Skip to main content
Log in

Attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose a model of attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters under three electoral rules: plurality, approval voting, and negative plurality. Voters’ conduct is determined by their attentiveness and impressions of candidates. We show that attentiveness is as important as voters’ preferences for the outcome of the election. Specifically, we show that candidates benefit from increased voter attention under all rules other than negative plurality. We then consider exogenous and endogenous attentiveness and show how our model can account for momentum effects in primaries, where candidates rise quickly and then fade away. Finally we consider the case of news coverage tone and show that under plurality rule e.g., primary elections, candidates may benefit from frequent news coverage even if the news is negative.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A tie is a measure zero event in our analysis, i.e., it occurs non-generically, and can be ignored. For completeness we can assume that ties are broken with equal probability.

  2. See Sect. 4.1 for further discussion, and examples of the factors that determine voters’ attentiveness.

  3. The two ways to define the “event” probabilities \(\Pr _{\theta }^{t}(.)\) are equivalent, and each can be derived from the other.

  4. Strictly speaking, we would have to index the set K by subscript \(\theta\) for the group of voters, and superscript t for time. For simplicity of notation, however we drop these two indexes here and in analogous cases.

  5. The parameter \(\lambda _{p}\) need not be the same across all voters. As we will prove in Proposition 1, the distribution of vote measures in a stationary distribution does not depend on \(\lambda _{p}\). This parameter can vary across e.g., groups of voters, without changing the stationary measures of votes.

  6. An alternative method of updating aspirations in the literature is that of Cyert-March (Cyert & March, 1963) where aspirations are a linear mixture of previous period aspirations and an average of present period impressions. The analysis would be more difficult, but would yield qualitatively similar results.

  7. We note that \(K_{\theta }^{\tau }\) is a random variable, with the distribution \(\{\Pr _{\theta }(K)\}_{K\subseteq N}\) as defined previously. We also note that if \(\sum _{\tau =1}^{t}|K_{\theta }^{\tau }|=0\), i.e., voters do not pay attention to any candidate up to period t, then the average of impressions from \(\tau =1\) to t is not well-defined. In this situation, we take, for example, \(a_{\theta }^{t+1}=a_{\theta }^{0}\) an arbitrary value.

  8. If the events \(\{e_{\theta }(i)\}_{i\in N}\) are correlated, some results continue to apply, but others are more difficult to prove, and likely necessitate assumptions on the full distribution of the attentiveness vector \(e_{\theta }\). Specifically, the results concerning the impact of positive/negative impressions would not change, while the results concerning attentiveness would be limited.

  9. In addition to the direct effect of the attention probabilities \(r_{\theta }(.)\) discussed, we note that attention probabilities also indirectly impact vote measures through the impression probabilities \(q_{\theta }(.)\). As aspirations are computed as average of impressions of candidates voters pay attention to, paying more attention to a candidate makes it more likely that voters’ impressions of that candidate have a larger weight on aspirations. In other words, attention probabilities affect the aspirations \(a_{\theta }\) in a stationary distribution. Furthermore, probabilities of positive impression \(q_{\theta }(.)\) depend on aspirations, yielding the indirect effect. However, this indirect effect is second-order, and not likely to dominate the direct effect we discuss above. For this reason, we set it aside.

  10. In the case of full attentiveness, i.e., \(k=n\), which corresponds to the model of Andonie and Diermeier (2022), the process has a unique stationary distribution.

  11. Under negative plurality, if attentiveness is endogenous then the distribution of the event vector \(e_{\theta }^{t}\) can never be stationary, and so Proposition 1 does not apply. Moreover, it is easy to see that the process cannot have distributions where the vote measures are stationary.

  12. The formal condition that “the average \(v_{\theta }^{1}\) for candidate 1 is sufficiently larger than the same average for the other candidates” is complicated, and we omit stating it formally in the proposition. In general, the condition depends not only on the fixed components \(v_{\theta }^{i}\) and group shares \(s_{\theta }\), but also on other parameters, e.g, distribution F(.), etc. (see the proof to Proposition 3 in the appendix).

  13. Recall that in our model aspirations are means of past impressions. Therefore, if past impressions are negative, then aspirations will be low.

  14. Under negative plurality, we assume that \(r_{R}(3)\) is “sufficiently” close to 1. We assume this additional condition for the following reason. From previous propositions, under negative plurality, the vote measure of a candidate increases if voters pay less attention to that candidate. Therefore, even though all voters rank candidate 3 at the bottom, if the attention probability \(r_{R}(3)\) is low enough, the vote measure of candidate 3 can increase so that it surpasses that of candidate 1 or candidate 2. To shut down this effect, which we separately analysed previously, we make the assumption that \(r_{R}(3)\) is “sufficiently” large.

  15. The cutoff \(v^{*}\) is characterized by the implicit equation: \((3-F( \frac{2v^{*}:-1}{4\alpha }))(8-F(\frac{2v^{*}-3}{4\alpha })-F(\frac{ 1+2v^{*}}{4\alpha }))=16\).

  16. In the quasi-stationary distribution under negative plurality, each of the three candidates can win, but the probability that candidate 3 wins is smaller than the probability that candidate 1 or candidate 2 wins.

  17. We can think of this specification as a simplified form of the following more detailed conception of news coverage. Suppose the distribution of impressions of candidate i among voters of type \(\theta\) is as follows:

    $$\begin{aligned} \pi _{\theta }^{t}(i):=v_{\theta }^{i}+\chi ^{i}+\xi ^{i}+\alpha \epsilon _{\theta }^{t}(i), \end{aligned}$$

    where \(\chi ^{i}\) is a binary random variable that can take values “\(+\nu ^{i}\)” and “\(-\nu ^{i}\)”, with probabilities \(\pi ^{i}\), and \(1-\pi ^{i}\) respectively; and \(\xi ^{i}\) is a continuous random variable with a symmetric, single-peaked, distribution around 0. The two additional random variables, \(\chi ^{i}\) and \(\xi ^{i}\), model the following two features. First, in some periods the news coverage of a candidate can be positive, i.e., when the realization of \(\chi ^{i}\) is \(+\nu ^{i}\), and in other periods news coverage can be negative, i.e., when the realization of \(\chi ^{i}\) is \(-\nu ^{i}\). Second, some voters may interpret some news as good, while others may interpret the same news as bad. This is captured by the second random variable \(\xi ^{i}\). This more detailed extension, however, is equivalent to the specification above, where \(\mu ^{i}\) corresponds to the expectation of \(\chi ^{i}\), and the uncertainty is combined into the random term \(\epsilon _{\theta }^{t}(i)\).

  18. The effect of an increase of \(\mu ^{i}\) on the mean of impressions \(\pi _{\theta }(i)\) is larger than the effect on the aspirations \(a_{\theta }\), and so the probability of positive impression \(q_{\theta }(i)\) increases with \(\mu ^{i}\).

  19. Here, we focus our analysis on plurality rule. The analysis under the two other rules is similar.

  20. To see that, consider first the effect of an increase in the impression probability \(q_{\theta }(i)\) on the distribution of vote measures. An increase of \(q_{\theta }(i)\) (assuming \(q_{\theta }(l)\), for \(l\ne i\), are fixed) induces an increase in the vote measure of candidate i, \(S_{\theta }(i)\), and a decrease in the vote measure of each candidate \(j\ne i\), \(S_{\theta }(j)\). Consider now in addition the effect of a decrease in the impression probabilities \(q_{\theta }(l)\), for each candidate \(l\ne i\). First, \(S_{\theta }(i)\) further increases. Second, we note that the measure of abstentions \(S_{\theta }(A)\) increases as well, as voters become less likely to have positive impressions of candidates \(l\ne i\). This implies that, on average, the vote measure of a candidate \(j\ne i\) further decreases. The vote measures \(S_{\theta }(j)\), for \(j\ne i\), decrease on average, however, the vote measure of some candidates \(l\ne i\) may increase, depending on their ranks in the vector of fixed components \(u_{\theta }\), and the shape of the distribution function of the random component \(\epsilon\).

  21. For technical reasons in the case of negative plurality we derive “quasi-stationary” distributions.

References

  • Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2002). Blind retrospection: Electoral responses to droughts, flu, and shark attacks. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Boston, September 2002.

  • Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2004). Musical chairs: Pocketbook voting and the limits of democratic accountability. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the APSA, Chicago, September 2004.

  • Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not produce responsive government. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anagol, S., & Fujiwara, T. (2016). The runner-up effect. Journal of Political Economy, 124(4), 927–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2017). Path-dependency and coordination in multi-candidate elections with behavioral voters. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 29(4), 520–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2019). Impressionable voters. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 11(1), 79–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andonie, C., & Diermeier, D. (2022). Electoral institutions with impressionable voters. Social Choice and Welfare, 59, 683–733.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, L. (1988). Presidential primaries and the dynamics of public choice. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, F., & Jones, B. (2009). Agendas and instability in American politics. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bendor, J. (2010). Bounded rationality and politics. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., Siegel, D., & Ting, M. (2011). A behavioral theory of elections. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bendor, J., Diermeier, D., & Ting, M. (2003). A behavioral model of turnout. American Political Science Review, 97, 261–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgers, T., & Sarin, R. (2000). Naive reinforcement learning with endogenous aspirations. International Economic Review, 41, 921–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouton, L. (2013). A theory of strategic voting in runoff elections. American Economic Review, 103, 1248–1288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouton, L., & Castanheira, M. (2012). One person, many votes: Divided majority and information aggregation. Econometrica, 80(1), 43–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bush, R., & Mosteller, F. (1955). Stochastic models of learning. Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cho, I., & Matsui, A. (2005). Learning aspiration in repeated games. Journal of Economic Theory, 124, 171–2001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, S., Healy, A., & Werker, E. (2012). Do voters demand responsive governments? Evidence from Indian disaster relief. Journal of Development Economics, 97, 167–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G. (1987). Electoral equilibrium under alternative voting institutions. American Journal of Political Science, 31(1), 82–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G. (1997). Making votes count. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cyert, R., & March, J. (1963). A behavioral theory of the firm. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diermeier, D., & Li, C. (2017). Electoral control with behavioral voters. Journal of Politics, 79(3), 890–902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duverger, M. (1954). Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, J., & Reeves, A. (2011). Make it rain? Retrospection and the attentive electorate in the context of natural disasters. American Journal of Political Science, 55(2), 340–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, B., & Baumgartner, F. (2005). The politics of attention: How government prioritizes problems. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karandikar, R., Mookherjee, D., Ray, D., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1998). Evolving aspirations and cooperation. Journal of Economic Theory, 80, 292–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingdon, J. (2003). Agendas, alternatives, and public policies. Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ledyard, J. (1984). The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice, 44, 7–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myatt, D. (2007). On the theory of strategic voting. Review of Economic Studies, 74, 255–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myatt, D., & Fisher, S. (2002). Tactical coordination in plurality electoral systems. Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 18(4), 504–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. (1999). Theoretical comparisons of electoral systems. European Economic Review, 43, 671–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. (2002). Comparison of scoring rules in Poisson voting games. Journal of Economic Theory, 103, 219–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R., & Weber, R. (1993). A theory of voting equilibria. American Political Science Review, 87, 102–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T. (1989). A mathematical proof of Duverger’s law. In P. Ordeshook (Ed.), Models of strategic choice in politics (pp. 69–92). University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1983). A strategic calculus of voting. Public Choice, 41, 7–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T., & Rosenthal, H. (1985). Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. American Political Science Review, 79, 62–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palomino, F., & Vega-Redondo, F. (1999). Convergence of aspirations and (partial) cooperation in the prisoner’s dilemma. International Journal of Game Theory, 28, 465–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sides, J., & Vavreck, L. (2013). The gamble: Choice and chance in the 2012 presidential election. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69(1), 99–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1971). Designing organizations for an information-rich world. In M. Greenberger (Ed.), Computers, communications and the public interest. Johns Hopkins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorndike, E. (1898). Animal intelligence: An experimental study of the associative processes in animals. Psychological Review (Monograph Supplement), 2(8), 4–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfers, J. (2002). Voters rational? evidence from gubernatorial elections. Stanford GSB Working Paper no. 1730, https://www.gsb.stanford.edu/faculty-research/workingpapers/are-voters-rational-evidence-gubernatorial-elections.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Costel Andonie.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file 1 (pdf 389 KB)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andonie, C., Diermeier, D. Attentiveness in elections with impressionable voters. Public Choice (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01161-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-024-01161-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation