphasize the point nearly as much or as well as Smith.

  12. Even knavery in Smith is often governed, or at least channeled, by group-approval dynamics. For discussion see Levy and Peart (2009).

  13. See Hargreave Heap (2021, 111–12) for discussion of Tocqueville in similar context.

  14. McCloskey (2016, 373–374) discusses Taylor’s ideas and affirms their parallel to her own ideas.

References

  • Becker, G. S. (1981). Altruism in the family and selfishness in the market place. Economica, 84(189), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, K. H. (1972). Toward the development of a cultural economics. Social Science Quarterly, 53(2), 267–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. (1998). Endogenous preferences: The cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions. Journal of Economic Literature, 36, 75–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. (2016). The Moral Economy: Why Good Incentives Are No Substitute for Good Citizens. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S., & Polanía-Reyes, S. (2012). Economic Incentives and Social Preferences: Substitutes or Complements? Journal of Economic Literature, 50(2), 368–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Edmund. (1999). Selected Works of Edmund Burke. In Francis Canavan (Ed.), 3 vol. (Vol. 2). Liberty Fund.

  • Camerer, C., & Thaler, R. H. (1995). Anomalies: Ultimatums, Dictators, and Manners. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2), 209–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, G. M. (2020). Commerce and Manners in Edmund Burke’s Political Economy. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cubeddu, R. (1997). The ‘Irrelevance’ of Ethics for the Austrian School. In P. Koslowski (Ed.), Methodology of the Social Sciences, Ethics, and Economics in the Newer Historical School: From Max Weber and Rickert to Sombart and Rothacker (pp. 259–284). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dold, M. F., & Lewis, P. (2021). F.A. Hayek on the political economy of endogenous preferences: An historical overview and contemporary assessment. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/352170207_FA_Hayek_on_the_Political_Economy_of_Endogenous_Preferences_An_Historical_Overview_and_Contemporary_Assessment. Accessed 12 Sep 2022.

  • Fabian, R., & Simons, P. M. (2011). The Second Austrian School of Value Theory. In W. Grassl & B. Smith (Eds.), Austrian Economics: Historical and Philosophical Background (2nd ed., pp. 37–101). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Hoff, K. (2011). Introduction: tastes, castes, and culture: The influence of society on preferences. The Economic Journal, 121(556), 396–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, A. J. (1984). Microeconomics, norms, and rationality. Economic Development and Cultural Change, 32(4), 683–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S. (1997). A Constitution for knaves crowds out civic virtue. The Economic Journal, 107(443), 1043–1053.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., Pommerehene, W. W., & Gygi, B. (1993). Economics indoctrination or selection? Some empirical results. Journal of Economic Education, 24, 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, D. (1994). A Positive account of property rights. Social Philosophy and Policy, 11(2), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grassl, W. (2011). Markets and Morality: Austrian Perspectives and the Economic Approach to Human Behaviour. In W. Grassl & B. Smith (Eds.), Austrian Economics: Historical and Philosophical Background (2nd ed., pp. 107–37). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grassl, W. (2017). Toward a unified theory of value: From Austrian economics to Austrian philosophy. Axiomathes, 27, 531–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haller, M. (2004). Mixing economics and ethics: Carl Menger vs Gustav von Schmoller. Social Science Information, 43(1), 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heap, H., & Shaun, P. (2021). Two accounts of the relation between political economy and economics (and Why It Matters Which Account Is Better). Social Philosophy and Policy, 37, 103–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, I. (1995). The teachings of the puritans about ordinary work. The Evangelical Quarterly, 67(3), 195–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. (1961). The non sequitur of the dependence effect. Southern Economic Journal, 27(4), 346–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2007). Meanings of methodological individualism. Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(2), 211–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2009). Institutional economics into the twenty-first century. Studi e Note Di Economica, 15(1), 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoff, K., & Stiglitz, J. E. (2016). Striving for balance in economics: Towards a theory of the social determination of behavior. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 126(Part B), 25–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmås, T. H., Kjerstad, E., Lurås, H., & Straume, O. R. (2010). Does Monetary Punishment Crowd Out Pro-Social Motivation? A Natural Experiment on Hospital Length of Stay. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 75(2), 261–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1998). An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. In T. L. Beauchamp (Ed). Clarendon Press.

  • Hume, D. (2000). A Treatise of Human Nature. In D. F. Norton, & M. J. Norton (Eds.), Oxford University Press.

  • Keynes, J. N. (2017). The Scope and Method of Political Economy. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. (2012). Knowledge and Coordination: A Liberal Interpretation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavoie, D. (1990). Hermeneutics, Subjectivity, and the Lester/Malchup Debate: Toward a More Anthropological Approach to Empirical Economics. In W. J. Samuels (Ed.), Economics as Discourse: An Analysis of the Language of Economics (pp. 167–184). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lavoie, D., & Storr, V. H. (2011). Distinction or dichotomy: rethinking the line between thymology and praxeology. Review of Austrian Economics, 24, 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D. M., & Peart, S. J. (2009). Adam Smith and the Place of Faction. In J. T. Young (Ed.), Elgar Companion to Adam Smith (pp. 335–345). Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matson, E. W., Doran, C., & Klein, D. B. (2019). Hume and smith on utility, agreeableness, propriety, and moral approval. History of European Ideas, 54(5), 675–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, D. N. (2011). Bourgeois Dignity: Why Economics Can’t Explain the Modern World. Paperback. University of Chicago Press.

  • McCloskey, D. N. (2017). Bourgeois Equality: How Ideas, Not Capital or Institutions, Enriched the World. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menger, C. (1994). Principles of Economics. In J. Dingwall, & B. F. Hoselitz (Eds.), Libertarian Press, Inc.

  • Menger, C. (2009). Investigations Into the Method of the Social Sciences with Special Reference to Economics. In L. Schneider (Ed.), Translated by Francis J. Nock. The Ludwig von Mises Institute.

  • Milford, K. (1990). Menger’s methodology. History of Political Economy, 22(S1), 215–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1977). On austrian methodology. Synthese, 36, 353–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paganelli, M. P. (2009). Smithian Answers to Some Puzzling Results in the Experimental Literature. In J. T. Young (Ed.), The Elgar Companion to Adam Smith (pp. 181–192). Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganelli, M. P. (2011). The same face of the two Smith’s: Adam Smith and Vernon Smith. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 78(3), 246–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paganelli, M. P. (2015). Recent engagements with Adam Smith and the scottish enlightenment. History of Political Economy, 47(3), 363–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prisching, M. (1993). Schmoller’s Theory of Society. History of Economic Ideas, 1/2(3/1):117–42.

  • Rubinstein, A. (2006). A sceptic’s comment on the study of economics. The Economic Journal, 116(March), C1-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schäffle, A. E. F. (2014). The Ethical Side of the Theory of Value in National Economics. In J. S. Chipman (Ed.), German Utility Theory: Analysis and Translations (pp. 334–60). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmoller, G. (1894). The Idea of Justice in Political Economy. Translated by Ernst L. von Halle and Carl L. Schutz. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 4, 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(4), 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1981). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. In R. H. Campbell, & A. S. Skinner (Eds.), 2 vols. Liberty Fund.

  • Smith, A. 1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. In D. D. Raphael, & A. L. Macfie (Eds.), Liberty Fund.

  • Smith, B. (1990). Aristotle, Menger, Mises: An essay in the metaphysics of economics. History of Political Economy, 22(S1), 263–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. L. (1962). An experimental study of competitive market behavior. Journal of Political Economy, 70(2), 111–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. L., & Wilson, B. J. (2019). Humanomics: Moral Sentiments and the Wealth of Nations for the Twenty-First Century. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J. (1971). Smith’s Travel on the Ship of State. In The Economist as Preacher and Other Essays (pp. 136–45). University of Chicago Press.

  • Sugden, R. (2005). The Economics of Rights, Co-Operation, and Welfare (2nd ed.). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titmuss, R. M. (1970). The Gift Relationship. Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. de. (2000). Democracy in America. Translated by Harvey C. Mansfield and Delba Winthrop. University of Chicago Press.

  • Wilson, B. J. (2020). The Property Species: Mine, Yours, and the Human Mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (1993). The moral sense. American Political Science Review, 87(1), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yagi, K. (1997). Carl Menger and the Historicism in Economics. In P. Koslowski (Ed.), Methodology of the Social Sciences, Ethics, and Economics in the Newer Historical School: From Max Weber and Rickert to Sombart and Rothacker (pp. 231–258). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. T. (1997). Economics as a Moral Science: The Political Economy of Adam Smith. Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. T. (2020). George Stigler’s Adam Smith: Successes and Failures. In C. Freedman (Ed.), George Stigler: Enigmatic Price Theorist of the Twentieth Century (pp. 293–393). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For valuable feedback, I thank Dan Klein, Karras Lambert, Marcus Shera, an anonymous referee, and the participants at the 2021 NYU Menger conference. A special word of thanks to the Menger conference organizers, David Harper, Mario Rizzo, and Daniel Nientiedt.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Erik W. Matson.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author has no competing financial or non-financial interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Matson, E.W. Ethical Economics or Economical Ethics? Considerations out of Carl Menger. Rev Austrian Econ 36, 311–330 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-022-00596-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-022-00596-7

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation