Skip to main content
Log in

Experimental ethics, intuitions, and morally irrelevant factors

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. Greene et al. (2009). The study offers a solution to the descriptive part of the trolley problem (which principles govern our responses to trolley scenarios?), not to its moral part (which responses are correct?).

  2. Greene et al. (2009, p. 365).

  3. Musen and Greene, MS; see Singer (1972).

  4. Uhlmann et al. (2009).

  5. For another study of this sort, see Gino et al. (2010).

  6. The moral (ir)relevance of intention, the second of the two factors identified by Greene and colleagues, is less clear (see Greene 2014, pp. 720–721). Note also that Greene and Musen’s study was challenged by Nagel and Waldmann (2013). They found that the apparent distance effect is really due to various confounding variables, such as informational directness, group membership and the relative efficaciousness of one’s helping efforts. But as Greene rightly points out, at least some of these factors are morally irrelevant, too (Greene 2013, p. 378).

  7. Greene (2016a, p. 176).

  8. See Berker (2009), Greene (2010, 2014), Kahane (2013), Kumar and Campbell (2012), Rini (2013) and Sauer (2012). I am not in this article concerned with the normative significance of experimental neuroscientific findings for moral theory (on this see Berker 2009; Kamm 2009; Königs 2018a).

  9. Note that Uhlmann and colleagues confirmed in a pre-test that ethnicity and nationality are typically not considered morally relevant.

  10. The distinction between these two types of intuitions is common in the literature, see e.g. Greene (2014, p. 724), Kagan (1998, pp. 13–14), Kamm (1993, pp. 5–7), McMahan (2013) and Sandberg and Juth (2011, p. 213).

  11. I am here expanding and, I hope, improving on previous characterizations of this type of argument (Berker 2009, p. 321; Kumar and Campbell 2012; Sauer 2018, p. 43).

  12. As previously observed by Kumar and Campbell (2012, pp. 317–318).

  13. At one point, Greene seems reluctant to explicitly endorse this assumption (Greene 2014, p. 713), but he has to if the argument is to be a precise argument from irrelevance against deontology. Due to the mentioned symmetry, he cannot attack the deontological intuition directly by claiming that it, but not the consequentialist response, is triggered by the irrelevant factor. For whenever our case-specific responses vary in response to an irrelevant factor, both responses are sensitive to this irrelevant factor. The deontological intuition is triggered by the irrelevant fact that the victim is pushed rather than killed by hitting a switch (or black rather than white). But the consequentialist intuition is likewise triggered by the irrelevant fact that the victim is killed by hitting a switch rather than pushed (or white rather than black).

  14. Greene (2010, p. 21), my emphasis.

  15. Greene (2008, p. 39). Elsewhere, he defines deontological judgments “as ones that are naturally justified in deontological terms (in terms of rights, duties, etc.) and that are more difficult to justify in consequentialist terms”, and consequentialist judgments “as ones that are naturally justified in consequentialist terms (by impartial cost–benefit reasoning) and that are more difficult to justify in deontological terms” (Greene 2014, p. 699). In this paper, I go along with Greene’s definition.

  16. Kumar and Campbell (2012, p. 318).

  17. Kumar and Campbell (2012, p. 322).

  18. Singer (1972) and Unger (1997). Singer’s argument may be an example of a successful precise argument from moral irrelevance. Surely, no one would want to suggest that we should resolve the conflict by concluding that we must not save the drowning child. See Campbell and Kumar (2012) for a related discussion.

  19. Unger has, however, “[i]nformally and intermittently […] asked many students, colleagues and friends” for their intuitions (Unger 1997, p. 31).

  20. Rini (2013, p. 267). Notice, though, that the morally irrelevant factors that Rini discusses also include factors that are external to the moral scenarios themselves, such as framing effects and psychological manipulation. I return to this point below.

  21. Unger (1997, pp. 11–12).

  22. See Bruni et al. (2014, p. 170), Ernst (2007, p. 136) and Kamm (2007, p. 417).

  23. Huemer (2005, p. 100); similarly DePaul (2006, pp. 599–600). Huemer points out elsewhere, however, that case-specific intuitions may eventually turn out to be more susceptible to debunking explanations (Huemer 2008, p 383).

  24. There is the third possibility of claiming that case-specific intuitions have priority over general ones. Preservationists like Frances Kamm are associated with this view. Ethical particularists, who do not believe in moral principles in the first place, are naturally inclined towards this view, too. While in principle conceivable, this would entail that arguments from moral irrelevance do not work at all, as they require that an intuition at a higher level of generality can override the case-specific intuitions. The third possibility is therefore not an option for proponents of arguments from moral irrelevance. These three ways of understanding the relation between general and case-specific intuitions are also distinguished by Kagan (1998, pp. 13–14) and Kamm (1993, pp. 5–7).

  25. Nye (2015).

  26. Singer (1972, p. 236). The principle Singer refers to is: “[I]f it is in our power to prevent something very bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it.” (Singer 1972, p. 231). This raises an interpretative question: Is the duty to give to charity entailed by our obligation to save the drowning child and the moral irrelevance of spatial distance? Or is it directly entailed by the above principle (which would render the other argument obsolete)? I won’t address this interpretative question here (refer e.g. to Nye 2015, p. 630). Singer is inspired by Henry Sidgwick (1981), another utilitarian who favors intuitions at a high level of generality.

  27. Unger (1997). Another skeptic about case-specific intuitions is Shelly Kagan (1989, pp. 13–15, 2016).

  28. This is not to deny that there are many uncontroversial cases, in which Greene’s deontological/consequentialist distinction does not apply. He explains: “When it comes to uncontroversial moral questions, these terms have little meaning. Disapproving of child abuse is both ‘characteristically consequentialist’ and ‘characteristically deontological’, or neither—take your pick. […] These two ‘characteristically’ labels are not very meaningful outside the context of moral dilemmas in which considerations about rights and duties, at least superficially, appear to conflict with an impartial cost–benefit analysis.” (Greene 2016b, p. 179) But ethical inquiry is all about truly controversial questions that involve precisely such a conflict, and there are therefore plenty genuine ‘characteristically deontological’ intuitions that challenge consequentialism.

  29. Kumar and Campbell (2012, p. 313).

  30. See also Berker (2009, p. 325). Note that these intuitions possess independent intuitive plausibility, unlike perhaps the doctrine of double effect (Greene 2014, p. 721).

  31. Liao et al. (2012), Petrinovich and O'Neill (1996), Schnall et al. (2008), Schwitzgebel and Cushman (2012, 2015), Tobia et al. (2013a, b), Wheatley and Haidt (2005) and Wiegmann et al. (2012). In light of the replication crisis, findings like these should be taken with a grain of salt (see e.g. Landy and Goodwin 2015).

  32. As already mentioned, many but not all of the examples discussed by Rini (2013) concern external factors. On the unreliability of moral intuitions due to sensitivity to morally irrelevant external factors, see also Sinnott-Armstrong (2008).

  33. In fact, even Kamm, the leader of the preservationist camp, acknowledges, if only by lip-service, that a moral principle derived from case-specific intuitions may stand in need of further validation: We must “consider the principle on its own, to see if it expresses some plausible value or conception of the person or relations between persons. This is necessary to justify it as a correct principle, one that has normative weight, not merely one that makes all of the case judgments cohere.” (Kamm 2007, p. 5, see also pp. 346, 379). In practice, Kamm shows relatively little interest in whether a principle considered on its own is plausible (Nye 2015, p. 627).

  34. I am here bracketing the problem that intention does seem to be a morally relevant factor.

  35. Berker (2009, p. 325) and Königs (2018a).

  36. See again Campbell and Kumar (2012) for a related discussion.

  37. Greene (2014).

  38. See especially Weinberg et al. (2010), but also e.g. Kauppinen (2014, p. 295).

  39. Schwitzgebel and Cushman (2012, 2015), Tobia et al. (2013a, b) and Wiegmann et al. (forthcoming).

  40. Greene (2008, 2014, p. 718).

  41. See e.g. Uhlmann et al. (2009), Wheatley and Haidt (2005) and Wilson (2002).

  42. Greene (2008, p. 68).

  43. See Königs (2018b, pp. 388–389) and Mihailov (2016, p. 2).

  44. Greene’s argument from moral irrelevance is, however, only one of several different attempts to debunk deontological intuitions (see Berker 2009; Königs 2018a; Paulo 2019).

  45. On this see Königs (2018a, p. 197).

References

  • Berker, S. (2009). The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy & Public Affairs,37(4), 293–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, T., Mameli, M., & Rini, R. A. (2014). The science of morality and its normative implications. Neuroethics,7(2), 159–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R., & Kumar, V. (2012). Moral reasoning on the ground. Ethics,122(2), 273–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, M. (2006). Intuitions in moral inquiry. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (pp. 595–623). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernst, Z. (2007). The liberationists’ attack on moral intuitions. American Philosophical Quarterly,44(2), 129–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gino, F., Shu, L. L., & Bazerman, M. H. (2010). Nameless + harmless = blameless: When seemingly irrelevant factors influence judgment of (un)ethical behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes,111(2), 93–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 3): The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 35–80). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2010). Notes on ‘The normative insignificance of neuroscience’ by Selim Berker. (unpublished manuscript)

  • Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. New York: Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2014). Beyond point-and-shoot morality: Why cognitive (Neuro)science matters for ethics. Ethics,124(4), 695–726.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2016a). Solving the Trolley problem. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A Companion to Experimental Philosophy (pp. 175–189). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2016b). Reply to Driver and Darwall. In S. M. Liao (Ed.), Moral brains: The neuroscience of morality (pp. 170–181). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition,111(3), 364–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical Intuitionism. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2008). Revisionary intuitionism. Social Philosophy and Policy,25(1), 368–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (2016). Solving the trolley problem. In E. Rakowski (Ed.), The Trolley problem mysteries (pp. 151–168). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2013). The armchair and the trolley: An argument for experimental ethics. Philosophical Studies,162(2), 421–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (1993). Morality, mortality: Volume 1: Death and Whom to Save from It. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (2007). Intricate ethics: Rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (2009). Neuroscience and moral reasoning: A note on recent research. Philosophy & Public Affairs,37(4), 330–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2014). Ethics and empirical psychology—Critical remarks one empirical informed ethics. In M. Christen, C. Van Schaik, J. Fischer, M. Huppenbauer, & C. Tanner (Eds.), Empirically informed ethics: Morality between facts and norms (pp. 279–305). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Königs, P. (2018a). On the normative insignificance of neuroscience and dual-process theory. Neuroethics,11(2), 195–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Königs, P. (2018b). Two types of debunking arguments. Philosophical Psychology,31(3), 383–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V., & Campbell, R. (2012). On the normative significance of experimental moral psychology. Philosophical Psychology,25(3), 311–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Does incidental disgust amplify moral judgment? A meta-analytic review of experimental evidence. Perspectives on Psychological Science,10(4), 518–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao, M. S., Wiegmann, A., Alexander, J., & Vong, G. (2012). Putting the trolley in order: Experimental philosophy and the loop case. Philosophical Psychology,25(5), 661–671.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2013). Moral intuition. In H. LaFollette & I. Persson (Eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory (2nd ed., pp. 103–120). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mihailov, E. (2016). Is deontology a moral confabulation? Neuroethics,9(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musen, J. D., & Greene, J. (MS). Mere spatial distance weakens perceived moral obligation to help those in desperate need. (unpublished manuscript)

  • Nagel, J., & Waldmann, M. R. (2013). Deconfounding distance effects in judgments of moral obligation. Journal of Experimental Psychology,39(1), 237–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nye, H. (2015). Directly plausible principles. In C. Daly (Ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of Philosphical Methods. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulo, N. (2019). In search of Greene’s argument. Utilitas,31(1), 38–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology,17(3), 145–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. A. (2013). Making psychology normatively significant. The Journal of Ethics,17(3), 257–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg, J., & Juth, N. (2011). Ethics and intuitions: A reply to Singer. The Journal of Ethics,15(3), 209–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, H. (2012). Morally irrelevant factors: What’s left of the dual process-model of moral cognition? Philosophical Psychology,25(6), 783–811.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, H. (2018). Debunking Arguments in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,34(8), 1096–1109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers. Mind and Language,27(2), 135–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2015). Philosophers’ biased judgments persist despite training, expertise and reflection. Cognition,141, 127–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1981). The methods of ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs,1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Framing moral intuitions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (Vol. 2, pp. 47–76). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2013a). Moral intuitions: Are philosophers experts? Philosophical Psychology,26(5), 629–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K., Chapman, G. B., & Stich, S. (2013b). Cleanliness is next to morality, even for philosophers. Journal of Consciousness Studies,20(11–12), 195–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D. A., Tannenbaum, D., & Ditto, P. H. (2009). The motivated use of moral principles. Judgment and Decision Making,4(6), 476–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1997). Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology,23(3), 331–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science,16(10), 780–784.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiegmann, A., Horvath, J., & Meyer, K. (forthcoming). Intuitive expertise and irrelevant options. In T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Wiegmann, A., Okan, Y., & Nagel, J. (2012). Order effects in moral judgment. Philosophical Psychology,25(6), 813–836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank the anonymous referee, Chiara Brozzo, Christian Seidel, Emilian Mihailov, Hanno Sauer, Irina Schumski, Katharina Brecht, Leo Menges, Michael W. Schmidt, Nora Heinzelmann, Norbert Paulo and audiences in Karlsruhe, Porto, Saarbrücken and Tübingen for their valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Königs.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Königs, P. Experimental ethics, intuitions, and morally irrelevant factors. Philos Stud 177, 2605–2623 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01330-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01330-z

Navigation