Skip to main content
Log in

Experimental philosophy and the fruitfulness of normative concepts

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper provides a new argument for the relevance of empirical research to moral and political philosophy and a novel defense of the positive program in experimental philosophy. The argument centers on the idea that normative concepts used in moral and political philosophy can be evaluated in terms of their fruitfulness in solving practical problems. Empirical research conducted with an eye to the practical problems that are relevant to particular concepts can provide evidence of their fruitfulness along a number of dimensions. An upshot of the argument is that philosophers should not only engage with but must also be involved in conducting experimental studies that examine the practical roles that normative concepts can play. Rather than just clearing the way for philosophical work to be done, the argument has the further implication that empirical research will be required to advance at least some important debates in moral and political philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nadelhoffer and Nahmias (2007), Weinberg (2007), Alexander and Weinberg (2007), Cappelen (2012), Alexander et al. (2014), Fisher (2015), Shepherd and Justus (2015) and Williamson (2016). Knobe (2016) argues that the positive–negative program distinction fails to capture much of the important work being conducted in the field. Sytsma and Livengood (2016) propose a broader taxonomy of programs (non-intuitional, negative, positive, cognitive, and descriptive) and hold that the work that Knobe points to largely falls under what they refer to as the “cognitive program”.

  2. See, e.g., the discussion in the Opinion Pages of the New York Times (X-Phi’s New Take on Old Problems 2010).

  3. Of course, there are some exceptions. See, e.g., Shepherd and Justus (2015).

  4. While I focus primarily on psychological research, the argument that I present in this paper supports a wide role for empirical research from other social sciences in moral and political philosophy. It may also support a broader role for non-empirical research in some of these fields, including economic theory, social choice theory, and game theory, but establishing this point would go beyond the bounds of the present paper. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting that my argument may also encompass some non-empirical research.

  5. I will remain neutral on the degree to which normative concepts employed in other fields of philosophy, such as epistemology or aesthetics, can be similarly evaluated in terms of their fruitfulness. Some commentators have suggested that what I have to say here about moral and political concepts can be extended to these other fields.

  6. Carnap used this term in putting forward a somewhat different view of the practical role that scientific concepts play. I discuss this in Sect. 4.

  7. The distinction between concepts and conceptions is due to Rawls (1971).

  8. Garner (2007) disagrees, but the view that morality should be abolished is not widely held. Walker (2007) emphasizes the negative social roles that moral and political concepts often play, but doesn’t take this to show that we should try to do away with them.

  9. This commitment does not require one to adopt any substantive positions in moral or political philosophy that Aristotle or Aristotelians endorse. It is instead a general commitment regarding how normative concepts should be evaluated, where their fruitfulness should go into such evaluations.

  10. For recent defenses of this view, see Cohen (2008), Enoch (2011), and Estlund (2014).

  11. See Korsgaard (2003) for a characterization of this disagreement in terms of the history of the debate between realism and constructivism in moral philosophy. One need not be a constructivist to endorse what I will say here, but I will suggest that Korsgaard is committed to the fruitfulness of normative concepts mattering to their evaluation in Sect. 2.

  12. The assumption here, of course, is that they have the kinds of deontological moral intuitions that most people report. If the person in question has consequentialist moral intuitions, following those intuitions will involve acting on consequentialist principles.

  13. Luke Buckland, David Rodríguez-Arias, Carissa Véliz, and I have conducted empirical studies examining the effects of reading some of these arguments on charitable giving. See Buckland et al. (unpublished manuscript).

  14. Peter Singer, Paul Slovic, Daniel Västfjäll, Joshua Greene, Marcus Mayorga and I have recently been conducting empirical research on these issues.

  15. See, e.g., Barrett et al. (2001), Payne (2005), and Amodio et al. (2008).

  16. Recent studies have questioned the extent to which both implicit bias and stereotype threat affect the kinds of behaviors thought to be affected by them in in prior research. While some of these effects have not replicated in these studies, other effects, such as the “shooter bias” effect (Correll et al. 2002), have replicated (Essien et al. 2017). There is an ongoing debate about the effects of implicit bias and stereotype threat on particular behaviors and what conclusions can be drawn from this literature for public policy. The point that I am making here relies only on the claim that any negative effects of biases grounded in social group membership on evaluations of others and oneself are worth addressing through the use of normative concepts if doing so is possible, and there is some evidence that this can be done (see Payne 2005).

  17. Working largely within the framework of Carnapian explication, Pinder (2017) argues that experimental philosophy can help to determine whether explicated concepts are fruitful in the sense that they can achieve uptake by “the relevant theoretical community”. Although I find much to agree with in Pinder, my view is not offered within the Carnapian framework, with its emphasis on explication. It is also a commitment of my view that, rather than only achieving uptake by moral and political philosophers, ordinary people as moral agents and citizens are part of the relevant community that moral and political philosophy must be fruitful for. This commitment, I suggest throughout the paper, is not uncommon among moral and political philosophers who take the practical upshots of their views to be philosophically significant.

  18. Mills (2005). See Valentini (2012) for a helpful overview of the ideal/non-ideal theory debate.

  19. Street (2008) takes Korsgaard to task on this point, arguing that it is implausible to regard this as a practical problem. However, Street in her recent work suggests that metaethics may be therapeutic, helping us to deal with “the problem of attachment and loss” (Street 2016), and so it seems that she is receptive to the thought that moral theory could be evaluated in terms of serving a practical purpose.

  20. For a helpful discussion of this view, which is often referred to as “motivational judgment internalism”, see Rosati (2016). For a prominent defense of the view, see Smith (1994). Of course, there are related but distinct internalist views in the literature, but the broad outlines will suffice for my purposes here.

  21. It may be the case that the only concepts of gender and race that are fruitful in the resilience sense, of course, will also have to be fruitful in other respects—motivating various kinds of feminist, antiracist actions, preventing sexist and racist actions, and so on. As with other concepts, an exploration of the resilience-based fruitfulness of gender and race may lead to questions concerning the other types of fruitfulness that I have described.

  22. For a helpful overview, see Knobe (2010).

  23. For early conversations on the topics addressed in this paper, I am grateful to Serene Khader, Josh Knobe, Tori McGeer, and Michael Strevens. For helpful discussions of earlier versions of the paper and the points raised in it, I would like to thank Christian Barry, Geoff Brennan, Ramon Das, Ben Fraser, Ana Gantman, Simon Keller, Eric Mandelbaum, Philip Pettit, Luke Russell, Nic Southwood, Katie Steele, Kim Sterelny, Justin Sytsma, John Thrasher, Joe Ulatowski, Dan Weijers, and audiences at the First Annual Australasian Experimental Philosophy Workshop at Victoria University of Wellington, the Fifth Australasian Workshop in Moral Philosophy at the Kioloa Coastal Campus of the Australian National University, the Experimental Methods in Social and Political Philosophy Workshop at ANU, and the ANU School of Philosophy Seminar. For helpful written comments, I am grateful to Justin Bruner, Toby Handfield, Frank Jackson, Serene Khader, Josh Knobe, Matt Kopec, Shaun Nichols, Peter Singer, Katja Vogt, and two anonymous reviewers for the journal.

References

  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2014). Accentuate the negative. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 31–50). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J., & Weinberg, J. M. (2007). Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass,2(1), 56–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amodio, D. M., Devine, P. G., & Harman, E. (2008). Individual differences in the regulation of intergroup bias: the role of conflict monitoring and neural signals for control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,94, 60–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2010). The imperative of integration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1999). Nicomachean ethics (T. Irwin, Ed.) (2nd ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co.

  • Barrett, L. F., Gollwitzer, P. M., Lee-Chai, A., Barndollar, K., & Trötschel, R. (2001). Individual differences in working memory capacity and dual-process theories of mind. Psychological Bulletin,130, 553–575.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, M., Nettle, D., & Roberts, G. (2006). Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biology Letters,2(3), 412–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson, C. D. (2008). Moral masquerades: experimental exploration of the nature of moral motivation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,7(1), 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonilla-Silva, E. (2003). Racism without racists: color-blind racism and the persistence of racial inequality in America. Lanham, MA: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boxill, B. R. (1992). Blacks and social justice (Rev ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (2018). Decisions behind the veil: an experimental approach. In T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J., & Lindauer, M. (2018). The varieties of impartiality, or, would an egalitarian endorse the veil? Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1190-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bryan, C. J., Adams, G. S., & Monin, B. (2012). When cheating would make you a cheater: implicating the self prevents unethical behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,142(4), 1001–1005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryan, C. J., Walton, G. M., Rogers, T., & Dweck, C. S. (2011). Motivating voter turnout by invoking the self. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,108(31), 12653–12656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckland, L., Lindauer, M., Rodríguez-Arías, D., & Véliz, C. Testing the motivational strength of positive and negative duty arguments regarding global poverty (unpublished manuscript).

  • Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy without intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1955). Meaning and synonymy in natural languages. Philosophical Studies,6(3), 33–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correll, J., Park, B., Judd, C. M., & Wittenbrink, B. (2002). The police officer’s Dilemma: Using ethnicity to disambiguate potentially threatening individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,83(6), 1314–1329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value: A dual-system framework for morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review,17(3), 273–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernest-Jones, M., Nettle, D., & Bateson, M. (2011). Effects of eye images on everyday cooperative behavior: A field experiment. Evolution and Human Behavior,32(3), 172–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Essien, I., Stelter, M., Kalbe, F., Koehler, A., Mangels, J., & Meliß, S. (2017). The shooter bias: Replicating the classic effect and introducing a novel paradigm. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,70, 41–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. (2014). Utopophobia. Philosophy & Public Affairs,42(2), 113–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2015). From gulf to bridge: When do moral arguments facilitate political influence? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,41, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, J. C. (2015). Pragmatic experimental philosophy. Philosophical Psychology,28(3), 412–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frohlich, N., Oppenheimer, J. A., & Eavey, C. L. (1987). Laboratory results on Rawls’s distributive justice. British Journal of Political Science,17(01), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner, R. (2007). Abolishing morality. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice,10(5), 499–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2010). The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Spassena, K., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,101(2), 366–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D. (2007). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, disease, and development (Vol. 3). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science,293(5537), 2105–2108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review,108(4), 814–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) Are they? (What) Do we want them to be? Noûs,34(1), 31–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassoun, N., Malikov, E., & Lubchenco, N. (2016). How people think about distributing aid. Philosophical Psychology,29(7), 1029–1044.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. M. (2001). Is globalization good for women? Comparative Literature,53(4), 298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. M. (2005). “Saving Amina”: Global justice for women and intercultural dialogue. Ethics & International Affairs,19(03), 55–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2012). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (M. J. Gregor & J. Timmermann, Eds.) (Revised Edition). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2009). Will the real moral judgment please stand up? The implications of social intuitionist models of cognition for meta-ethics and moral psychology. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice,12(1), 77–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khader, S. J. (2011). Adaptive preferences and women’s empowerment. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2014). The ethical project. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as moralist. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,33(04), 315–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2016). Experimental philosophy is cognitive science. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 37–52). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (2003). Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Moral Philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research,28(Supplement), 99–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith, H. (2012). The motivation question: Arguments from justice and from humanity. British Journal of Political Science,42(03), 661–678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, J. S., & Tetlock, P. E. (1999). Accounting for the effects of accountability. Psychological Bulletin,125(2), 255–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy Paluck, E., Shepherd, H., & Aronow, P. M. (2016). Changing climates on conflict: A social network experiment in 56 schools. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,113(3), 566–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenberg, J. (2010). Negative duties, positive duties, and the “new harms”. Ethics,120(3), 557–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenberg, J. (2014). Distant strangers: Ethics, psychology, and global poverty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lissowski, G., Tyszka, T., & Okrasa, W. (1991). Principles of distributive justice: Experiments in Poland and America. Journal of Conflict Resolution,35(1), 98–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, D. M., & Roman, J. S. (2002). Female role models: Protecting women’s math test performance. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,28(9), 1183–1193.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, R. B., Lord, C. G., Gresky, D. M., Ten Eyck, L. L., Frye, G. D. J., & Bond, C. F., Jr. (2005). A social impact trend in the effects of role models on alleviating women’s mathematics stereotype threat. Current Research in Social Psychology,10, 116–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, R. B., Paulson, R. M., & Lord, C. G. (2003). Alleviating women’s mathematics stereotype threat through salience of group achievements. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,39(1), 83–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. M. (2007). Universal moral grammar: Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in Cognitive Sciences,11(4), 143–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. M. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. W. (2005). “Ideal theory” as ideology. Hypatia,20(3), 165–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. W. (2011). The racial contract (Nachdr.). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2018). Minimal morality: A multilevel social contract theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Colyvan, M., Martini, C., Sillari, G., & Sprenger, J. (2014). Disagreement behind the veil. Philosophical Studies,170(3), 377–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T., & Nahmias, E. (2007). The past and future of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations,10(2), 123–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1992). Reasons and persons (Repr.). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Payne, B. K. (2005). Conceptualizing control in social cognition: How executive functioning modulates the expression of automatic stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,89(4), 488–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1999). Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2014). Just freedom: A moral compass for a complex world (1st ed.). New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinder, M. (2017). Does experimental philosophy have a role to play in Carnapian explication? X-phi and explication. Ratio,30, 443–461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. W. (2008). World poverty and human rights: Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice (rev. 1991). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1980). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. The Journal of Philosophy,77(9), 515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. S. (2016). Moral motivation. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Winter Edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-motivation. Accessed 7 Aug 2018.

  • Shepherd, J., & Justus, J. (2015). X-phi and Carnapian explication. Erkenntnis,80(2), 381–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics (7th ed.). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs,1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2005). Ethics and intuitions. The Journal of Ethics,9(3–4), 331–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skitka, L. J. (2010). The psychology of moral conviction. Social and Personality Psychology Compass,4(4), 267–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G. (2005). Moral conviction: Another contributor to attitude strength or something more? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,88(6), 895–917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1996). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2016). Evolution, norms and the social contract. Arizona State Law Journal,48, 1087–1100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P. (2007). “If I look at the mass I will never act”: Psychic numbing and genocide. Judgment and Decision Making,2(2), 79–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Small, D. A., Loewenstein, G., & Slovic, P. (2007). Sympathy and callousness: The impact of deliberative thought on donations to identifiable and statistical victims. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes,102, 143–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, N. (2016). Does “ought” imply “feasible”? Philosophy & Public Affairs,44(1), 7–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Constructivism about reasons. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 3, pp. 207–245). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2016). Constructivism in ethics and the problem of attachment and loss. Aristotelian Society Supplementary,90(1), 161–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (1990). Contractarianism and norms. Ethics,100(4), 768–786.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2016). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Peterborough, ON: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thrasher, J. (2012). Uniqueness and symmetry in bargaining theories of justice. Philosophical Studies,167(3), 683–699.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2012). Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map: Ideal vs. non-ideal theory. Philosophy Compass,7(9), 654–664.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohs, K., & Schooler, J. W. (2008). The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science,19(1), 49–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, M. U. (2007). Moral understandings: A feminist study in ethics (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M. (2007). How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy,31(1), 318–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicklund, R. A. (1979). The influence of self-awareness on human behavior: The person who becomes self-aware is more likely to act consistently, be faithful to societal norms, and give accurate reports about himself. American Scientist,67(2), 187–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2016). Philosophical criticisms of experimental philosophy. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 22–36). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • X-Phi’s New Take on Old Problems. (2010). The New York Times. https://www.nytimes.com/roomfordebate/2010/8/19/x-phis-new-take-on-old-problems. Accessed 7 Aug 2018.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Lindauer.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lindauer, M. Experimental philosophy and the fruitfulness of normative concepts. Philos Stud 177, 2129–2152 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01302-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01302-3

Keywords

Navigation