Skip to main content
Log in

Pluralism and heterodoxy in economic methodology

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Economists work within models that are simplified depictions of reality. An argument for a pluralistic understanding of economics is that different approaches lend insight by looking at different phenomena from different viewpoints. While all economists can benefit from taking a pluralistic approach to understanding economics, Austrian school economists must be more pluralistic in their understanding and presentation of ideas than mainstream economists if they want their ideas to have an impact on mainstream economics. Despite the argument for a pluralistic understanding of economics, in research, as in other activities, specialization increases productivity. While Austrian school economists can benefit from taking a pluralistic approach to understanding economics, they are likely to be most productive in their research by specializing in the development of Austrian school methods and ideas.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In each case, at least one of the pioneers in those areas who helped them achieve mainstream acceptability has won the Nobel prize in economics: James Buchanan for public choice, Douglass North for the new institutional economics, and Vernon Smith for experimental economics.

  2. Lawson (2003, 2006) argues that despite a variety of approaches, the mainstream only accepts ideas that are structured in a mathematical framework, and is not pluralistic because it rejects non-mathematical “open system” analysis.

  3. This brings to mind a comment a colleague of mine made over lunch that “If you haven’t shown it in a general equilibrium model, you don’t know it’s true.” Because all models, including general equilibrium models, are simpler than the real world, if you have shown it in a general equilibrium model you also don’t know it’s true. Lunchtime conversations do not carry the same weight as journal articles in print, so this observation is relegated to a footnote, but it illustrates his commitment of one researcher to undertaking research within a specific theoretical framework.

  4. See, for example, Coleman (1990), who applied economic ideas to take a rational choice approach to sociology, making a substantial impact in that discipline and altering the dominant paradigm.

References

  • Arrow, K. J., & Debreu, G. (1954). Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica, 22, 265–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bator, F. M. (1957). The simple analytics of welfare maximization. American Economic Review, 47, 22–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug, M. (1980). The methodology of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. J (2007) Methodological Pluralism and the Austrian School of Economics? Available at: (http://austrianeconomists.typepad.com/weblog/2007/12/methodological.html). Accessed 5 Aug 2010.

  • Boland, L. A. (1982). The foundations of economic method. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell, B. J. (1982). Beyond positivism: economic methodology in the twentieth century. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. S. (1990). Foundations of social theory. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow, S. C. (2002). Methodological pluralism and pluralism of method. In G. Hodgson (Ed.), A modern reader in institutional and evolutionary economics (pp. 136–146). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1953). Essays in positive economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fullbrook, E. (2005) Concealed ideologies: a PAE view of ideology in economics. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Association for Heterodox Economics, London.

  • Garnett, R. F., Jr. (2010). Why Should Austrian Economists Be Pluralists? Review of Austrian Economics.

  • Hayek, F. A. (1945). The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35, 519–530.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, J. R. (1939). Value and capital: an inquiry into some fundamental principles of economic theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (1989). Economic models and methodology. New York: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (2008). Pluralism versus heterodoxy in economics and the social sciences. Journal of Philosophical Economics, 1(2), 51–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagel, J. H., Battalio, R. C., Rachlin, H., & Green, L. (1981). Demand curves for animal consumers. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 96, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. (1991). Anomalies: the endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5, 193–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landreth, H., & Colander, D. C. (2002). History of economic thought (4th ed.). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (2003). Reorienting economics. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (2006). The nature of heterodox economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 3, 483–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, D. M. (1985). The rhetoric of economics. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, A. W. (1958). The Relation Between Unemployment and the Rate of Change of Money Wage Rates in the United Kingdom, 1862–1957. Economica, 25, 283–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1947). Foundations of economic analysis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1983). My life philosophy. The American Economist, 27(2), 5–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A., & Solow, R. M. (1960). Analytical aspects of anti-inflation policy. American Economic Review, 40, 177–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V. (1994). Economics in the laboratory. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 8, 113–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J., & Becker, G. S. (1977). De Gustibus Non Est Desputandum. American Economic Review, 67, 76–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Subrick, J. R., & Young, A. T. (2010). Nobelity and Novelty: Finn Kydland and Edward Prescott’s contributions viewed from Vienna. Review of Austrian Economics, 23(1), 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Graaf, J. (1957). Theoretical welfare economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Randall G. Holcombe.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Holcombe, R.G. Pluralism and heterodoxy in economic methodology. Rev Austrian Econ 24, 57–65 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-010-0125-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-010-0125-1

Keywords

JEL Codes

Navigation