Skip to main content
Log in

What it means to respect individuality

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Using pure statistical evidence about a group to judge a particular member of that group is often found objectionable. One natural explanation of why this is objectionable appeals to the moral notion of respecting individuality: to properly respect individuality, we need individualized evidence, not pure statistical evidence. However, this explanation has been criticized on the ground that there is no fundamental difference between the so-called “individualized evidence” and “pure statistical evidence”. This paper defends the respecting-individuality explanation by developing an account of what it means to respect individuality. It combines an idealistic account of respecting individuality and a prioritization account of respecting individuality, and offers a principled way to distinguish individualized evidence from non-individualized evidence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the sake of argument, let's assume that the situation is such that any bystander in the peddler's position would easily perceive Austin as talking to the woman standing next to him and that this is apparent to Austin upon reflection.

  2. Smith v. Rapid Transit, 317 Mass. 469, 470, 58 N.E.2d 754, 755 (1945).

  3. United States v. Montero-Camargo, 208 F.3d 1122, 1134 (9th Cir. 2000), emphasis in original.

  4. Some recent epistemically based accounts for distinguishing between individualized and pure statistical evidence, such as Enoch et al. (2012), seem to hold this “yes-or-no” view too.

  5. Whether a piece of evidence e confirms or disconfirms a belief B is understood in the Bayesian way: e confirms B if the probability of B being true given e is greater than that without e; e disconfirms B if the probability of B being true given e is smaller than that without e; e neither confirms nor disconfirms B if the probability of B being true given e is equal to that without e.

  6. O(e) is not modified by I(y) because only when the information is not yet considered, the significance of the impact that the formed belief has on Y increases the importance to obtain that information and thus the threshold of unavailability.

  7. The problem underlying these two cases is often referred to as the “reference class problem”.

  8. This is, of course, not suggesting that the prior information (or base rate, as it is often called) does not count at all. Informative prior distributions (based on the base rate) are used to lower the posterior variation if the data are considered inaccurate or highly uncertain; non-informative prior distributions are used when the data are highly certain. In other words, high-quality individualized evidence is prioritized in Bayesian practices. In Disease, since the accuracy of the medical test is relatively high, the prior probability is weighed lightly; were the accuracy of the medical test sufficiently low, the prior probability would be weighed more heavily. Di Bello (2019) gives a detailed discussion of the application of Bayesian theory in statistically grounded beliefs..

  9. Respecting individuality is best understood as a subjective moral duty, and thus it does not require our justification to be grounded on something that is objectively true of Y.

  10. This echoes Moss's point that “in many situations where you are forming beliefs about a person, you morally should keep in mind the possibility that they might be an exception to statistical generalizations”, which Moss calls the “rule of consideration”. See Moss (2018a, p. 221).

  11. See, for example, Churchman (1948), Rudner (1953), Hempel (1965), and more recently Douglas (2000).

  12. We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for this journal for raising this objection.

  13. What is at issue here is whether a belief is subjectively justified, not whether it constitutes knowledge. Thus, those well-known counterexamples, such as the Fake-Barn cases, should not concern us.

  14. One may worry that the “social meaning” of a mechanism can be morally problematic. For example, there might exist a mechanism of racialization that determines how much money people of different race earn, and we can reasonably believe that this mechanism operates on everybody. It follows that, on our account, “race” qualifies as individualized evidence for how much money one earns. We think, if there indeed exists such a mechanism, “race” does count as individualized evidence. In reality, race does not count precisely because we cannot reasonably believe such a universal mechanism exists. Moreover, calling “race” individualized evidence in this case does not suggest that the mechanism itself is morally justified. The latter is a completely different issue.

  15. As we discussed in the previous section, the possibility that the observation is incorrect is a flaw internal to the observational model, not one pertaining to respecting individuality.

  16. This explains, in the famous Blue Bus Case, why a witness’s testimony of seeing a blue bus passing through the area should be treated differently from the pure statistical evidence that a bus from the blue bus company has a high probability of passing through that area during that specific time. Even though a witness’s testimony can be mistaken, it is formed through an epistemic process that respects the defendant’s individuality. Consequently, insofar as the testimony’s reliability is not much lower than that of non-individualized counterevidence, using that testimony properly respects the defendant’s individuality.

  17. Lippert-Rasmussen raised a similar worry by using cases involving “non-autonomous minors” (2011: 53). It is debatable whether minors are truly “non-autonomous”. But the general point behind his worry is valid.

  18. For more detailed discussion on the difficulties facing the sensitivity account, see Blome-Tillmann (2015) and Pardo (2018).

References

  • Basu, R. (2018). The wrongs of racist beliefs. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1137-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beeghly, E. (2018). Failing to treat persons as individuals. Ergo, 5(26), 687–711.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2015). Sensitivity, causality, and statistical evidence in courts of law. Thought, 4, 102–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2017). More likely than not’—Knowledge first and the role of bare statistical evidence in courts of law. In J. A. Carter, E. C. Gordon, & B. Jarvis (Eds.), Knowledge first—Approaches to epistemology and mind (pp. 278–292). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blum, L. (2002). “I’m not a racist, but…”: The moral quandary of race. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, R. (2018). The rational impermissibility of accepting (some) racial generalizations. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1809-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchman, C. W. (1948). Theory of experimental inference. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bello, M. (2019). Trial by statistics: Is a high probability of guilt enough to convict? Mind, 128, 1045–1084.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. E. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eidelson, B. (2015). Discrimination and disrespect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., & Fisher, T. (2015). Sense and ‘sensitivity’: Epistemic and instrumental approaches to statistical evidence. Stanford Law Review, 67, 557–611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., Spectre, L., & Fisher, T. (2012). Statistical evidence, sensitivity, and the legal value of knowledge. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40(3), 197–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, G. (2019). Legal burdens of proof and statistical evidence. In D. Coady & J. Chase (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of applied epistemology (pp. 179–195). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2012). Better safe than sensitive. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 193–206). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, D. (2018). The epistemic commitments of nondiscrimination. Virginia Public Law and Legal Theory Research Paper No. 2018-60.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Science and human values. In C. G. Hempel (Ed.), Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 81–96). New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, S. (2007). The limits of loyalty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Khaitan, T. (2015). A theory of discrimination law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levin, M. (1992). Responses to race differences in crime. Journal of Social Philosophy, 23(1), 5–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2011). ‘We are all different’: Statistical discrimination and the right to be treated as an individual. Journal of Ethics, 15, 47–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2014). Born free and equal?: A philosophical inquiry into the nature of discrimination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, X. (2015). No fats, femmes, or Asians. Moral Philosophy and Politics, 2(2), 255–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1999). Principles of social justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mogensen, A. (2017). Racial profiling and cumulative injustice. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. (2018a). Probabilistic knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. (2018b). Moral encroachment. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 118(2), 177–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pace, M. (2011). The epistemic value of moral considerations: Justification, moral encroachment, and James’ ‘will to believe’. Noûs, 45, 239–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pardo, M. (2018). Safety vs. sensitivity: Possible worlds and the law of evidence. Legal Theory, 24, 50–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert, C. (2007). The Bayesian choice: From decision theoretic foundations to computational implementation. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. (2003). Profiles, probabilities, and stereotypes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2018). Rational stability under pragmatic encroachment. Episteme, 15(3), 297–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, S. (2006). Epistemic partiality in friendship. Ethics, 116(3), 498–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1986). Liability and individualized evidence. Law and Contemporary Problems, 49(3), 199–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We want to thank Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Peter Vallentyne, Eddy Keming Chen, Wilfried Hinsch, Ryan Hornbeck, and one anonymous reviewer for this journal and one anonymous reviewer for another journal for very helpful criticisms and suggestions on earlier drafts. This work was presented at the Philosophy Departments of Xiamen University and Nanjing University, and we want to thank the participants, especially Andrea Strollo, for helpful comments. We are also indebted to the “Principles of Cultural Dynamics” program at Free University of Berlin, which funded the research leave that enabled the writing of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Xiaofei Liu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Liu, X., Liang, Y. What it means to respect individuality. Philos Stud 178, 2579–2598 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01563-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01563-3

Keywords

Navigation