Skip to main content
Log in

Enhancing voluntary contributions in a public goods economy via a minimum individual contribution level

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose and theoretically analyze a measure to encourage greater voluntary contributions to public goods. Our measure is a simple intervention that restricts individuals’ strategy sets by imposing a minimum individual contribution level while still allowing for full free riding for those who do not want to contribute. We show that for a well-chosen value of the minimum individual contribution level, this measure does not incentivize any additional free riding while strictly increasing the total contributions relative to the situation without the minimum contribution level. Our measure is appealing because it is nonintrusive and in line with the principle of “freedom of choice.” It is easily implementable for many different public goods settings where more intrusive measures are less accepted. This approach has been implemented in practice in some applications, such as charities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We refer to Bergstrom et al. (1986), Kollock (1998) and Guido et al. (2019) for extensive reviews of the theoretical studies and applications on the topic of social dilemmas and the voluntary provision of public goods.

  2. Our proposal fundamentally differs from research on threshold public goods games (van de Kragt et al., 1983; Cadsby & Maynes, 1999; Palfrey & Rosenthal, 1984) In these studies instead, the researchers investigate the impact of a minimum level for the total level of contributions or number of contributors for the public good to be provided.

  3. We denote by \(\bar{{\mathbb {R}}}\) the extended real number line \({\mathbb {R}} \cup \{-\infty , +\infty \}\).

  4. As we discuss in the conclusions, an experimental validation of our model is the main direction for future work on the topic.

  5. These preliminary results, which are valid for a fairly classic nonlinear public goods model, translate into our specific context some well-known results already present in the literature (see, e.g., Bergstrom et al., 1986).

  6. However, the last three inequalities hold instead strictly under some specific assumptions; for instance, whenever the new individual is such that \(h^{\prime }(G^*(N\cup \{n+1\})) > p_{n+1}(\lambda _{n+1}^*(N))\) (i.e., if she is not a free rider once she enters the game) and, in particular, whenever Assumption 1 holds and \(n+1\) is ranked in the ordering no higher than the last non-free rider of the original game \(\Gamma (N)\). This second condition is sufficient but not necessary for the inequalities to hold strictly.

  7. The additive constant is given by the sum over i of the \(p_i(0)\) with i being the original free riders. All our findings for such a reduced game may be generalized to the original game, simply by observing that when imposing a minimum contribution level, the free riders continue to use free riding. Therefore, our incentives can be calibrated on and intended for increasing the effort of individuals who were already contributors to the public good.

  8. A critical point of \(\Phi\) on the domain \((\lambda _n^*,1]^n\) is also critical on the full domain \([0,1]^n\), but we have shown that \(\varvec{\lambda }^*\) is the only critical point of \(\Phi\) on this domain.

  9. This Nash equilibrium is such that individual n has exactly the same utility by contributing and by free riding.

  10. Formally, if there exists \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*,1]\), such that, \(h(G^M(N,\eta ))-h(G^M(N,\eta )-\eta )= p_n(\eta )\), we define the parameter \(\eta ^*\) as the smallest \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*,1]\) satisfying the former equation. If the condition is never fulfilled, this corresponds to the situation in which individual n is always better off by contributing than by free riding; then, \(\eta ^*=1\), as \(h(G^*(N,1))-h(G^*(N,1)-1) = h(n) - h(n-1) > p_n(1)\).

  11. However, this is not true, for example, in the special case when \(|N|=1\), for which the utility function is necessarily decreasing in \([\eta ^*,1]\). As \(\eta ^*\) is the threshold at which the unique individual has exactly the same utility by contributing and by free riding, for each minimum contribution level strictly greater than \(\eta ^*\), she will be better off by free riding than by contributing.

  12. Formally, for each \(j\in N\) such that \(p_j^{\prime }(\cdot )=p_n^{\prime }(\cdot )\), there exists a NE \(\varvec{\nu }\) of \(\Gamma (N,\eta ^*)\) such that, \(\nu _i=\lambda _i^*(N,\eta ^*)=\lambda _i^*(N\setminus \{n\},\eta ^*)\) for each \(i\ne j\) and \(\nu _j=0\). Such an equilibrium is such that \(\Phi (\varvec{\nu })=\Phi (\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta ^*))\).

  13. Formally, if there exists \(\bar{\eta }\in (\lambda _n^*,\eta ^*]\) such that \(\Phi \mid _{\lambda _n=0}(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(N{\setminus } \{n\},\eta )) = \Phi (\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta ))\), where \(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(N{\setminus } \{n\},\bar{\eta })\) is the unique global maximum of the potential function \(\Phi\) defined on the restricted domain \([\bar{\eta }, 1]^{n-1}\cup \{0\}\) and \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\bar{\eta })\) is the unique global maximum of \(\Phi\) on \([\bar{\eta },1]^n\), we define the parameter \(\bar{\eta }\) as the smallest \(\bar{\eta }\in (\lambda _n^*,\eta ^*]\) satisfying the former equation. Of course, for values of the minimum level of contribution in \([0, \lambda _n^*]\), the maximum value of the potential function is unique, and this condition is never satisfied.

  14. In addition, we also observe that, in equilibrium, the individual utility and the social welfare are strictly larger when a new individual enters the game.

  15. Formally, given a value of \(\eta \in (\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1), \eta ^*(m_{\eta })]\), one can at best obtain \(m_{\eta }\) individuals contributing \(\eta ^*(m_{\eta })\) at a NE. That is, the maximal total contribution at a NE is \(m\eta ^*(m)\) for some \(m\le n\). Hence, in all cases where \(m\eta ^*(m)\) is an increasing function of m, one cannot improve in terms of total public good contribution by setting \(\eta > \eta ^*(n)\).

  16. Iran, Libya, Yemen and Eritrea have not ratified the agreement. The United States withdrew from the agreement in 2020 but rejoined in 2021.

  17. All-or-nothing contributions have also been studied in other kinds of games, such as trust games (Schniter et al., 2015)

References

  • Abowd, J. M., & Schmutte, I. M. (2019). An economic analysis of privacy protection and statistical accuracy as social choices. American Economic Review, 109, 171–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Admati, A. R., & Perry, M. (1991). Joint projects without commitment. The Review of Economic Studies, 58, 259–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akerlof, G. A. (1980). A theory of social custom, of which unemployment may be one consequence. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 94, 749–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J. (1989). Giving with impure altruism: Applications to charity and ricardian equivalence. Journal of Political Economy, 97(6), 1447–1458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving. The Economic Journal, 100(401), 467–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J., & Bergstrom, T. C. (1996). Do government subsidies increase the private supply of public goods? Public Choice, 88, 295–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arlegi, R., Benito-Ostolaza, J. M., & Osés-Eraso, N. (2021). Participation in and provision of public goods: Does granularity matter? Journal of Economic Interaction and Coordination, 16(2), 265–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bénabou, R., & Tirole, J. (2006). Incentives and prosocial behavior. American Economic Review, 96, 1652–1678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom, T., Blume, L., & Varian, H. R. (1986). On the private provision of public goods. Journal of Public Economics, 29, 25–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, P. (1972). Estimating demand for public goods: An experiment. European Economic Review, 3, 111–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bramoullé, Y., & Kranton, R. (2007). Public goods in networks. Journal of Economic Theory, 135, 478–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burlando, R. M., & Guala, F. (2005). Heterogeneous agents in public goods experiments. Experimental Economics, 8, 35–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bursztyn, L., & Jensen, R. (2017). Social image and economic behavior in the field: Identifying, understanding, and shaping social pressure. Annual Review of Economics, 9(1), 131–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cadsby, C. B., & Maynes, E. (1999). Voluntary provision of threshold public goods with continuous contributions: Experimental evidence. Journal of Public Economics, 71, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chessa, M., Grossklags, J., & Loiseau, P. (2015a). A game-theoretic study on non-monetary incentives in data analytics projects with privacy implications. In Proceedings of the 2015 IEEE 28th computer security foundations symposium (CSF) (pp. 90–104).

  • Chessa, M., Grossklags, J., & Loiseau, P. (2015b). A short paper on incentives to share private information for population estimates. In Proceedings of the 19th international conference on financial cryptography and data security (FC).

  • Clarke, E. H. (1971). Multipart pricing of public goods. Public Choice, 11, 17–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courtois, P., & Haeringer, G. (2012). Environmental cooperation: Ratifying second-best agreements. Public Choice, 151, 565–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duca, S., Helbing, D., & Nax, H. H. (2018). Assortative matching with inequality in voluntary contribution games. Computational Economics, 52, 1029–1043.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egas, M., & Riedl, A. (2008). The economics of altruistic punishment and the maintenance of cooperation. Proceedings of the Royal Society B -Biological Sciences, 275(1637), 871–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2000). Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. The American Economic Review, 90, 980–994.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gangadharan, L., & Nikiforakis, N. (2009). Does the size of the action set matter for cooperation? Economics Letters, 104(3), 115–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groves, T., & Ledyard, J. (1977). Optimal allocation of public goods: A solution to the “free rider’’ problem. Econometrica, 45, 783–809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guido, A., Robbett, A., & Romaniuc, R. (2019). Group formation and cooperation in social dilemmas: A survey and meta-analytic evidence. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 159, 192–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, B., Thöni, C., & Gächter, S. (2008). Antisocial punishment across societies. Science, 319, 1362–1367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt, C. A., & Laury, S. K. (1997). Classroom games: Voluntary provision of a public good. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 11, 209–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kollock, P. (1998). Social dilemmas: The anatomy of cooperation. Review of Sociology, 24, 183–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld, M., Okada, A., & Riedl, A. (2009). Institution formation in public goods games. The American Economic Review, 99(4), 1335–1355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ledyard, J. O. (1995). Public goods: A survey of experimental research. In Kagel & Roth (Eds.), Handbook of experimental economics. Princeton University Press.

  • Ledyard, J. O., & Palfrey, T. R. (1994). Voting and lottery drafts as efficient public goods mechanisms. Review of Economic Studies, 61, 327–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, H., & Romero, J. (2023). IPCC, 2023: Climate Change 2023: Synthesis Report. Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the Sixth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change [Core Writing Team, H. Lee and J. Romero (eds.)]. IPCC, Geneva, Switzerland. https://doi.org/10.59327/IPCC/AR6-9789291691647. Retrieved from https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:260074696.

  • Liu, J., & Riyanto, Y. E. (2017). The limit to behavioral inertia and the power of default in voluntary contribution games. Social Choice and Welfare, 48, 815–835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lugovskyy, L., Puzzello, D., Sorensen, A., Walker, J., & Williams, A. (2017). An experimental study of finitely and infinitely repeated linear public goods games. Games and Economic Behavior, 102, 286–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marron, D. B., & Toder, E. J. (2014). Tax policy issues in designing a carbon tax. The American Economic Review, 104(5), 563–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marwell, G., & Ames, R. E. (1979). Experiments on the provision of public goods i: Resources, interests, group size, and the free rider problem. American Journal of Sociology, 84, 1335–1360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, M. A. (1988). Information as property and as a public good: Perspectives from the economic theory of property rights. The Library Quarterly: Information, Community, Policy, 58, 265–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinty, M., & Milam, G. (2013). Public goods provision by asymmetric agents: Experimental evidence. Social Choice and Welfare, 40, 1159–1177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1994). Comparing equilibria. American Economic Review, 84, 441–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milinski, M., Semmann, D., Krambeck, H.-J., & Marotzke, J. (2006). Stabilizing the earth’s climate is not a losing game: Supporting evidence from public goods experiments. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 103(11), 3994–3998.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monderer, D., & Shapley, L. S. (1996). Potential games. Games and Economic Behavior, 14, 124–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nax, H. H., Murphy, R. O., & Helbing, D. (2014). Stability and welfare of ‘merit-based’ group-matching mechanisms in voluntary contribution game. (Available at SSRN. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2404280)

  • Nikiforakis, N. (2008). Punishment and counter-punishment in public good games: Can we really govern ourselves? Journal of Public Economics, 92, 91–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliveira, A., Croson, R., & Eckel, C. (2015). One bad apple? Heterogeneity and information in public good provision. Experimental Economics, 18, 116–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T. R., & Rosenthal, H. (1984). Participation and the provision of discrete public goods: A strategic analysis. Journal of Public Economics, Enhancing Voluntary Contributions in a Public Goods Economy, 24(2), 171–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rand, D. G., & Nowak, M. A. (2013). Human cooperation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 413–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reuben, E., & Riedl, A. (2013). Enforcement of contribution norms in public good games with heterogeneous populations. Games and Economic Behavior, 77(1), 122–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (1984). A positive model of private charity and wealth transfers. Journal of Political Economy, 92, 136–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. A. (1954). The pure theory of public expenditure. The Review of Economics and Statistics, 36, 387–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schniter, E., Sheremeta, R., & Shields, T. (2015). The problem with all-ornothing trust games: what others choose not to do matters in trust-based exchange. (In: MPRA Paper, no. 68561)

  • Sigmund, K., Hauert, C., & Nowak, M. (2001). Reward and punishment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 98, 10757–10762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1982). On the economics of philanthropy. The Economic Journal, 341–350.

  • Tolenen, H., Lundqvist, A., Jääskeläinen, T., Koskinen, S., & Koponen, P. (2017). Reasons for non-participation and ways to enhance participation in health examination surveysthe health 2011 survey. European Journal of Public Health, 27, 909–911.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trauth, J. M., Musa, D., Siminoff, L., Jewell, I. K., & Ricci, E. (2000). Public attitudes regarding willingness to participate in medical research studies. Journal of Health & Social Policy, 12, 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • UN (2015). United Nations Treaty Collection: Paris Agreement. Retrieved from https://treaties.un.org/doc/Treaties/2016/02/20160215

  • UNICEF (2023). UNICEF Annual Report 2022 New York: United Nations Childrens Fund. Retrieved from https://www.unicef.org/media/141001/file/UNICEF

  • van de Kragt, A., Orbell, J., & Dawes, R. (1983). The minimal contributing set as a solution to public goods problems. American Political Science Review, 77, 112–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Huyck, J., Battalio, R., & Beil, R. (1990). Tactic coordination games, strategic uncertainty, and coordination failure. American Economic Review, 80, 234–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varian, H. R. (1994). Sequential contributions to public goods. Journal of Public Economics, 53, 165–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, D. T. (1982). Voluntary purchase of public goods. Public Choice, 38, 73–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zelmer, J. (2003). Linear public goods experiments: A meta-analysis. Experimental Economics, 6, 299–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Y., Fu, F., Wu, T., & Xie, G. L. W. (2013). A tale of two contribution mechanisms for nonlinear public goods. Scientific Reports, 3, 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Jens Grossklags, Heinrich Nax, Arno Riedl, Galina Schwartz and Paolo Zeppini for helpful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this paper; as well as the editor and anonymous referee for constructive feedback that helped improve the presentation.

Funding

This work has been partially supported by the Multidisciplinary Institute in Artificial Intelligence MIAI @ Grenoble Alpes (ANR-19-P3IA-0003), by the French National Research Agency (ANR) under Grant ANR-20-CE23-0007, and by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Loiseau.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no Conflict of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix A Proofs

Appendix A Proofs

1.1 Proof of the results of Sect. 3.1

Game \(\Gamma (N)\) is a potential game with a concave potential function \(\Phi\) (defined as in (3)), where the strategy sets are closed intervals of the real line. It follows that a strategy profile is a Nash equilibrium if and only if it maximizes the potential function. As the potential function \(\Phi\) is strictly concave on the convex set on which it is defined, it has a unique global maximum \(\varvec{\lambda }^*\in [0,1]^n\) that coincides with the unique Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N)\). Such an equilibrium is strict. In particular, the equilibrium \(\varvec{\lambda }^*\) is such that for each \(i\in N\), \(\lambda _i^*\) satisfies the following KKT conditions

$$\begin{aligned} \left\{ \begin{aligned}&h^\prime (G^*(N))-p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*)+\psi _i^*-\phi _i^* = 0 \\&\psi _i^* \lambda _i^*=0\ \ \phi _i^*(\lambda _i^*-1)=0,\ \ \psi _i^*,\phi _i^*\ge 0, \end{aligned} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(A1)

where \(G^*(N)\) denotes the total contribution level at equilibrium. We may observe by (A1) that, owing to the assumption that \(h^\prime (0)> p_i^\prime (0)\) for at least one \(i\in N\), this equilibrium is \(\varvec{\lambda }^* \ne (0,\ldots ,0)\).

As the term \(h^\prime (G^*(N))\) is the same for each \(i\in N\), it immediately follows that, if the \(p_i\)s are such that \(p_1^\prime (\lambda ) \le ... \le p_n^\prime (\lambda )\), for each \(\lambda \in [0,1]\), then \(\lambda ^*_n \le \ldots \le \lambda ^*_1\).

1.2 Proof of the results at the beginning of Sect. 3.2

Given the game \(\Gamma (N)\), we suppose that an additional \((n+1)\)-th individual enters the game.

First, to show that the i-th individual’s contribution at equilibrium for each \(i\in N\) is such that \(\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) \le \lambda _i^*(N)\), we suppose by contradiction that there exists \(i\in N\) such that \(0 \le \lambda _i^*(N) < \lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) \le 1\). Because of the strict convexity of \(p_i\),

$$\begin{aligned} p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N)) < p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\})), \end{aligned}$$

and, from the KKT conditions in (A1), and as \(\lambda _i^*(N)<1\) and \(\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\})>0\),

$$\begin{aligned} h^\prime (G^*(N)) \le p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N)) < p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\})) \le h^\prime (G^*(N\cup \{n+1\})). \end{aligned}$$

From the first and from the last term and because of the concavity of h, it follows that

$$\begin{aligned}&G^*(N) > G^*(N\cup \{n+1\}). \end{aligned}$$
(A2)

If the total contribution without individual \(n+1\) is strictly greater than that after her entrance, this implies that there exists at least one individual \(j\in N\), which verifies the opposite inequality compared to i, i.e., such that \(1 \ge \lambda _j^*(N) > \lambda _j^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) \ge 0\). Following the same reasoning as before, we conclude that \(G^*(N) < G^*(N\cup \{n+1\})\), which contradicts (A2).

Second, we show that the total level of contribution is such that \(G^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) \ge G^*(N)\). We know that \(\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) \le \lambda _i^*(N)\) for each \(i\in N\). In particular, if the equality holds for each \(i\in N\), the thesis follows trivially, as \(G^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) = G^*(N)+ \lambda _{n+1}^*(N\cup \{n+1\})\), with \(\lambda _{n+1}^*(N\cup \{n+1\})\ge 0\). In contrast, if there exists \(i\in N\) such that \(\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\}) < \lambda _i^*(N)\), following the same reasoning as before, then we can conclude that the inequality holds strictly.

Finally, we show that individual utility and social welfare are \(U_i(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N\cup \{n+1\})) \ge U_i(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N))\) for all \(i\in N\) and \(W(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N\cup \{n+1\}))) \ge W(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N))\), respectively. It is sufficient to observe that at equilibrium,

$$\begin{aligned} U_i^*(N\cup \{n+1\})&= h(G^*(N\cup \{n+1\}))-p_i(\lambda _i^*(N\cup \{n+1\})) \\&\ge h(G^*(N))-p_i(\lambda _i^*(N)) \\&= U_i^*(N). \end{aligned}$$

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3.1

We observe that the modified game \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) is still a potential game with potential function \(\Phi\) but defined in the restricted domain \(\big [\{0\}\cup [\eta ,1]\big ]^n\). In contrast to \(\Gamma (N)\), the strategy sets of the modified game are not closed intervals of the real line, and the equilibria may not coincide with the global maxima of the potential function.

For a better reading of the following of the proof, we present it organized in 5 steps.

Step 1 Given a subset of the individuals \(S\subseteq N\), with \(s=|S|\), and for each \(\eta \in [0,1]\), we define a new modified game \(\Gamma '(S,\eta )=\left\langle S,[\eta ,1]^s, (U_i)_{i\in S} \right\rangle\), where the utility function \(U_i\) is defined by (1) for each individual \(i\in S\), but it is now restricted to the domain \([\eta ,1]\). \(\Gamma '(S,\eta )\) is still a potential game, with potential function \(\Phi\), defined on the restricted domain \([\eta ,1]^s\). As for the original game \(\Gamma (N)\) and the modified game \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\), we also observe that the game \(\Gamma '(S,\eta )\) is a potential game with a concave potential function and where similar to \(\Gamma (N)\) but different from \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\), the strategy sets are closed intervals of the real line. It follows that a strategy profile is a Nash equilibrium if and only if it maximizes the potential function. Moreover, the potential function is strictly concave on the convex set on which it is defined; then, it has a unique global maximum \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(S,\eta )\in [\eta ,1]^s\), which coincides with the unique Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma '(S,\eta )\). In particular, for each \(\eta \in (0,1]\), \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )\) is the unique Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma '(N,\eta )\).

Step 2 We define \(\eta ^*\) as in Definition 1. We show that \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta ^*)\) is a Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N,\eta ^*)\). First, we observe that no individual has incentives to deviate to a quantity in \([\eta ^*, 1]\) because \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta ^*)\) is a Nash equilibrium of the game \(\Gamma '(N,\eta ^*)\). It remains to be shown that no individual has incentives to go to zero. Individual n does not have incentives by Definition 1. For any other individual \(i\ne n\), such that \(\lambda _i^M(N,\eta ^*) = \eta ^*\), if agent n, who is the most privacy concerned, does not have incentives to deviate from \(\eta ^*\), that is still valid for i. For any other agent \(i\ne n\), such that \(\lambda _i^M(N,\eta ^*) > \eta ^*\), as i does not have incentives to deviate to \(\eta ^*\), then, because of the concavity of the utility function, she cannot have incentives to deviate to 0.

Step 3 We observe that for each \(\eta \in [0, \eta ^*)\), \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )\) is a Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\). Moreover, when \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*,\eta ^*)\), we can repeat the same reasoning as in Step 3, with the only difference being that individual n (and any other individual contributing \(\eta\)) is always strictly better off by contributing rather than free riding, and then, the inequality is always strict.

Step 4 We observe that for any \(\eta \in (0,\eta ^*]\), \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )\) is the unique Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) such that each individual has a nonzero contribution, i.e., such that \(\lambda ^M_i(N,\eta )>0\) for each \(i\in N\). To show that, it is sufficient to observe that an equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) such that each individual has a nonzero contribution, is also an equilibrium of the game \(\Gamma '(N,\eta )\) (as if an individual does not have incentives to deviate in \(\{0\}\cup [\eta ,1]\), she does not have incentives to deviate in the restricted strategy set \([\eta ,1]\) either), and the equilibrium of \(\Gamma '(N,\eta )\) is unique.

Step 5 We show that any other NE \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) is such that \(\bar{\lambda }_i=\lambda _i^M(S,\eta )\) for each \(i\in S\), where \(S=\{i\in N \mid \bar{\lambda }_i \ne 0\}\). Let \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*,\eta ^*]\), and we let \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}=\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}(N)\) be a Nash equilibrium of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) such that \(\bar{\lambda }_i(N)=0\) for at least one \(i\in N\). We define S as the set of individuals who contribute nonzero values at this equilibrium. As, by definition, of NE, none of the individuals has incentives to deviate, and, in particular, none of the individuals in S has incentives to deviate in \([\eta , 1]\). It follows that \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}(S)\), i.e., the vector of the nonzero elements of the vector \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}(N)\), is a Nash equilibrium of the game \(\Gamma ^\prime (S,\eta )\) defined in step 2 of this proof. As we have seen, this equilibrium is unique and coincides with the unique Nash equilibrium \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(S,\eta )\) of the game \(\Gamma (S,\eta )\) such that no individual is free riding. Trivially, we can conclude that \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta )\) is the unique NE of \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\) s.t., \(\lambda ^*_i(N,\eta ) > 0\) for all \(i\in N\).

1.4 Proof of Theorem 3.2

Let us recall that we assumed that the equilibrium contribution \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N)\) of \(\Gamma (N)\) is such that \(\lambda ^*_n(N) < 1\), i.e., it is such that the total level of contribution is not optimal.

When \(\eta \in [0,\lambda _n^*(N)]\), \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta )=\varvec{\lambda }^*(N)\); consequently, \(G^*\) is constant, i.e., \(G^*(N,\eta )=G^*(N)\).

When \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*(N),\eta ^*]\), individual n contributes to equilibrium \(\lambda _n^*(N,\eta ) = \eta > \lambda _n^*(N)\). We now show that for \(\eta ^* \ge \eta _2 > \eta _1 \ge \lambda _n^*\), \(G^*(N,\eta _2) > G^*(N,\eta _1)\). By contradiction, we assume that \(G^*(N,\eta _2) \le G^*(N,\eta _1)\). It follows that

$$\begin{aligned} h^\prime (G^*(N,\eta _2)) \ge h^\prime (G^*(N,\eta _1)), \end{aligned}$$
(A3)

because of the concavity of the public good utility function h. Moreover, as the total level of contribution with \(\eta _2\) is less than or equal to the level of contribution with \(\eta _1\), we know that individual n has a strictly larger level of contribution; it follows that there exists \(i\in N\) who contributes strictly less, i.e., such that,

$$\begin{aligned} \eta _2 \le \lambda _i^*(N,\eta _2) < \lambda _i^*(N,\eta _1) \le 1. \end{aligned}$$
(A4)

By equation (A4), because of the convexity of the cost of contribution function \(p_i\) and from the KKT conditions for the potential function of the modified game \(\Gamma ^*(N,\eta )\), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} h^\prime (G^*(N,\eta _2)) \le p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N,\eta _2)) < p_i^\prime (\lambda _i^*(N,\eta _1)) \le h^\prime (G^*(N,\eta _1)) \end{aligned}$$

and this contradicts equation (A3).

1.5 Proof of the results at the beginning of Sect. 3.3

First, we observe that

$$\begin{aligned}&h(G^*(N,\eta ^*))-p_j(\lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*)) \ge h(G^*(N,\eta ^*) - \lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*))-p_j(0)\ \ \forall j\in N \end{aligned}$$
(A5)

because, as shown in Proposition 3.1, \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta ^*)\) is a NE of \(\Gamma (N,\eta ^*)\), and thus, no individual has incentives to go to zero. Now, we suppose by contradiction that the vector \(\varvec{\nu }\) such that, \(\nu _i=\lambda _i^*(N,\eta ^*)=\lambda _i^*(N\setminus \{n\},\eta ^*)\) for each \(i\ne n\) and \(\nu _n=0\) is not a NE of \(\Gamma (N,\eta ^*)\). This means that there exists an individual \(j\in N\setminus \{n\}\) for whom it is convenient to deviate, i.e., such that, it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} h(G^*(N,\eta ^*)-\eta ^*)-p_j(\lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*)) < h(G^*(N,\eta ^*) - \eta ^* - \lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*))-p_j(0). \end{aligned}$$
(A6)

From Equations (A5) and (A6), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned}&h(G^*(N,\eta ^*))-h(G^*(N,\eta ^*) - \lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*)) \ge p_j(\lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*))-p_j(0) \\&\quad > h(G^*(N,\eta ^*)-\eta ^*) - h(G^*(N,\eta ^*) - \eta ^* - \lambda _j^*(N,\eta ^*)) \end{aligned}$$

This cannot hold because of the concavity of h. It follows that \(\varvec{\nu }\) is a NE of \(\Gamma (N,\eta ^*)\).

Second, we observe that \(\varvec{\nu }\) provides the same value of the potential function as \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta ^*)\). Then, if the second one is a potential maximizer, the first one is as well.

1.6 Proof of Proposition 3.3

Let \(\bar{\eta }\) be defined as in Definition 2, \(\eta \in (\lambda _n^*,\bar{\eta })\), and \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta )=\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )\) be the unique nonzero component Nash equilibrium of the modified game \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\), which is the unique maximizer of \(\Phi\) on \([\eta ,1]^n\). As \(\eta < \bar{\eta }\), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi (\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )) > \Phi \mid _{\lambda _n=0}(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(N\setminus \{n\}),\eta ). \end{aligned}$$
(A7)

As \(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(N\setminus \{n\})\) is the potential maximizer of function \(\Phi\) restricted to domain \([\bar{\eta }, 1]^{n-1}\cup \{0\}\), it also holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi \mid _{\lambda _n=0}(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(N\setminus \{n\}),\eta ) \ge \Phi \mid _{\lambda _i=0, \forall i\in N\setminus S}(\varvec{\lambda }^{M0}(S,\eta )). \end{aligned}$$
(A8)

(A7) and (A8) show that \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(N,\eta )=\varvec{\lambda }^M(N,\eta )\) is the unique PMNE of the modified game \(\Gamma (N,\eta )\).

1.7 Proof of the results of Section  3.4

When the game \(\Gamma (N)\) is homogeneous, the potential function \(\Phi\) is a symmetric function on a symmetric domain. As a consequence, the unique maximum is also symmetric, i.e., \(\lambda _i^*=\lambda ^*\) for each \(i\in N\). In particular, as the equilibrium vector is a nonzero vector, we have \(\lambda ^*>0\).

From Equation (A1), recalling that we are now in a homogeneous case, we observe that \(\lambda ^*>0\) is the unique solution of the following fixed-point problem

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda =g(n,\lambda ), \end{aligned}$$
(A9)

where the function \(g: {\mathbb {N}}_+ \times (0,1] \rightarrow [0,+\infty ]\) is defined for each \(\lambda \in (0,1]\) and for each \(n\in {\mathbb {N}}_+\) as

$$\begin{aligned} g(n,\lambda ) = \min \left\{ (p^\prime )^{-1} (h^\prime \left( n \lambda \right) ), 1\right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(A10)

We consider the problem with the parameter n defined on the real interval \([1,+\infty ]\). For each \(n\in [1,+\infty ]\), g is continuous in \(\lambda\). Moreover, the function g is monotonic and nonincreasing in n. Indeed,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {g}}{\partial {n}}=&\frac{\lambda }{p^{\prime \prime }((p^\prime )^{-1}(h'\left( n \lambda \right) ))}h^{\prime \prime }\left( n \lambda \right) < 0 \end{aligned}$$

for each \(\lambda\) internal solution, and g is identically 1 otherwise. Applying Corollary 1 of Milgrom and Roberts (1994), the unique fixed point \(\lambda ^*(n)>0\) is nonincreasing in n; consequently, \(\lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }\lambda ^*(n)\ge 0\) is well defined.

Second, for each \(\lambda >0\),

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }g(n,\lambda )=0 \end{aligned}$$

pointwise. Indeed, \(\lim _{x\rightarrow +\infty }h^\prime (x)=0\), \(p^\prime (0)\ge 0\) and \(p^\prime\) are strictly monotonic.

If we suppose by contradiction that \(\lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }\lambda ^*(n) = a > 0\), then, from Equation (A9), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} 0 < \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }\lambda ^*(n) = \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }g(n,\lambda ^*(n)) = \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }g(n,a) = 0. \end{aligned}$$

Now, we know that \(G^*(n+1) \ge G^*(n)\) for each \(n\in N\). In particular, we know that the inequality holds strictly at equilibrium in the homogeneous case where any new individuals are not free riders. We suppose by contradiction that \(\lim _{n\rightarrow + \infty }G^*(n)<+\infty\). It follows that \(\lim _{n\rightarrow + \infty }h^\prime (n\lambda ^*(n))>0\); then, by (A10), the solution to the fixed-point problem is such that \(\lim _{n\rightarrow + \infty } \lambda ^*(n)>0\), which contradicts the fact that we already know that this limit goes to zero.

1.8 Proof of Theorem 3.4

For each \(\eta \in (0,1]\), let \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(n,\eta )\) be the unique global maximum of \(\Phi\) on \([\eta , 1]^n\). When the individuals are homogeneous, the potential function \(\Phi\) is a symmetric function that we are maximizing on a symmetric domain. As a consequence, the maximum is \(\lambda _i^M(n,\eta )=\lambda ^M(n,\eta )\) for each \(i\in N\), with

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda ^M(n,\eta )=\left\{ \begin{aligned}&\lambda ^*(n)&\text { if } 0< \eta \le \lambda ^*(n) \\&\eta&\text { if } \lambda ^*(n) < \eta \le 1. \\ \end{aligned} \right. \end{aligned}$$
(A11)
  1. (i)

    For each \(\eta \in (0,\eta ^*(n)]\), where \(\eta ^*(n)\) is defined as in Definition 1, \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(n,\eta )=\varvec{\lambda }^M(n,\eta )\) is the unique NE of the modified game \(\Gamma (n,\eta )\) such that no individual is free riding. As a particular case of Proposition 3.3, for each \(\eta \in (0,\bar{\eta }(n)]\), where \(\bar{\eta }(n)\) is defined as in Definition 2, \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(n,\eta )\) is the unique PMNE of the modified game \(\Gamma (n,\eta )\).

  2. (ii)

    This result follows Definition 1 for the homogeneous case.

  3. (iii)

    For each \(\eta \in (\eta ^*(n),1]\), we show that there does not exist a NE \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) of \(\Gamma (n,\eta )\) such that \(\bar{\lambda }_i > 0\) for each \(i\in N\). We assume that \(\eta ^*(n)<1\). First, we observe that, with reasoning similar to that in the proof of Proposition 3.1, A.3-Step 5, whenever we have a nonzero component NE of \(\Gamma (n,\eta )\), this has to be a NE of the corresponding game \(\Gamma ^{\prime }\) and then a maximum of the potential function \(\Phi\) restricted to the domain \([\eta ,1]^n\). Because of this symmetry, the only possible candidate nonzero component NE is the vector \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}=\varvec{\eta }=(\eta , \ldots , \eta )\). Second, we observe that by definition, \(\eta ^*(n)\) is the smallest solution of the following fixed-point problem:

    $$\begin{aligned} p(\eta )&= h(n\eta )-h((n-1)\eta ) \end{aligned}$$
    (A12)

    or, equivalently, of

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{p(\eta )}{\eta }&= \frac{h(n\eta )-h((n-1)\eta )}{\eta } \end{aligned}$$
    (A13)

    where n is a fixed parameter. Then, we show that \(\eta ^*(n)\) is, in fact, the unique solution of (A13). Indeed, because of the concavity of h, we have that

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{h(y)-h(x)}{y-x} \end{aligned}$$

    is a decreasing function both in y and in x; in particular, the right term of (A13) is decreasing in \(\eta\). Moreover, because of the convexity of p, we have

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{p(y)-p(x)}{y-x} \end{aligned}$$

    is an increasing function both in y and in x; in particular, the left term of (A13) is increasing in \(\eta\) (when \(y=\eta\), \(x=0\) and p(0) are constants). It follows that the fixed-point problem in (A13) has at most one solution.

    In particular, applying Corollary 1 of Milgrom and Roberts (1994), the unique (i.e., smallest) fixed point \(\eta ^*(n)>0\) is nonincreasing in n. Moreover, if we assume that \(\eta ^*(n) = \eta ^*(n-1) = \eta < 1\), we obtain from (A12) that

    $$\begin{aligned} h(n\eta ) - h((n-1)\eta ) = h((n-1)\eta ) - h((n-2)\eta ), \end{aligned}$$

    which contradicts the fact that h is strictly concave. Hence, we conclude that \(\eta ^*(n)\) is strictly decreasing in n.

    Third, we know that \(\varvec{\lambda }^*(n)\) is an SNE of \(\Gamma (n)\); i.e., we know that \(p(\lambda ^*(n)) < h(n\lambda ^*(n))-h((n-1)\lambda ^*(n))\). Moreover, we observe that \(\eta ^*(n)\) verifies the equality by definition when \(\eta ^*(n)<1\). As the solution of the previous fixed-point problem is unique when it exists, it follows that

    $$\begin{aligned} p(\eta ) > h(n\eta )-h((n-1)\eta ) \end{aligned}$$
    (A14)

    for each \(\eta \in (\eta ^*(n),1]\). Equation (A14) translates to the fact that when individuals adopt the strategy \(\varvec{\eta }=(\eta , \ldots , \eta )\), with \(\eta \in (\eta ^*(n),1]\), each individual in N is strictly better able to go to zero, and then, the only candidate nonzero component NE cannot be a NE.

    Now, we assume that \(\eta \le \eta ^*(1)\) and let \(m_{\eta } \in \{1, \cdots , n-1\}\) be the integer such that \(\eta \in (\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1), \eta ^*(m_{\eta })]\). Such an integer exists and is unique because \(\eta ^*(n)\) is strictly decreasing in n.

    Let us note that by definition of \(m_\eta\), we see that it is possible that \(\eta ^*(m_{\eta })=1\) (in which case \(\eta ^*(m) = 1\) for all \(m\le m_{\eta }\) but those values of m never correspond to any \(m_{\eta ^{\prime }}\) for any \(\eta ^{\prime }\)); however, we necessarily have \(\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)<1\).

    We assume that there exists a NE \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) of \(\Gamma (N, \eta )\) where s individuals in set S contribute positively, i.e., \(\bar{\lambda }_i >0\) for all \(i\in S\) and \(\bar{\lambda }^*_i =0\) for all \(i\in N{\setminus } S\), where \(s = |S|\). First, following arguments from the proof of Proposition 3.1, \(( \bar{\lambda }_i)_{i\in S}\) is equal to \(\varvec{\lambda }^M(S, \eta )\) which is symmetric. We denote by \(\bar{\lambda }\) the value of \(\bar{\lambda }_i\) for \(i\in S\) and we have \(\bar{\lambda } = \lambda ^*(s)\) is \(\eta < \lambda ^*(s)\) and \(\bar{\lambda } =\eta\) otherwise.

    Next, we observe that we must have \(s \le m_{\eta }\). Indeed, we assume that \(s>m_{\eta }\). Then, \(\lambda ^*(s) \le \eta ^*(s) \le \eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1) < \eta\), so that \(\bar{\lambda } = \eta\). In that case, an individual \(i\in S\) switching from \(\bar{\lambda }\) to zero contribution gains \(p(\bar{\lambda }) - \left( h(s\bar{\lambda })h((s-1)\bar{\lambda }) \right)\), which is strictly positive since, by using arguments similar to the ones introduced above, we can show:

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{p(\bar{\lambda })}{\bar{\lambda }} = \frac{p(\eta )}{\eta }&> \frac{p(\eta ^*(m+1))}{\eta ^*(m+1)} \\&= \frac{h((m+1)\eta ^*(m+1)) - h(m\eta ^*(m+1))}{\eta ^*(m+1)} \\&\ge \frac{h(s\eta ^*(m+1)) - h((s-1)\eta ^*(m+1))}{\eta ^*(m+1)} \\&\ge \frac{h(s\bar{\lambda }) - h((s-1)\bar{\lambda })}{\bar{\lambda }}. \end{aligned}$$

    This contradicts the fact that \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) is a NE.

    We now show that for \(s=m_{\eta }\), the profile \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) with \(\bar{\lambda }_i = \max (\lambda ^*(s), \eta ) \in (\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1), \eta ^*(m_{\eta })]\) for all \(i\in S\) is indeed a NE. First, let us note that, by definition of \(\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)\), individuals outside S (i.e., given zero) have no incentive to deviate. Indeed, if \(i\in N\setminus S\) deviates to \(\lambda ^{\prime } \ge \eta > \eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)\), the gain is

    $$\begin{aligned} h((s+1)\lambda ^{\prime }) - h(s\lambda ^{\prime }) - p(\lambda ^{\prime })&= \lambda ^{\prime } \frac{h((s+1)\lambda ^{\prime }) - h(s\lambda ^{\prime })}{\lambda ^{\prime }} - \lambda ^{\prime } \frac{p(\lambda ^{\prime })}{\lambda ^{\prime }}\\&\le \lambda ^{\prime } \frac{h((s+1)\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)) - h(s\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1))}{\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)} +\\&- \lambda ^{\prime } \frac{p(\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1))}{\eta ^*(m_{\eta }+1)}\\&= 0, \end{aligned}$$

    Here, we again use the convexity of p and concavity of h, as derived above. Similarly, individuals in S have no incentive to deviate to zero. Hence, \(\bar{\varvec{\lambda }}\) is a NE.

1.9 Proof of the additional results of Sect. 3.4

It remains to be observed that, because of the monotonicity, \(\lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }\eta ^*(n)\ge 0\) is well defined. Indeed, \(\lim _{x\rightarrow +\infty }h(nx)-h((n-1)x)=0\), \(p(0)\ge 0\) and p are strictly monotonic. If we suppose by contradiction that \(\lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }\eta ^*(n) = a > 0\), then, from Equation (A12), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} 0&< p(a) \\&= \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }p(\eta ^*(n)) \\&= \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }h(n\eta ^*(n))-h((n-1)\eta ^*(n)) \\&= \lim _{n\rightarrow +\infty }h(na)-h((n-1)a) \\&= 0. \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chessa, M., Loiseau, P. Enhancing voluntary contributions in a public goods economy via a minimum individual contribution level. Public Choice (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01165-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01165-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation