Skip to main content
Log in

Ramified structure

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Russell–Myhill theorem threatens a familiar structured conception of propositions according to which two sentences express the same proposition only if they share the same syntactic structure and their corresponding syntactic constituents share the same semantic value. Given the role of the principle of universal instantiation in the derivation of the theorem in simple type theory, one may hope to rehabilitate the core of the structured view of propositions in ramified type theory, where the principle is systematically restricted. We suggest otherwise. The ramified core of the structured theory of propositions remains inconsistent in ramified type theory augmented with axioms of reducibility. This is significant because reducibility has been thought to be perfectly consistent with the ramified approach to the intensional antinomies. Nor is the addition of reducibility to ramified type theory sufficient to restore other intensional puzzles such as Prior’s paradox or Kripke’s puzzle about time and thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is not uncommon to construe the vicious circle principle as a constraint on explicit comprehension principles, which provide a partial specification of the range of the variables of each type. In the propositional case, comprehension follows from a suitable formulation of existential generalization for quantification into sentence position. In the more general case, comprehension is derivable from existential generalization in the presence of a device of lambda abstraction governed by extensional beta equivalence.

  2. Here we follow Church (1976) and depart from Russell (1908), which uses the term ’order’ for what Church calls a level. Like Church, we reserve the term ’order’ for a measure of the complexity of a ramified type and the variables that belong to it.

  3. Uzquiano (2021) discusses the link between the two results in more detail.

  4. Thanks to an anonymous referee for the question of what is the role of sets in Kripke’s puzzle about time and thought.

  5. In this respect, our presentation comes closer to Hazen and Davoren (2000). Other versions of ramified type theory are developed in Myhill (1979), Hazen (1983), and Hodes (2015). While these versions of ramified type theory differ from the present one in other respects, these differences are generally unimportant for present purposes.

  6. This is one slight departure from Church (1976), who defines the order of a variable (rather than that of the r-type to which it belongs.)

  7. Thanks to an anonymous referee for the suggestion.

  8. (Church 1976, p. 750) takes for granted a standard axiomatization of quantificational logic to which the comprehension axioms are supposed to be added.

  9. Instances of the first schema become instances of the second, more general schema when formulas are construed as 0-place propositional functions.

  10. This is not to deny there may be other motivations for ramification. Hodes (2015), for example, does considers an independent motivation grounded on a substitutional interpretation of quantification into certain grammatical types.

References

  • Bacon, A., Hawthorne, J., & Uzquiano, G. (2016). Higher-order free logic and the Prior-Kaplan paradox. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46, 493–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church, Alonzo. (1956). Introduction to mathematical logic. Princeton University Press.

  • Church, Alonzo. (1976). Comparison of Russell’s resolution of the semantical antinomies with that of Tarski. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 41(4), 747–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, Cian. (2016). To be F is to be G. Philosophical Perspectives, 30, 39–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fritz, P., Lederman, H., Uzquiano, G. (2021). Closed structure. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1–43.

  • Goodman, Jeremy. (2017). Reality is not structured. Analysis, 77, 43–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hazen, Allen. (1983). Predicative logics. In Handbook of philosophical logic, pp. 331–407. Springer.

  • Hazen, A. P., & Davoren, Jen M. (2000). Russell’s 1925 logic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78(4), 534–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodes, Harold T. (2015). Why ramify? Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 56(2), 379–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, David. (1995). A problem in possible-world semantics. In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Diana Raffma, & Nicholas Asher (Eds.), Modality, Morality and Belief: Essays in Honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus (pp. 41–52). Cambridge University Press.

  • Kripke Saul, A. (2011). A puzzle about time and thought. In Saul A. Kripke (Ed.), Philosophical Troubles. Oxford University Press.

  • Martino, Enrico. (2001). Russellian type theory and semantical paradoxes. In Logic, Meaning and Computation, pp. 491–505. Springer.

  • Myhill, John. (1958). Problems arising in the formalization of intensional logic. Logique et Analyse, 1, 78–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myhill, John. (1979) A refutation of an unjustified attack on the axiom of reducibility. In Bertrand Russell Memorial, pp. 81–90. George Allen and Unwin.

  • Potter, Michael D. (2000). Reason’s Nearest Kin: Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap. Oxford University Press.

  • Prior, A. N. (1961). On a family of paradoxes. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 2, 16–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. (1903). The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge University Press.

  • Russell, Bertrand. (1908). Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types. American Journal of Mathematics, 30(3), 222–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B., & Whitehead, A. N. (1910). Principia Mathematica (Vol. I). Cambridge University Press.

  • Tucker, Dustin. (2018). Paradoxes and restricted quantification: A non-hierarchical approach. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 7(3), 190–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, D., & Thomason, R. H. (2011). Paradoxes of intensionality. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(3), 394–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uzquiano, Gabriel. (2015). A neglected resolution of Russell’s paradox of propositions. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 8, 328–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uzquiano, Gabriel. (2021). Elusive propositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1–21.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I presented earlier versions of this paper at a conference on higher-order metaphysics at the University of Birmingham and at the conference on Paradox, Context, and Generality at the University of Salzburg in summer of 2019. I greatly benefitted from the feedback I received from the two audiences. Thanks as well to Paul Egré, Peter Fritz, Michael Glanzberg, Jeremy Goodman, Nick Jones, Julien Murzi, Agustín Rayo, Lorenzo Rossi, James Studd. Special thanks to Amirhossein Kiani, Øystein Linnebo, and an anonymous referee for detailed comments on an earlier version of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gabriel Uzquiano.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Uzquiano, G. Ramified structure. Philos Stud 180, 1651–1674 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01780-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01780-y

Keywords

Navigation