Skip to main content
Log in

Progressive Democracy: the ideology of the modern predatory state

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The state must expend resources to credibly threaten the use of force, and the actual use of force is more costly than just exercising the threat. A population that views itself as prey to a predatory state will resist the state’s demands and will not produce much that the state can appropriate. The predatory state will be more successful if it can convince its citizens that the state’s activities are in the public interest, which will enhance voluntary compliance with the state’s mandates and lessen the need for the state to invest resources in overt coercion. The ideology of “Progressive Democracy” encourages citizens to cooperate with the state, and legitimizes the state’s predatory activities. The ideology of Progressivism justifies the imposition of costs on some for the benefit of others. The ideology of democracy implies that when a democratic government does this, it is acting in the public interest.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Locke’s idea was quite literally revolutionary, according to Bailyn (1967), who explains that pamphleteers who agitated for the American Revolution in 1776 made frequent reference to Locke’s ideas to support their cause. Bailyn says that while most Americans at the time probably did not read Locke, they would have been familiar with Locke’s name because of those pamphleteers.

  2. McCloskey (2006) and Pinker (2018) make powerful arguments and present good evidence on the contribution of Enlightenment ideas to human prosperity and general well-being.

  3. Survey data for this and other questions in the World Values Survey are found at www.worldvaluessurvey.org/WVSOnline.jsp, accessed December 27, 2018. The responses cited here are from Wave 6, the most recent one available, which questioned those surveyed from 2010 to 2016.

  4. Holcombe (2002) explains this idea in more detail, examining the constitutional history of the United States. Things are less clear-cut in European democracies that do not have the same explicit founding documents. Congleton (2011) gives a good discussion of the evolution of constitutional ideas and liberal democracy in European governments.

  5. While this is a translation from the French original, it is interesting to note that it refers to people as a singular rather than plural concept, further reinforcing Rousseau’s idea that a general will exists that encompasses all citizens.

  6. Forceful criticism of this framework of hypothetical agreement is presented by Yeager (1985, 2001).

  7. Buchanan (1975, pp. 175–176) does criticize Rawls for speculating on the outcomes that would emerge from the process Rawls recommends.

  8. As previously noted, Buchanan and Tullock (1962, ch. 6) refer to this as expected external costs.

  9. A few members of the economic elite can offer sufficient funds to parties and candidates such that their political actions can make a difference. It is interesting to see the way in which the political elite objects to this conclusion, arguing that the influence of money on politics is pernicious, even as they devote much of their own time to fund-raising. Politicians argue that citizens should become more engaged in the political process, because they realize that higher voter turnout legitimizes their political power, but when citizens who actually can make a difference get involved, those same politicians object strenuously to their engagement. Note, however, that if the members of the economic elite donate to their political campaigns, the donations are readily accepted.

References

  • Anderson, T. L., & Hill, P. J. (1980). The birth of a transfer society. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailyn, B. (1967). The ideological origins of the American revolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, L. M. (2008). Unequal democracy: The political economy of the new gilded age. New York, Princeton: Russell Sage Foundation; Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beard, C. (1913). An economic interpretation of the Constitution of the United States. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (1997). Democracy and decision: The pure theory of electoral preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1962). The relevance of Pareto optimality. Journal of Conflict Resolution,6(4), 341–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1975). The limits of liberty: Between anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B. (2007). The myth of the rational voter: Why democracies choose bad public policies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2011). Perfecting parliament: Constitutional reform, liberalism, and the rise of Western democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, M. (1964). The symbolic uses of politics. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, D. (1989). The machinery of freedom: A guide to radical capitalism (2nd ed.). La Salle, IL: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilens, M. (2012). Affluence and influence: Economic inequality and political power in America. New York: Russell Sage Foundation and Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, J. S., & Pierson, P. (2010). Winner-take-all politics: How Washington made the rich richer—and turned its back on the middle class. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. ([1651] 1950). Leviathan. New York: E.P. Dutton.

  • Hochman, H. M., & Rodgers, J. D. (1969). Pareto optimal redistribution. American Economic Review,59(4), 542–557.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (1994). The economic foundations of government. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (2002). From liberty to democracy: The transformation of American government. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, R. G. (2018). Political capitalism: How economic and political power is made and maintained. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolko, G. (1963). The triumph of conservatism: A reinterpretation of American history, 1900–1916. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, A. O. (1974). The political economy of the rent-seeking society. American Economic Review,64, 291–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. (2012). Ordeals. Journal of Law and Economics,55(3), 691–714.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. (2013a). Vermin trials. Journal of Law and Economics,56(3), 811–836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. (2013b). “God Damn”: The law and economics of monastic malediction. Journal of Law Economics and Organization,30(1), 193–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. (2013c). Gypsy law. Public Choice,155(3/4), 273–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. (2014). Oracles. Rationality and Society,26(2), 141–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T., & Coyne, C. J. (2012). Sassywood. Journal of Comparative Economics,40(4), 608–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, M. (1988). Of rule and revenue. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. ([1690] 1967). Two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • McCloskey, D. N. (2006). The bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an age of commerce. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D. C. (1981). Structure and change in economic history. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1982). The rise and decline of nations. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (2000). Power and prosperity: Outgrowing communist and capitalist dictatorships. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2018). Enlightenment now: The case for reason, science, humanism, and progress. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Belknap: Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M. N. (1973). For a new liberty. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J. J. (1762). The social contract, or principles of political right (G. D. H. Cole, Trans.). www.constitution.org/jjr/socon.htm.

  • Stigler, G. J. (1971). The theory of economic regulation. Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science,2(1), 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G. J., & Becker, G. S. (1977). De gustibus non est disputandum. American Economic Review,67(2), 76–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E. (2012). The price of inequality: How today’s divided society endangers the future. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare cost of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal,5, 224–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1971). The charity of the uncharitable. Economic Inquiry,9(4), 379–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1983). Economics of income redistribution. Boston, MA: Kluwer-Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Usher, D. (1992). The welfare economics of markets, voting, and predation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittman, D. A. (1989). Why democracies produce efficient results. Journal of Political Economy,97(6), 1395–1424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittman, D. A. (1995). The myth of democratic failure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeager, L. B. (1985). Rights, contract, and utility in policy espousal. Cato Journal,5(1), 259–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeager, L. B. (2001). Ethics as a social science: The moral philosophy of social cooperation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Randall G. Holcombe.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Holcombe, R.G. Progressive Democracy: the ideology of the modern predatory state. Public Choice 182, 287–301 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00637-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00637-z

Keywords

Navigation