Skip to main content
Log in

Natura naturans, natura naturata

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, which is concerned with philosophical methodology as it might affect social science and ethics, the endeavor is to explore the depth and implications of Buchanan’s interest in Spinoza. After establishing their connection, the paper explores the parallels between Spinoza’s “dualism” and Buchanan’s own dualism and how that can shed light on Buchanan’s distinction between constitutional and operational modalities. Given their analogous perspectives, the paper then considers the possibility of dimensional shifts in the dualism, such that what was once a constitutional perspective becomes operational and how that ability to shift might affect various research agendas in the social sciences and ethics. Finally, we raise the question of how separate are the two levels and can they be brought together. In a Spinozistic framework, they ultimately would collapse into a monism, but the conclusion here is that for Buchanan there must always be a gap between them. As a result, the effort to resolve the tension between the dimensions may signal future research agendas in ethics and political economy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I did this with my “Sociality and Social Contract: A Spinozistic Perspective” (1985).

  2. The text from the Ethica (Spinoza 2002) reads as follows: “Before going any further, I wish here to explain, what we should understand by nature viewed as active (natura naturans), and nature viewed as passive (natura naturata). I say to explain, or rather call attention to it, for I think that, from what has been said, it is sufficiently clear, that by nature viewed as active we should understand that which is in itself, and is conceived through itself, or those attributes of substance, which express eternal and infinite essence, in other words (Prop. xiv., Coroll. i., and Prop. xvii., Coroll. ii) God, in so far as he is considered as a free cause. By nature viewed as passive I understand all that which follows from the necessity of the nature of God, or of any of the attributes of God, that is, all the modes of the attributes of God, in so far as they are considered as things which are in God, and which without God cannot exist or be conceived” (1p29s). Our point in what follows is to draw an analogy to this distinction and not literally apply Spinoza’s metaphysics to Buchanan’s world view. Whether Spinoza’s metaphysics would apply to Buchanan I do not know, but the distinction between natura naturans and natura naturata can be used usefully I believe without that metaphysics. However, as we shall see below without that metaphysical base, the distinction becomes more relativized than Spinoza would allow.

  3. Obviously there are many complications here including Spinoza’s idea of infinite modes on the one hand and the problematic nature of individuals on the other. Nonetheless, the foregoing description is not misleading.

  4. See Spinoza’s Letter to Oldenberg (Ep32) Spinoza (1928) discusses the idea that a worm in the bloodstream views its world as complete whole even though that whole is actually part of a much larger system.

  5. In political philosophy, Rasmussen and I employ this same sort of dualistic perspective in our distinction between norms and metanorms. See Rasmussen and Den Uyl (2005, 33ff).

  6. Boettke quotes Buchanan as saying: “[The economist’s] task includes the derivation of the institutional order itself from the set of elementary behavioral hypotheses with which he commences” (Boettke 2014: 352). Nothing about this view requires limiting one’s frame of analysis to traditional social contract assumptions and procedures.

  7. Continuing our analogy even here, the actual rules arrived at are the natura naturata of the constitutional process that gives rise to them. Our question about the ontic gap, though formulated somewhat differently, applies here as well.

  8. See for example Buchanan (1999a, 77; 2001d, 87, 113; 2001a, 161). I am speaking here of the essence of decision making and not the “veil of uncertainty” which Buchanan uses in constitutional contexts.

  9. Buchanan cites G.L.S. Shackle in numerous places in this essay and elsewhere (e.g., 1999a, 287 where he admits the influence; 1999b, 35–37; 2000, 140–150 passim; 2001b, 38–39, 171–184; 2001c, 293–298 passim; 2001d, 153–157.

  10. See my response to Buchanan’s rejection of teleology in Den Uyl (2009).

  11. Earlier Buchanan was taken with the work of David Gautier in this regard. See Buchanan (2001b, 437–468).

  12. Another example from a different source might be Barden and Murphy (2011).

References

  • Barden, G., & Murphy, T. (2011). Law and justice in community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. J. (2014). Fearing freedom: the intellectual and spiritual challenge to liberalism. The Independent Review, 18(3), 343–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999a). The logical foundations of constitutional liberty. Vol. 1 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. ([1969]1999b). Cost and choice. Vol. 6 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2000). Economic inquiry and its logic. Vol. 12 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2001a). Choice contracts, and constitutions. Vol. 16 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2001b). Moral science and moral order. Vol. 17 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2001c). Federalism, liberty and the law. Vol. 18 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2001d). Ideas, persons and events. Vol. 19 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. ([1962] 1999). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Vol. 3 of the collected works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Den Uyl, D. J. (1985). Sociality and social contract: a spinozistic perspective. Studia Spinozana, 1, 19–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Den Uyl, D. J. (2005). Spinoza and Oakeshott. In C. Abel & T. Fuller (Eds.), The intellectual legacy of Michael Oakeshott. Charlottesville: Imprint Academics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Den Uyl, D. J. (2009). Homo Moralis. Review of Austrian Economics, 22, 349–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2011). The order of pulbic reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, D. B., & Den Den, D. J. (2005). Norms of liberty. University Park: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (2002). Ethics in Spinoza: Complete works. In M. Morgan (Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

  • Spinoza, B. (1928). The correspondence of Spinoza, translated and edited by A. Wolf. London: George Allen & Unwim, Ltd.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas J. Den Uyl.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Den Uyl, D.J. Natura naturans, natura naturata. Rev Austrian Econ 27, 175–182 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-014-0261-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-014-0261-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation