Skip to main content
Log in

A justification for excuses: Brown’s discussion of the knowledge view of justification and the excuse manoeuvre

  • Book Review
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Fallibilism: Evidence and Knowledge, Jessica Brown identifies a number of problems for the so-called knowledge view of justification. According to this (unorthodox) view, we cannot justifiably believe what we do not know. Most epistemologists reject this view on the grounds that false beliefs can be justified if, say, supported by the evidence or produced by reliable processes. We think this is a mistake and that many epistemologists are (mistakenly) classifying beliefs as justified because they have properties that indicate that something should be excused. Brown thinks that previous attempts to make this case have been unsuccessful. While the difficulties Brown points to are genuine, I think they show that attempts to explain a classificatory judgment haven't been successful. Still, I would argue that the classification is correct. We need a better explanation of this classificatory judgment. (The situation is similar to the one in which we correctly distinguish knowledge from non-knowledge but then embarrass ourselves trying to explain what this difference consists in.) I will try to clarify the justification-excuse distinction and explain why it's a mistake to insist that beliefs that violate epistemic norms might be justified. Just as it's possible for a rational agent to act without justification in spite of her best intentions (e.g., by using force or violence in trying to defend another from a merely apparent threat), it's possible that a rational thinker who follows the evidence and meets our expectations might nevertheless believe without sufficient justification. If our justified beliefs are supposed to guide us in deciding what to do, we probably should draw on discussions from morality and the law about the justification/excuse distinction to inform our understanding of the epistemic case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. This view is controversial even amongst knowledge-firsters. While Sutton (2007), Williamson (2016), and I defend it, we can find alternative knowledge-first approaches to justification or rationality in Bird (2007), Dutant and Littlejohn (2021), and Ichikawa (2017).

  2. To be sure, there might be other more ‘subjective’ senses of justification just as we might distinguish between different readings of ‘ought’. My impression is that most critics of J = K think that the view isn’t true of any notion of justification. If they were pluralists who were content to admit that there were different readings of ‘justified’ that, say, connected to different readings of ‘ought’, they might acknowledge that there is some legitimate notion of justification that is identified with knowledge and say that they choose to discuss some other notion. Their attitude instead seems to be that we can see the view is false without considering different readings of the normative language.

  3. Suppose I concede that I don’t know whether it was you who spoiled the surprise party I’ve been planning. Having conceded this, I cannot reasonably continue to be upset with you for doing that. Why not? It’s not because doing such a thing wouldn’t be upsetting, but precisely because I cannot reasonably continue to take you to be responsible for this. Acknowledged ignorance enjoins suspension.

  4. In thinking about whether this challenge can be met, I found Boult’s (2017) discussion of a virtue-theoretic approach as an alternative to the more familiar dispositional approach of Lasonen-Aarnio (2018) and Williamson (2016) particularly helpful.

  5. This distinction was used by Bach (1985) and Engel (1992) to try to argue that some of the intuitions elicited by Cohen’s (1984) new evil demon thought experiment are compatible with their reliabilist views. The distinction also appears early in the Gettier literature. See Lowy (1978).

  6. This fits with Fletcher’s take on the case when he says, ‘Whether a wrongful actor is excused does not affect the rights of other persons to resist or to assist the wrongful actor. But claims of justification do’ (2000: 760). This is, of course, controversial. Baron (2007), for example, takes the view that objective features of the situation don’t have any bearing on justification. To my mind, this comes with a cost. As Zimmerman (2008) notes, if you take this line, you probably have to deny that the innocent person Bertrand assaults, shoots, stabs, etc. didn’t have any right not to be assaulted, shot, stabbed, etc. Rights have correlative duties. On the view that Baron and Zimmerman defend, since there’s no duty not to shoot the person who has the misfortune of looking like a dangerous person, there’s no right here to violate. Explaining intuitions about justified interference and reparative duties gets tricky. This, in my view, is the clear sign that they’ve made a mistake. I don’t think people critical of J = K typically think that they’re embracing this kind of view. Most of them would probably complain that being shot by someone who mistakes them for a threat isn’t just one of those bad things that happened. They’d probably think that, at the very least, they are owed something by the shooter and it’s hard to see how such a rich normative relation could obtain just because someone out there permissibly did something that was bad in some way.

  7. Bird (2007) and Ichikawa (2017) defend similar views.

  8. I understand that this assumes that, say, the Kantian view that the normative is only concerned with the quality of the agent’s will, but short of defending this sweeping philosophical view, it’s going to be hard to deny that Bertrand’s behaviour couldn’t have violated any norm (e.g., Battery).

  9. As Gardner puts it, ‘The gist of an excuse … is precisely that the person with the excuse lived up to our expectations’ (2008: 124).

  10. I’ll assume that Arpaly (2002) is right that the kind of responsiveness that matters is de re responsiveness, not de dicto.

  11. In some cases, norms can conflict. Think of the clash between non-maleficence and justice. K- and K + aren’t like this. There’s no situation in which they both apply to an agent and, say, pressure her to believe and to suspend. Nevertheless, they pull in different directions and given uncertainty about which one applies, it still makes sense to approach this case in the way we might approach norms that can conflict in the same situation provided that we can compare the degree of wrongdoing that results from violating these norms.

  12. For discussion and defence of views of the subjective ought in the neighbourhood of this idea, see Lazar (2020) and Olsen (2018).

  13. With sufficient patience, we might run through preface cases of varying sizes to get a sense of when we think it’s reasonable for someone with n beliefs who is highly certain that some subset of those beliefs constitute knowledge to retain belief in each of the n-propositions. We won’t ever locate the threshold, but the situation doesn’t seem different from that of trying to determine the force of reasons to keep promises and refrain from killing strangers in deciding when it’s irresponsible to drive somewhere (and thus increasing the chance of killing a stranger) to ensure that the promise is kept.

  14. See Dorst (2019) for a discussion of how the threshold can be set that focuses on a veritist value theory. If the above is right, there might be a further problem with the dispositional account. On Williamson’s (2014) description of his unmarked clock cases, a thinker could know even when it’s nearly certain on her evidence that she doesn’t. If showing sensitivity to risk is part of meeting expectations, a thinker might believe what she knows (i.e., conforming to K + and K-), have the disposition to conform to K- and K + (if risk-sensitivity isn’t part of the disposition), and respond in the way that someone disposed to conform to K- and K + would. Intuitively, however, it seems unreasonable to believe in this case given the risk of violating K-. The problem is easily addressed by building risk-sensitivity into the relevant dispositions, but it’s worth noting that the risk-sensitivity condition seems important for addressing a number of objections to the dispositional account.

References

  • Arpaly, N. (2002). Unprincipled virtue. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1956). A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1985). A rationale for reliabilism. The Monist, 68, 246–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. (2007). Excuses, excuses. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 1, 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Justified judging. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 81–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boult, C. (2017). Epistemic normativity and the justification-excuse distinction. Synthese, 194, 4065–4081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. 2018. Fallibilism: Evidence and knowledge. Oxford University Press.

  • Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth. Philosophical Studies, 46, 279–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorst, K. (2019). Lockeans maximize expected accuracy. Mind, 128, 175–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutant, J., & Littlejohn, C. (2021). Defeaters as indicators of ignorance. In J. Brown & M. Simion (Eds.), Reasons, justification, and defeat. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, M. (1992). Personal and doxastic justification in epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 67, 133–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. (2000). Rethinking Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (2008). Offences and defences. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2016). Virtue ethics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Ichikawa, J. (2017). Contextualising knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2018). Virtuous failure and victims of deceit. In J. Dutant & F. Dorsch (Eds.), The new evil demon. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazar, S. (2020). Duty and doubt. Journal of Practical Ethics, 8, 28–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2009). The externalist’s demon. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39, 399–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth-connection. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2014). The unity of reason. In C. Littlejohn & J. Turri (Eds.), Epistemic norms. Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lowy, C. (1978). gettier’s notion of justification. Mind, 87, 105–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. (1997). Placing blame. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsen, K. (2018). Subjective rightness and minimizing expected objective wrongness. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 417–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2007). Without Justification. MIT University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2014). very improbable knowing. Erkenntnis, 79, 971–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2016). Justifications, excuses, and skeptical scenarios. In F. Dorsch & F. Dutant (Eds.), The new evil demon. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. (2008). Living with Uncertainty. Cambridge University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Clayton Littlejohn.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Littlejohn, C. A justification for excuses: Brown’s discussion of the knowledge view of justification and the excuse manoeuvre. Philos Stud 179, 2683–2696 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01786-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01786-6

Keywords

Navigation