Skip to main content
Log in

Austrian economics and the analysis of labor markets

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Theory and policy relating to labor markets is dominated by the mainstream labor market model, although a less well-known, socioeconomic version can also be identified. The mainstream model is methodologically flawed and forced, thereby, to relegate any (serious) investigation of labor market institutions and/or social structures to the margins of its analysis. The socioeconomic account is not so much methodologically flawed, as methodologically ambivalent. While this ambivalence does not actually prevent the investigation of institutions and/or social structures, it does promote ambiguity whenever we inquire into the precise nature of the interaction between them and labor markets. Insights from Austrian economics, when used in collaboration with critical realist methodology, can play a part in augmenting the socioeconomic account, generating a totally new approach to the analysis of labor markets.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I prefer the term “account” to “model” or “theory” because the latter come with so much unwanted baggage. On my understanding, an “account” is a coherent and consistent set of statements designed to systematically explain some aspect of the phenomenon under investigation.

  2. Critical realist ideas in economics can be found in Downward (2003), Lawson (1995, 2003), Lewis (2004), and Fleetwood (1999).

  3. This paper draws upon, while also extending and deepening, ideas first presented in Fleetwood (2006b). The latter paper makes no mention of Austrian economics, although it does elaborate a little more upon the socioeconomic account, and a lot more on the critical realist critique of the deductivist method, and closure conditions, that underpin the mainstream model. Readers wishing to know more about this form of critical realist critique should consult Fleetwood (2006b).

  4. Gerhart and Rynes (2003, 15) clearly have something like this “systematicity” in mind when referring to the “highly interconnected logic of the neoclassical model”.

  5. Saint-Paul (2000) is a good example of this. Misleadingly entitled The Political Economy of Labor Market Institutions, it contains virtually no insights into the nature of institutions (or social structures): in fact, they are not even defined.

  6. While Gerhart and Rynes (2003, 40–44) recognize there is a gap between mainstream theory and reality, in the final analysis they cite both Samualson and Coase to make the point that mainstream theory may not be perfect, but it is probably the best available. It is time we stopped accepting this old chestnut.

  7. The fact that this model can be made more sophisticated does not actually mean the basic principle is, or can be, abandoned. I have never come across a mainstream economist (even one ready to concede that a socioeconomic approach has some validity) who is ready to abandon the idea that wages, supply, and demand for labor are functionally related.

  8. Note well that (Old) Institutionalists have little or nothing in common with New Institutionalists or Neo-Institutionalists who, essentially, attempt to “modify or broaden the mainstream toolkit” (Rogers, 1994, 6).

  9. For discussion of institutions and/or social structures, see Auer (2001), Hodgson (1988, 1999, 2001), Rogers Hollingsworth (2005), Lawson (2005), Rogers (1994), Rutherford (1999), and Searle. I have attempted to clarify the relationship between institutions and social structures in Fleetwood (2006a).

  10. Rules are informal, implicit, and often tacit, whereas regulations are formal, explicit, and never tacit.

  11. Another socioeconomists writes: “Whereas in standard theory, it is assumed that in markets the exchange between supply and demand occurs in abstraction of any power relation or regulation, the term ‘institutions’ implies a socioeconomic regulation of the unbridled working of the markets” Auer (2001, 3).

  12. In a review of economic sociology, Ingham (1996) comes very close in a couple of places to actually stating this sentiment.

  13. A deterministically closed system can be expressed probabilistically and can, thereby, be transposed to a stochastically closed system. Here y and x 1, x 2, … x n are regularly conjoined under some well behaved probabilistic function. In effect, the claim “whenever event x then event y” is transposed into the claim “whenever events x 1, x 2, … x n on average, then event y on average”, or “whenever the average value of events measured by variables x 1, x 2, … x n are what they are, then the average value of event y measured by variable y is what it is”. Stochastically, closed systems, are still closed systems.

  14. Mainstream theorists do, of course, recognize that substitution between labor and capital is not ubiquitous and attempt to deal with it through nonconvex isoquants. “L” shaped isoquants associate one production technique with one capital-labor combination and allow no substitution. Isoquants with n “flat” sections imply n−1 production techniques and allow limited substitution. But, where tangency between the isocost curve and the isoquants is at a corner, factor prices could change without “causing” substitution. Where tangency occurs along the face of one of the “flat” sections of the isoquant, then the choice of technique becomes indeterminate.

  15. Incidentally, this argument works despite the fact that in many cases workers can be substituted for machinery because the mainstream model assumes that this substitution is always possible. It is forced to treat nonsubstitutability as a special case.

  16. Social theorists discussing the so called agency-structure debate tend not to use the term “institution,” and while it seems strange referring to the agency-institution debate, this may be little more than linguistic preference. If institutions are systems of rules, and if rules are distinct from the agents that draw upon, and reproduce them, then most critical realists would be quite happy to consider institutions alongside social structures, as nonagential social phenomena. There should, then, be no problem extending the scope of the agency-structure concept to include agency-institution/structure.

  17. See Fleetwood (1996), footnote of first page, for a comment on the way mainstream economists try to deal with processes.

  18. In any case, a causal-explanation of the agents, structures, and processes involved in making labor markets work, should involve much more than deducing/predicting wage rates and quantities of labor, perhaps in the presence of “imperfections” like institutions or social structures. This preoccupation is, arguably, a hangover from mainstream labor economics.

  19. I wish to thank Nick Wilson, for constantly reminding me not to lose sight of the role of agent when attempting to emphasize the role of social structures. He also expresses a similar antidualist position in Wilson (2004).

  20. Note that Vaughn (quoted earlier) seems to imply that there are two phenomena, markets and institutions (or social structures), but she is not entirely clear.

References

  • Archer, M. (1995). Realist social theory: The morphogenetic approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Auer, P. (2001). Introduction. In P. Auer (Ed.), Changing labor markets in Europe: The role of institutions and policies. Geneva: International Labor Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaulier, S., & Boettke, P. (2004). The really real in economics. In P. Lewis (Ed.), Transforming economics: Perspectives on the critical realist project (pp. 187–201). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1989). The possibility of naturalism. Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. (1997). Where did economics go wrong? Modern economics as a flight from reality. Critical Review, 11, 11–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P., & Storr, V. (2002). Post-classical political economy: Polity, society and economy in Weber, Mises & Hayek. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 61(1), 161–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downward, P. (2003). Applied economics and the critical realist critique. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fevre, R. (1992). The sociology of labor markets. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (1995). Hayek's political economy: The socioeconomics of order. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (1996). Order without equilibrium: A critical realist interpretation of Hayek's notion of spontaneous order. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 20, 729–747.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (1999). Critical realism in economics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (2001). Causal laws, functional relations and tendencies. Review of Political Economy, 13(2), 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleetwood, S. (December, 2002). Why mainstream economics explains nothing at all. Post-Autistic Economics Review, 17.

  • Fleetwood, S. (2006a). ‘Institutions and Social Structures’ paper presented at the Tenth Annual conference of the Japan Association for Evolutionary Economics, University of Hokkaido, Hokkaido, Japan, March.

  • Fleetwood, S. (2006b). Re-thinking labor markets: A critical realist-socioeconomic perspective. Capital and Class, 89, 59–89.

  • Gallaway, L., & Vedder, R. (2003). Ideas versus ideology: The origins of modern labor economics. Journal of Labor Research, XXIV(4), 643–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, B., & Rynes, S. (2003). Compensation: Theory, evidence and strategic implications. Thousand Oakes, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granovetter, M. (1992). The sociological and economic approaches to labor market analysis: A social structural view. In M. Granovetter & R. Swedberg (Eds.), The sociology of economic life. San Fransisco: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. (1946). The meaning of competition. In Individualism and Economic Order. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. (1960). The constitution of liberty. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. (1968). Competition as a discovery process. In F. Hayek (1978) New studies in philosophy, politics and economics. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Hayek, F. (1976). The mirage of social justice. In F. Hayek (1982) Law, legislation and liberty. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Hodgson, G. (1988). Economics and institutions. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. (1999). Institutions and habits. In P. O’Hara (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of political economy (Vol. 1). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. (2001). How economics forgot history: The problem of historical specificity in social science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyclak, T., Johnes, G., & Thornton, R. (2004). Fundamentals of labor economic. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingham, G. (1996). The new economic sociology. Work, employment and society, 10(13), 549–564.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ioannides, S. (1992). The market, competition and democracy. Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1994). Realism and Hayek: A case of continuous transformation. In M. Colona & H. Hageman (Eds.), The economics of Hayek: Vol 1. Money and business cycles. Aldershot Hants: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1995). Developments in Hayek's social theorising. In S. Frowen (Ed.), Hayek the economist and social philosopher: A critical retrospect. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (2003). Reorienting economics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, T. (2005). The nature of institutional economics. Evolutionary Institutionalist Economics Revue, 2(1), 7–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2004). Transforming economics: Perspectives on the Critical Realist Project. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2005). Boettke, the Austrian school and the reclamation of reality in modern economics. Review of Austrian Economics, 18(1), 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2006). Hayek: From economics as equilibrium analysis to economics as social theory. In N. Barry (Ed.), The Elgar companion to Hayek. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises, L. Von. (1996). Human action, Irvington, CA: Foundation for Economic Education, retrieved from http://mises.org/humanaction.asp

  • Rogers, G. (1994). Institutional economics, development economics and labor economics. In G. Rogers (Ed.), Workers. Institutions and economic growth in Asia. Geneva: International Institute for Labor Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers Hollingsworth, J. (2005). On institutional embeddedness. In J. Rogers Hollingsworth, K. Muller, E. Hollingsworth, &  D. Gear (Eds.), Advancing socio-economics: An institutionalist perspective. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubery, J. (1992). Productive systems, international integration and the single European market. In A. Castro, P. Mehaut, & J. Rubery (Eds.), International integration and labor market organisation. London: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubery, J. (1997). Wages and the labor market. British Journal of Industrial Relations, 35(3), 337–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubery, J., & Grimshaw, D. (1998). Integrating the internal and external labor markets. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 22, 199–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubery, J., & Grimshaw, D. (2003). The organization of employment: An international perspective. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runde, J. (2001). Bringing social structure back into economics: On critical realism and Hayek's scientism essay. Review of Austrian Economics, 14, 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, M. (1999). Institutions in economics: The old and the new institutionalism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryoo, J., & Rosen, S. (2004). The engineering labor market. Journal of Political Economy, 112(1 Pt. 2), S110–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saint-Paul, G. (2000). The political economy of labor market institutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2005). What is an institution. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solow, R. (1990). The labor market as a social institution. NewYork: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughn, K. (1999). Hayek's implicit economics: Rules and the problem of order. Review of Austrian Economics, 11, 128–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vedder, R., & Gallaway, L. (2002a). The economic effects of labor unions revisited. Journal of Labor Research, XXIII(1), 105–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vedder, R., & Gallaway, L. (2002b). The minimum wage and poverty among full-time workers. Journal of Labor Research, XXIII(1), 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, N. (2004). The labor market for early musicians, paper presented at the IACR conference, Cambridge, MA.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steve Fleetwood.

Additional information

JEL Codes B4 · J3

I wish to thank Paul Lewis and Gregor Zwirn for their insightful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fleetwood, S. Austrian economics and the analysis of labor markets. Rev Austrian Econ 20, 247–267 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-006-0009-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-006-0009-6

Keywords

Navigation