Skip to main content
Log in

What’s new in the new ideology critique?

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue that contemporary accounts of ideology critique—paradigmatically those advanced by Haslanger, Jaeggi, Celikates, and Stanley—are either inadequate or redundant. The Marxian concept of ideology—a collective epistemic distortion or irrationality that helps maintain bad social arrangements—has recently returned to the forefront of debates in contemporary analytic social philosophy. Ideology critique has similarly emerged as a technique for combating such social ills by remedying those collective epistemic distortions. Ideologies are sets of social meanings or shared understandings. I argue in this paper that because agents must coordinate on them to be mutually intelligible, ideologies, on the fashionable contemporary account, are conventions. They are equilibrium solutions to a particular kind of social coordination problem. The worry is that changing pernicious conventions requires more than the epistemic remedy contemporary critical social theorists prescribe. It also requires overcoming strategic impediments like high first-mover costs. Thus contemporary proponents of ideology critique—the “new ideology critics,” as I’ll call them—face a dilemma. Either their account of social change fails to account for important strategic impediments to social change, in which case it is inadequate, or it incorporates a theory of strategic behavior, and thus merely reinvents the wheel, poorly. It adds nothing to prominent convention-based accounts of social change in the social sciences. More generally, this is an example of a pernicious trend in contemporary critical social theory. Contemporary critical social theorists have abandoned their predecessors’ commitment to engaging with social science, thereby undermining their efforts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, in 2016 Yale held a conference on ideology, which has resulted in a forthcoming edited volume. Cf. Celikates et al. (2019).

  2. Lewis (1969) and Schelling (1960).

  3. Cf. Celikates et al. (2019), Celikates (2006), Gooding-Williams (2019), Haslanger (2012, 2017a, b, c), Jaeggi (2008, 2015), Mills (2007, 2013), Shelby (2002, 2003, 2014, 2016) and Stanley (2015).

  4. "Strategic" just means that the outcome of some action that someone might take depends on what actions other people take. The study of strategic behavior is called game theory. Most broadly Marxian social theory fails to account for strategic behavior; notable (and noble) exceptions include Elster (1985) and Sensat (1988).

  5. The better version of the wheel belongs to e.g. Bicchieri (1993, 2006, 2017), Bicchieri and Muldoon (2011), Binmore (2005), Brennan et al. (2013), Elster (1989), Kuran (1995), Mackie (1996, 2000, 2003), Muldoon (2016) and Young (1998).

  6. Cf. Haslanger (2017a, 8): "Ideology…is intended to function as an answer to the explanatory question: What explains persistent racial injustice?".

  7. This follows Geuss' (1981) taxonomy, on which theories of ideology can have epistemic, functional, and "genetic" or etiological dimensions. Cf. also Shelby (2003).

  8. Rosen (1996, Ch. 6).

  9. Horkheimer (1937); Haslanger has explicitly self-identified as a critical theorist. I explicitly lay out my targets in footnote 3 above.

  10. For our purposes, ideology is defined functionally. This is not the same thing as "functionalism" about ideology, according to which the functional role of an ideology causally explains its prevalence. Cf. Cohen (2001, Ch. IX, X), and Cohen (1982), the rejoinder to Cohen by Elster (1982). None of what I attribute to my interlocutors entails their being committed to a functionalist explanatory strategy; perhaps some of them are. For more on this debate cf. Heath (2015a)

  11. Though certainly not all of them; for perhaps the best existing account of ideology (as opposed to ideology critique) see Geuss (1981); for a useful survey of prominent definitions of ideology see Shelby (2003, 162–163).

  12. Boas and Gans-Morse (2009).

  13. Cf. Eagleton (2004): "As with bad breath, ideology is always what the other person has".

  14. Cf. Shelby (2003, 2014, 2016) and Haslanger (2017a, b).

  15. Cf. Gadamer (1960) and Taylor (1971/1985).

  16. Jaeggi (2008, 64).

  17. Haslanger (2017a, 16).

  18. The idea of a "perspective" from analytical political philosophy is also similar: viz., "Perspectives are simply the filters that we use to view the world….we…(consciously or unconsciously) choose to group certain features together, choose to ignore certain information while focusing on other information, and choose systems of representation and interpretation." (Muldoon 2016, 48–49) Cf. also Gaus (2017, 158–176); cf. also Bicchieri (2006, 93–94) on "schemata" and "scripts".

  19. Geuss (1981) distinguishes between ideology in the descriptive and the pejorative sense. The new ideology critics and I use the term in the pejorative sense; ideology in the purely descriptive sense is just constituted by feature 1. Geuss and Shelby use the term "form of consciousness" to denote ideology in the merely descriptive sense. Haslanger uses the term "cultural techne" for the same purpose, presumably to emphasize that inhabiting such a thing is a kind of learned practical skill.

  20. Cf. Muldoon (2017) for a clear statement of how this works.

  21. Cf. Honneth (2008), following Lukacs (1923).

  22. Jaeggi (2008, 65). Cf. also Shelby (2003, 176–177), Geuss (1981, 12–15), and McCarthy (1981, 2004).

  23. Wood (1972) is a lovely, clear account of how this works.

  24. Wood (1972, 257).

  25. Ibid. 256–257.

  26. Ibid. 255.

  27. Haslanger (2017b, 150).

  28. Haslanger (2017c, 11).

  29. Haslanger (2017a, b, c, 43–44). Capitalization in the original.

  30. Shelby (2014, 66).

  31. Cf. Department of Justice (2015, 2016, 2017).

  32. Jaeggi (2008); but cf. Boas and Gans-Morse (2009).

  33. Note that the new ideology critics embrace a somewhat broader application of ideology than their predecessors. Traditionally, ideology is a collective irrationality that's supposed to explain why people help reproduce their own oppression. Cf. Heath (2001, 163). The new ideology critics, however, don't seem to restrict themselves to cases of people acting against their own interests. Rather, they're concerned with oppression and domination more generally. Thanks to Allen Buchanan and an anonymous referee for making this clear to me.

  34. Cf. Heath (20002001); cf. also Mummolo (2018) for an empirical examination of the issue.

  35. Schelling (1960) and Lewis (1969).

  36. Cf. Goodman (1989, 80): The terms “convention” and “conventional” are flagrantly and intricately ambiguous. On the one hand, the conventional is the ordinary, the usual, the traditional, the orthodox as against the novel, the deviant, the unexpected, the heterodox. On the other hand, the conventional is the artificial, the invented, the optional, as against the natural, the fundamental, the mandatory.

  37. Technically, a pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Each player's best response, conditional on the strategies of all the other players, is to play the same strategy as each of the other players.

  38. There are lots of different equilibrium concepts and I'm trying to stay neutral among them, because it's not clear which one applies here.

  39. Cf. Davidson (1974) for a classic formulation of this point. Cf. also Gadamer (1960); and for a contemporary scientific take, Tomasello (2014, Ch. 4, 5).

  40. Haslanger (2017a, 13).

  41. Tomasello (2014, 85).

  42. Haslanger (2017c, 12).

  43. Schelling (1960, 91).

  44. Haslanger (2017c, 43–44). Capitalization in the original.

  45. Schelling (1960) and Mackie (1996, 1007).

  46. Ibid. 1007.

  47. This common way of understanding rational choice theory comes from e.g. Green and Shapiro (1994) and Satz and Frerejohn (1994). Cf. Lovett (2016, 238): "For the most part, people view [Rational Choice Theory] as a species of intentional explanation. Roughly, according to this view, the point of RCT is to explain social phenomena by showing how they arise from the deliberate or intentional pursuit of self-interest by social actors (and especially, individual persons)." Lovett (2016) is an extended, and to my mind, convincing argument against this position.

  48. Cf. Elster (1986).

  49. But cf. Heath (2001) for some skepticism about this.

  50. Celikates (2006, 33).

  51. Haslanger (2017a, 19).

  52. Haslanger (2017b, 169).

  53. Haslanger (2017c, 46–47).

  54. Mackie (1996, 1008).

  55. Ibid.

  56. Ibid. 1004.

  57. Ibid. 1004: "The most common explanation given by participants is that infibulation is required for marriage and honor".

  58. Cf. also Bicchieri (2017, 108–111).

  59. Mackie (1996, 1000, 1003).

  60. Kuran (1995, 78).

  61. Mackie (1996, 1011).

  62. Admittedly, Senegal is in West Africa; Mackie's original (1996) paper was about the practice in Sudan. But the convention story explains the Senegalese events. Cf. also Orubuloye et al. (2000).

  63. Mackie (1996, 1008): "As measured by a sociologist's data, for example, the population of Tinghsien, a conservative rural area 125 miles south of Peking, went from 99 percent bound in 1889 to 94 percent bound in 1899 to zero bound in 1919".

  64. Thanks to Allen Buchanan and an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out. Another example of this is the Schelling segregation model. Cf. Schelling (1969, 1971, 1978), Fossett and Dietrich (2009), and Muldoon et al. (2012).

  65. Mackie (2000, 257).

  66. Haslanger (2017c, 24).

  67. Haslanger (2017c, 25).

  68. Haslanger (2017b) and Celikates (2016).

  69. Feminist consciousness-raising groups might also be an example of this.

  70. A representative example is Haslanger (2017b, 169); this theme appears throughout the paper.

  71. This should not be taken as an endorsement of the "meta-ethical" claim that morality is conventional, though I think that's a stance I endorse; rather, by the phrase "moral convention" I mean a set of moral commitments accepted in general, and which have the formal structure of conventions.

  72. Bicchieri (2017, 121).

  73. Haslanger (2017a, 13, b, 155, 156, 157).

  74. Bicchieri (2017, 132).

  75. Ibid.

  76. Both good and bad ones, but let's concentrate on the pernicious ones.

  77. Bicchieri (2017, 133).

  78. Mackie (1996, 1004).

  79. Mackie (1996, 1009).

  80. Bicchieri (2017, 137).

  81. Mackie (1996, 1011–1012, 2000).

  82. Bicchieri (2017, 139).

  83. Ibid. 139–140.

  84. Haslanger (2017a, 10).

  85. Jay (1996, Ch. 7).

  86. Celikates (2017, 846). Italics in original.

  87. One notable and noble exception is Joseph Heath.

  88. Buchanan and Powell (2018, 147). There are a number of examples of social-scientific literature on topics of interest to the New Ideology Critics. Here is an incredibly abbreviated list of works on the causes of persistent racial inequality: cf. Fryer (2010), Hutt (1964), Loury (1994), and Rothstein (2017).

  89. Haslanger (2017b, 156).

  90. Cf. e.g. Tomasello (1999, 2014, 2016, 2019), Kahan et al. (2012, 2016) and Kahan (2016a, b).

  91. Cf. Brown (2008), Bowles and Gintis (2011), Boyd and Richerson (1985, 1992, 2004), Henrich et al. (2004, 2005), Henrich and Henrich (2007), Ensminger and Henrich (2014), Henrich (2000, 2016), Bicchieri (2006, 2017), Jones (2006) and Heath (2011).

  92. Kahan et al. (2012).

  93. Cf. Bolinger (2017, Section IV, and fn.19–31) for a discussion.

  94. Cf. Uslaner (2018) and Letki (2018).

  95. Cf. World Bank (2015); the 2015 World Development Report is about the role of social norms in economic development. Cf. also Buchanan and Powell (2017).

  96. Buchanan and Powell (2018, 316–325). Cf. also Kitcher (2014, 158–162).

  97. Buchanan and Powell (2018, 318).

  98. Ibid., 316.

  99. Heath (2015b); the term comes from Nozick (1974, 247): "Normative sociology, the study of what the causes of problems ought to be, greatly fascinates us all".

  100. Ibid.

  101. Stanley (2015).

  102. Brennan (2017).

References

  • Bicchieri, C. (1993). Rationality and coordination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C. (2017). Norms in the wild. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri, C., & Muldoon, R. (2011). Social norms. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/social-norms/. Accessed 2018.

  • Binmore, K. (2005). Natural justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boas, T. C., & Gans-Morse, J. (2009). Neoliberalism: From new liberal philosophy to anti-liberal slogan. Studies in Comparative International Development,44(2), 137–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, R. J. (2017). Reasonable mistakes and regulative norms: Racial bias in defensive harm. Journal of Political Philosophy,25(2), 196–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2011). A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and evolutionary process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1992). Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethology and Sociobiology,13, 171–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2004). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, J. (2017). Propaganda about propaganda. Critical Review,29(1), 34–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., Eriksson, L., Goodin, R. E., & Southwood, N. (2013). Explaining norms. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. J. (Ed.). (2008). Explaining culture scientifically. Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., & Powell, R. (2017). De-moralization as emancipation: Liberty, progress, and the evolution of invalid moral norms. Social Philosophy and Policy,34(2), 108–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., & Powell, R. (2018). The evolution of moral progress: A biocultural theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, R. (2006). From critical social theory to a social theory of critique: On the critique of ideology after the pragmatic turn. Constellations,13(1), 21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, R. (2016). Rethinking civil disobedience as a practice of contestation: Beyond the liberal paradigm. Constellations,23(1), 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, R. (2017). Critique and resistance: Ethical, social-theoretical, political? On Fabian Freyenhagen’s Adorno’s practical philosophy. European Journal of Philosophy,25(3), 846–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, R., Haslanger, S., & Stanley, J. (Eds.). (2019). Analyzing ideology: Rethinking the concept. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (1982). Reply to Elster on ‘Marxism, functionalism, and game theory’. Theory and Society,11(4), 483–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2001). Karl Marx’s theory of history: A defence, expanded edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Constantine, G., & Sensat, J. O. (1975). A critique of the foundations of utility theory. Science and Society,39(2), 157–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association,47, 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Department of Justice. (2015). Investigation of the Ferguson Police Department. https://www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_department_report.pdf. Accessed 2018.

  • Department of Justice. (2016). Investigation of the Baltimore City Police Department. https://www.justice.gov/crt/file/883296/download. Accessed 2018.

  • Department of Justice. (2017). Investigation of the Chicago Police Department. https://www.justice.gov/opa/file/925846/download. Accessed 2018.

  • Eagleton, T. (2004). Why ideas no longer matter. The Guardian. https://www.theguardian.com/books/2004/mar/23/immigrationpolicy.politics. Accessed 2018.

  • Elster, J. (1982). The case for methodological individualism: Marxism, functionalism, and game theory. Theory and Society,11(4), 453–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1985). Making sense of Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1986). Replies to critics. Inquiry,29(1–4), 65–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1989). The cement of society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ensminger, J., & Henrich, J. (Eds.). (2014). Experimenting with social norms: Fairness and punishment in cross-cultural perspective. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fossett, M., & Dietrich, D. (2009). Effects of city size, shape, and form, and neighborhood size and shape in agent-based models of residential segregation. Environment and Planning B,36(1), 149–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fryer, R. (2010). Racial inequality in the 21st century: The declining significance of discrimination. In O. Ashenfelter & D. Card (Eds.), Handbook of labor economics (Vol. 4, pp. 855–972). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (1960). Truth and method. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2017). The tyranny of the ideal. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geuss, R. (1981). The idea of a critical theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooding-Williams, R. (2019). Ideology, social practices, and anti-black concepts. In Celikates, Haslanger, and Stanley (eds.) forthcoming.

  • Goodman, N. (1989). Just the facts, Ma’am! In M. Krausz (Ed.), Relativism: Interpretation and confrontation, south bend. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, D., & Shapiro, I. (1994). Pathologies of rational choice theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2017a). Racism, ideology, and social movements. Res Philosophica,94(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2017b). Culture and critique. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary,91, 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2017c). Critical theory and practice (Amsterdam Spinoza Lectures). Amsterdam: Koninklijke van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2000). Ideology, irrationality and collectively self-defeating behaviour. Constellations,7(3), 363–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2001). Problems in the theory of ideology. In J. Bohman & W. Rehg (Eds.), Pragmatism and critical theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2011). Following the rules: Practical reasoning and deontic constraint. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. (2015a). Methodological individualism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/methodological-individualism/. Accessed 2018.

  • Heath, J. (2015b). On the problem of normative sociology. In Due Course Blog. http://induecourse.ca/on-the-problem-of-normative-sociology/. Accessed 2018.

  • Henrich, J. (2000). Does culture matter in economic behavior? Ultimatum game bargaining among the Machiguenga. American Economic Review,90(4), 973–979.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J. (2016). The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Gintis, H., et al. (2005). “Economic man” in cross-cultural perspective: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,28(6), 795–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Gintis, H., Camerer, C., & Fehr, E. (Eds.). (2004). Foundations of human sociality: Ethnography and experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, N., & Henrich, J. (2007). Why humans cooperate. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, A. (2008). Reification: A new look at an old idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, M. (1937). Traditionelle und kritische Theorie. Zeitschrift fur Sozialforschung,6(2), 245–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutt, W. H. (1964). The economics of the colour bar. London: Merritt & Hatcher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeggi, R. (2008). Rethinking ideology. In B. de Bruin & C. F. Zurn (Eds.), New waves in political philosophy (pp. 63–86). Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeggi, R. (2015). Towards an immanent critique of forms of life. Raisons Politiques,57(1), 13–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jay, M. (1996). The dialectical imagination: A history of the Frankfurt School and the Institute for Social Research 1923–1950. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, E. L. (2006). Cultures merging. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M. (2016a). The politically motivated reasoning paradigm, part 1: What politically motivated reasoning is and how to measure it. Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118900772.etrds0417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M. (2016b). The politically motivated reasoning paradigm, part 2: Unanswered questions. Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118900772.etrds0418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M., Hoffman, D., Braman, D., Evans, D., & Rachlinski, J. (2012). “They saw a protest”: Cognitive illiberalism and the speech-conduct distinction. Stanford Law Review,64(4), 851–906.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M., Hoffman, D., Evans, D., Devins, N., Lucci, E., & Cheng, K. (2016). “Ideology” or “situation sense”? and experimental investigation of professional judgment and motivated reasoning. University of Pennsylvania Law Review,164(1), 349–439.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2014). The ethical project. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuran, T. (1995). Private truths, public lies: The social consequences of preference falsification. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Letki, N. (2018) Trust in newly democratic regimes. In Uslaner, E. M. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Social and Political Trust (pp. 336–356). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loury, G. (1994). Self-censorship in public discourse: A theory of ‘political correctness’ and related phenomena. Rationality and Society,6(4), 428–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovett, F. (2016). Rational choice theory and explanation. Rationality and Society, 18(2), 237–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lukacs, G. (1923). History and class consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (1996). Ending footbinding and infibulation: A convention account. American Sociological Review,61(6), 999–1017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (2000). Female genital cutting: The beginning of the end. In B. Sheil-Duncan & Y. Hernlund (Eds.), Female “circumcision” in Africa: Culture, controversy, and change (pp. 245–282). Boulder, CO: Lynne Reinner Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (2003). Female genital cutting: A harmless practice? Medical Anthropology Quarterly,17(2), 135–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. (1981). The critical theory of Jurgen Habermas. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. (2004). Political philosophy and racial justice: From normative to critical theory. In S. Benhabib & N. Fraser (Eds.), Pragmatism, critique, judgment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. (2007). White ignorance. In S. Sullivan & N. Tuana (Eds.), Race and epistemologies of ignorance. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. (2013). White ignorance and hermeneutical injustice: A comment on Medina and Fricker. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective,3(1), 38–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R. (2016). Social contract theory for a diverse world: Beyond tolerance. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R. (2017). Exploring tradeoffs in accommodating moral diversity. Philosophical Studies,174(7), 1871–1883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., Smith, T., & Weisberg, M. (2012). Segregation that no one seeks. Philosophy of Science,79(1), 38–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mummolo, J. (2018). Modern police tactics, police-citizen interactions, and the prospects for reform. The Journal of Politics, 80(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orubuloye, I. O., Caldwell, P., & Caldwell, J. C. (2000). Female “circumcision” among the Yoruba of Southwestern Nigeria: The beginning of change. In B. Sheil-Duncan & Y. Hernlund (Eds.), Female “circumcision” in Africa: Culture, controversy, and change (pp. 73–94). Boulder, CO: Lynne Reinner Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. (1996). On voluntary servitude. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, R. (2017). The color of law: A forgotten history of how our government segregated America. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Satz, D., & Frerejohn, R. (1994). Rational choice and social theory. Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 71–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1969). Models of segregation. American Economic Review,59(2), 488–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology,1, 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sensat, J. O. (1988). Methodological individualism and marxism. Economics and Philosophy,4(2), 189–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, T. (2002). Is racism in the ‘heart’? Journal of Social Philosophy,33, 411–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, T. (2003). Ideology, racism, and critical social theory. The Philosophical Forum,34(2), 153–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, T. (2014). Racism, moralism, and social criticism. Du Bois Review,11(1), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, T. (2016). Dark ghettos: Injustice, dissent, and reform. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2015). How propaganda works. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1971/1985). Interpretation and the sciences of man. In Philosophical papers, Vol. 2: Philosophy and the human sciences (pp. 15–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2016). A natural history of human morality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2019). Becoming human: A theory of ontogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uslaner, E. M. (Ed.). (2018). The Oxford handbook of social and political trust. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (1972). The Marxian critique of justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs,1(3), 244–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Bank. (2015). World Development Report 2015. http://www.worldbank.org/content/dam/Worldbank/Publications/WDR/WDR%202015/WDR-2015-Full-Report.pdf. Accessed 2018.

  • Young, H. P. (1998). Individual strategy and social structure: An evolutionary theory of institutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks especially to Matthew Adams, Jake Monaghan, and Daniel Muñoz, all of whom read multiple drafts of this paper. Thanks also to Jonny Anomaly, Jacob Barrett, Allen Buchanan, Cesar Cabezas, Gianna Englert, Dave Estlund (who suggested the title), Arianna Falbo, Jeff Feldman, Jerry Gaus, Nick Geiser, Adam Gjesdal, Charles Larmore, Rachel Leadon, Ferris Lupino, Chad Marxen, Sam Meister, Thomas Moore, Alex Motchoulski, Julian Mueller, Ryan Muldoon, Adam Pautz, Phil Smolenski, Valerie Soon, Bobby Wallace, Taylor White, various anonymous referees, and audiences at the 2016 Princeton Workshop in Social Philosophy, 2017 Politics, Philosophy, and Economics Society, New England Political Science Association meeting, and North American Society for Social Philosophy meetings, ECAP IX, and the Brown Graduate Political Philosophy Workshop for comments, feedback, and helpful discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kirun Sankaran.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sankaran, K. What’s new in the new ideology critique?. Philos Stud 177, 1441–1462 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01261-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01261-9

Keywords

Navigation