The T-schema and its semantic derivation
So how can unqualified truth (truth simpliciter) enter the picture? This is an issue just as pressing for the supervaluationist as the epistemicist. It is worth keeping in mind that when a language contains expressions with context dependent semantics values, the truth value of sentences can also vary with context, and so the extension of the non-relational truth-predicate is context dependent. On positing that \(x^2 = 4\), \(\text{`}x=3\text{'}\) is false. On positing that \(x = 4-1\), \(\text{`}x=3\text{'}\) is true. This much is common ground for the supervaluationist and the epistemicist.
The obvious place to start when characterising truth is the T-schema; the account of unqualified truth should be such that it commands acceptance in all contexts of every instance of the sentence-schema:
(T-schema) ‘#’ is true if and only if #.
Is there some reason why the supervaluationist in particular (as opposed to the epistemicist) should not abide by the T-schema? I think the answer is no.Footnote 12
Given the T-schema (and an underlying classical logic) we get bivalence (‘\(x=2\)’ is not true if and only if ‘\(x\ne 2\)’ is true) and a truth-functional analysis of disjunctions: ‘\(x=2\) or \(x = -2\)’ is true iff ‘\(x=2\)’ is true or ‘\(x = -2\)’ is true. The supervaluationist abiding by the T-schema would not need to be revisionist on these matters.
The idea, of course, is not new. Fine, in his Vagueness, Truth and Logic (1975), proposes a supervaluationist analysis of vague sentences and considers using a distinct notion of truth, ‘true\(_T\)’ in such a way as to satisfy the T-schema. The result, in Fine’s words, is that “The vagueness of ‘true\(_T\)’ waxes and wanes, as it were, with the vagueness of the given sentence” (p. 298); in the present context one could rephrase this as: the indeterminacy of truth waxes and wanes...with the indeterminacy of the given sentence. Fine, however, does not wish to equate ‘true\(_T\)’ with ‘true’ (simpliciter), as it would violate the requirement that “the meta-language not be vague or, at least, not so vague in its proper part as the object-language”. McGee and McLaughlin (1994), in articulating their ‘radical’ supervaluationism, reject this line of reasoning:
‘True’ is likewise vague. Because “‘Harry is bald’ is true if and only if Harry is bald” is definitely true—it is, on to the disquotational conception of truth, analytic—“‘Harry is bald’ is true” will be definitely true, definitely false, or unsettled according as ‘Harry is bald’ is definitely true, definitely false, or unsettled. ‘True’ inherits the vagueness of other vague terms, like ‘bald’. (p. 228)
The latter approach will be adopted here. But can the supervaluationist make sense of a notion of truth governed by the T-schema? I take this question to mean: can one devise a supervaluationist theory of a fragment of our language in such a way that the T-schema is entailed by the theory? The worry here is that somehow the semantic framework adopted by the supervaluationist would make it impossible to also adopt the T-schema. One could, of course, have a similar worry for the epistemicist. So let us explore whether the semantic framework itself could deliver the T-schema, on an appropriate interpretation of the truth-predicate.
We are going to build a new ‘object-meta-language’ on top of our original object language. To this effect we add to our original object language a term ‘\(\phi\)’ for each sentence \(\phi\) in the object language. In addition we add one variable, A, that is allowed to vary over object language sentences. In addition we add the truth- and falsity-predicates ‘is true’ and ‘is false’ and syntactically restrict these predicates so that sentences of the form ‘\(\alpha\) is true’ are well-formed only when \(\alpha\) is a term that is allowed to denote a sentence. Thus “‘\(x=2\)’ is true” and ‘A is true’ will now be sentences of our extended object language (the object-meta-language), but “‘A is true’ is false” will not be a sentence of our new object-meta-language.
Semantically we add a new domain \(D_M\) alongside the original domain D. \(D_M\) contains all the linguistic expressions of the object language. The original interpretation function I remains unchanged as far as object-language constructions are concerned (so only employs the original domain). The new terms of the form ‘\(\phi\)’ are given a homophonic interpretation so \(I(\text{`}\phi \text{'}) = \phi\). Assignment functions as before assign values to the variables of the object language, but now also assign a value to the sentence variable \(\text{`}A\text{'}\). So in our new model the interpretation function I and an assignment function g will have to assign values to a portion of the language that is not in the original object language. Let \(I^o\) and \(g^o\) denote the restriction of I and g, respectively, to the original object language.
The extension of the truth and falsity predicates is given by the following:
$$\begin{aligned} I_g({\text{`is true'}})&= \{\phi : \phi {\text{ is true relative to }}g^o\}.\\ I_g({\text{`is false'}})&= \{\phi : \phi \,{\text{ is false relative to }}g^o\}. \end{aligned}$$
That is, the extension of the predicate ‘is true’ assigned by \(I_g\) will be the set of object language sentences that are true relative to \(g^o\).
Note that the extensions of the truth- and falsity-predicates come to depend on the assignment g. So, whereas predicates in the object language proper are given a fixed interpretation (by the non-contextual assignment I), the extensions of the truth- and falsity-predicates are allowed to vary. This respects the fact that their extensions are context dependent.
The semantics yields the following truth-conditions (where \(\alpha\) is a name of a sentence):
$$\begin{aligned}&{\text{`}}\alpha {\text{ \,is \,true' \,is \, true \, relative \, to }}\, g \, {\text{ iff }} \, I_g({\alpha }) \, {\text{ is \, true\, relative \, to \, }}g. \end{aligned}$$
$$\begin{aligned}&{\text{`}}\alpha \,{\text{ is false' is true relative to }} g \text{ iff }\, I_g(\alpha ) \, {\text{ is not true relative to }} g. \end{aligned}$$
Our enriched object language and its accompanying semantics constitutes a theory of how we are to assign relational truth values to English sentences like “‘\(x=2\)’ is true”. In adopting a particular theory this will regulate how we use such sentences beyond cases that might not be dictated by the pre-theoretical intuitions we wish to respect. It will regulate usage in the same way that assignment relative truth conditions regulate usage of sentences like ‘\(x=2\)’.
Let us now derive an instance of the T-schema. Note that “‘\(x=2\)’ is true” is true relative to g iff ‘\(x=2\)’ is true relative to g. So:
“‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if
\(x=2\)” is true in every admissible assignment.
That is:
“‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if
\(x=2\)” is determinately true.
From (DT) we have:
If “‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if
\(x=2\)” is determinately true, then “‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if
\(x=2\)” is true.
So:
“‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if
\(x=2\)” is true.
When a sentence has been proven true one is in a position to assert it, which is what I now do:
‘\(x=2\)’ is true if and only if \(x=2\).
This is an instance of the T-schema. Every other relevant (object language) instance of the T-schema can be derived in a similar way.
One can thus see that on this theory of the meaning of our (unqualified) truth-predicate (‘A is true’ is true relative to g iff A is true relative to g), supervaluationism dictates that one should accept every instance of the T-schema that falls under the object-language.
The R-schema and its semantic derivation
Consider the R-schema for reference. It states that every instance of the following schema is properly assertable (where # is to be replaced by a singular term):
R-schema ‘#’ refers to #.
Or, equivalently:
R-schema The value of ‘#’ = #.
Just like the T-schema it provides an implicit definition of ‘refers to’ or ‘the value of’. And just like the T-schema it provides a reasonable starting point for our discussion about how to speak of the value that has been assigned to free variables.
Now, there are cases where one might want to deny an instance of the R-schema, for instance, one might want to deny that ‘Superman’ refers to Superman, on the basis that ‘Superman’ fails to refer. Is there, however, some reason why the supervaluationist in particular should deny some instance of the R-schema when the term is a free variable subject to proper posits like the posit that \(x^2=4\), where we know that there exists a number fitting the description? I think not. I think the supervaluationist should accept the R-schema and so (in the context in which it has been assumed that \(x^2=4\)) reject any suggestion to the effect that the variable x has no value, or that it has many values or that it is meaningless to ask for the value of x. The variable x refers to exactly one number, it has exactly one value, but its value is indeterminate. Let us see where this leads.
One instance of the R-schema is:
The value of \(\text{`}x\text{'} = x\).
So, the supervaluationist and epistemicist alike can always reply—if anyone asks for the value of the variable x in a given context—that the variable x has the value x. This is a strange answer, I admit, but its strangeness can be explained by the fact that it is a completely uninformative and so uncooperative: it doesn’t mean that the answer is false or lacks truth value. Indeed the following would be an equally uncooperative answer:
\(\quad \quad \quad \quad \quad \quad \quad x = x\),
yet no one denies, given proper posits, that \(x=x\). Of course, in many cases we can say something more informative. Given that \(x^2 = 4\), we know that either \(x=2\) or \(x=-2\) so we can, given the R-schema and the transitivity of identity, derive the meta-language claim:
Either the value of ‘x’ = 2 or the value of ‘x’ = \(-2\).
This is as informative a reply as we can offer yet neither more nor less informative than the claim that either \(x=2\) or \(x=-2\). No new more specific solution to the equation \(x^2=4\) will show up just because we use semantic vocabulary in the meta-language, but at least we can specify the possible values of x.
One can make supervaluationist sense of the R-schema. Our object-meta-language already contains terms that denote object-language terms (so the object-meta-language term ‘x’ denotes the variable x). Now introduce the function-name ‘The value of’ into our object-meta-language. It is restricted syntactically only to take terms denoting object-language terms as arguments and will yield a term in the extended object-meta-language. Thus, for instance, “The value of ‘x”’ will be a term in our extended object-meta-language and its semantic value will be an object in our original object-language domain.
We expand the meta-domain \(D_M\) so as to contain every possible assignment function on the original domain (we keep in place the restriction that no term or predicate of the object language can denote an element of the meta-domain, so the quantifiers—defined on object-language variables—will only range over the object domain).
The expression ‘The value of’ is syntactically a functional term. However, it is also context sensitive. So as opposed to the functions of the object language, it cannot be interpreted by the fixed interpretation function I. Instead we let:
$$\begin{aligned} I_g({\text{`The value of'}}) = g^o. \end{aligned}$$
This entails:
$$\begin{aligned}&I_g(\text{`}{\text{The value of }}\,{\mathbf {\alpha }}{\text{'}}) = g({\text{`The value of'}})(I_g(\alpha )) = g^o(I_g(\alpha )). \end{aligned}$$
Given this one can derive every object language instance of the R-schema. For it follows that:
“The value of ‘x’ = x” is determinately true.
Combining this with (DT) we get
“The value of ‘x’ = x” is true.
So “The value of ‘x’ = x” is properly assertable, and so:
This vindicates that the R-schema is accessible to both the supervaluationist and epistemicist. There is no need for the supervaluationist to hold that ‘x’ lacks reference or has no value, or has many values in a context where there are multiple admissible assignments of value to x. What the supervaluationist should say is that ‘x’ lacks determinate reference, that it has no determinate value only many different possible values. In this way the supervaluationist will differ from the epistemicist who claims that ‘x’ has a determinate value, only it cannot be known. When talking about the non-modalised value of ‘x’ they can both agree that the value of ‘x’ is x, and in a context where it has been assumed that \(x^2= 4\), they can both agree that either the value of ‘x’ is 2 or it is \(-2\).
Truth-tracking assignments
So, in a radical supervaluational mode of analysis one can ‘make sense’ of ordinary unqualified truth and reference, and of the idea that unqualified truth and reference may be indeterminate. A worry one might have, however, is that these notions, as analysed, are left dangling, quite free from any connection to the semantic notions of the supervaluational framework (truth and reference relative to an assignment g). Why take our ordinary semantic concepts and their potential indeterminacy to be at all important if they do not connect to the semantic theory of our choice?
A further worry is about the concepts of truth and reference in a context of use u. As a semanticist one is concerned not only with truth and reference in this (one’s own) context of use, one is concerned with all contexts of use. Accordingly, truth and reference in a context of use u are the target concepts of the supervaluational analysis: by means of the formal/technical notions of truth and reference relative to an assignment g one strives to analyse truth and reference in a context of use, with the idea that a context of use constrains but doesn’t uniquely determine the relevant assignment g. All we got from the supervaluational analysis, however, was an analysis of the concepts of determinate truth and reference in a context of use. What about their non-modal counterparts? Where do they enter the analysis, what is their relationship to the technical concepts of truth and reference relative to an assignment g?
Let us tackle the first problem first. In a given context an assignment g is truth-tracking iff for every A:
A is true relative to g iff A is true.
In general there can in any given context be several truth-tracking assignments—if there are any at all; this holds in virtue of the fact that when the domain is uncountable we can have two distinct assignments g and \(g'\) such that for every A: A is true relative to g iff A is true relative to \(g'\). However, if the domain is countable (e.g. the set of whole numbers) and every element of the domain is picked out by some constant in the language (e.g. the numerals) then there is only one truth-tracking assignment—if there is any truth-tracking assignment at all. To simplify the discussion let me assume then that the domain is countable and that every element of the domain is picked out by some constant, guaranteeing uniqueness of truth-tracking assignments.
The potentially problematic part is existence: will there in every context exist a truth-tracking assignment? The epistemicist will of course answer ‘yes’: as there in any proper context exists precisely one assignment that picks out the referent of each variable, that assignment is truth-tracking; as there can only be one truth-tracking assignment, that one assignment is the truth-tracking assignment. I claim that the supervaluationist can also answer ‘yes’: there is always a truth-tracking assignment, the truth-tracking assignment, giving us, for every object language sentence A:
A is true iff A is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment.
At first blush it might seem surprising that the supervaluationist can make claim to refer to the truth-tracking assignment in a context where there are many admissible assignments: any two different admissible assignments will make different sentences true, and so at most one can be truth-tracking. So which one is the truth-tracking assignment? The answer is that this is indeterminate. Of any admissible assignment we can say that it is possible that it is the truth-tracking assignment; of no admissible assignment can we say that it is definitely not the truth-tracking assignment. The property of being an admissible assignment will in every context have a determinate extension, but the property of being a truth-tracking assignment—like the property of being true—will have an indeterminate extension. Thus we can add ‘the truth-tracking assignment’ to the list of meta-language semantic singular terms and definite descriptions (a list already containing “the truth value of ‘\(x=2\)”’ and “The value of ‘x”’) that have, or can have, indeterminate reference. The truth-tracking assignment is an admissible assignment, but it is indeterminate which one.
To see that this makes supervaluationist sense we again need to subject this part of our language to formal scrutiny by putting it into our object-meta-language. Our meta-domain \(D_M\) already contains assignment functions. To our object-meta-language we need to add singular terms that are allowed to refer to assignment functions. In particular we add the context sensitive definite description ‘the truth-tracking assignment’, interpreted by:
$$\begin{aligned}&I_g(\text{`}{\text{the truth-tracking assignment'}}) = g^o. \end{aligned}$$
In order to make way for the equivalence between unqualified truth and truth relative to the truth-tracking assignment we also add an assignment relative truth-predicate ‘\(\alpha\) is true relative to \(\beta\)’ to the language syntactically restricted so that \(\alpha\) is a term allowed to denote an object language sentence and \(\beta\) is a term denoting assignments (in this fragment we only have one such term: ‘the truth-tracking assignment’).
Assignment-relative truth is not context sensitive, so its extension [a set of pairs (sentence, assignment)] can be given by the fixed interpretation function I:
$$\begin{aligned} I({\text{`is true relative to'}}) = \{(\phi , g) :&\,\phi \,{\text{ is an object language sentence and}}\\&\,g \,{\text{ is an object language assignment such that}}\\&\,\phi \,{\text{ is true at }} g\}. \end{aligned}$$
It follows that (where \(\alpha\) is a term denoting the name of a sentence and \(\beta\) is a term denoting the name of an assignment):
$$\begin{aligned} \text{`}\alpha \,{\text{ is true relative to }}\beta \,{\text{'}} \, \text{ is true relative to } g {\text{ iff }} g(\alpha ) {\text{ is true relative to }} g(\beta ). \end{aligned}$$
[Note that \(g(\beta )\) will denote an assignment that only assigns values to object language variables, it wont be an assignment that assigns a value to \(\beta\); as \(g(\alpha )\) denotes an object language sentence containing only object language variables, this restriction is harmless.] We are now in a position to derive the equivalence stated at the outset of this section.
Recall that in our object-meta language we allowed one free variable that was allowed to take sentences as values: the free variable ‘A’. So take some assignment g. From the truth conditions given to unqualified truth we have:
$$\begin{aligned} \text{`}A \,{\text{is true' is true relative to }} g {\text{ if and only if }} g(\text{`} A\text{'}) {\text{ is true relative to }}g. \end{aligned}$$
As \(g(\text{`}A\text{'})\) denotes an object language sentence the truth value of this sentence will depend only on the assignments to object-language variables, and so it follows that:
$$`\begin{aligned} \text{`}A \, {\text{is true' is true relative to }} g {\text{ if and only' if }} g(\text{`} A\text{'}) \, {\text{ is true relative to }} g^o. \end{aligned}$$
(4)
Likewise, from the truth conditions we have:
$$\begin{aligned}&\text{`}A \, {\text{is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment' is true relative to }}\, g \, {\text{if and only if }}\\&\quad \quad g(\text{`} A\text{'}) \, {\text{is true relative to }} g({\text{`the truth-tracking assignment'}}). \end{aligned}$$
As \(g({\text{`the truth-tracking assignment'}}) = g^o\) we have:
$$\begin{aligned}&\text{`}A \,{\text{is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment' is true relative to }} g \, {\text{if and only if }}\\&\quad \quad \, g({\text{`}A\text{'}}) \, {\text{is true relative to }} g^o. \end{aligned}$$
Combining this last step with (4) we have:
$$\begin{aligned}&{\text{`}}A \, {\text{is true' is true relative to }}\, g \, {\text{if and only if }}\\&\quad \quad {\text{`}}A \, {\text{ is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment' is true relative to }} g. \end{aligned}$$
So:
‘A is true if and only if
A is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment’ is true relative to g.
This holds for arbitrary g, so:
‘A is true if and only if
A is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment’ is determinately true.
Throughout it has been assumed that A is an object language sentence. So, assuming only that A is an object language sentence:
A is true if and only if A is true relative to the truth-tracking assignment.
So we have an explicit characterisation of the extension of unqualified truth in terms of assignment-relative truth. But we do not have a reductive analysis of truth simpliciter in terms of truth relative to an assignment; the reference of the singular term ‘the truth-tracking assignment’ is, after all, fixed by appeal to (and waxes and wanes with the indeterminacy of) what is true. We cannot get further. If it were possible to define truth simpliciter by means of properties with a determinate extension and terms with a determinate reference, the result would be a property with a determinate extension. What we can conclude, however, is that there is some admissible assignment g such that the predicate ‘true’ has the same extension as ‘true relative to the assignment g’, we just can’t say which assignment that has this property as this is indeterminate. (The epistemicist is in no better position; for the epistemicist will have to acknowledge that it is in principle impossible to state—in a non-question begging manner—which of the admissible assignments that is the truth-tracking assignment.)
A similar story (I will spare the reader the details) establishes the following identity:
(The value of the variable ‘x’) = (the value of the variable ‘x’ relative to the truth tracking assignment).
This does not amount to a reductive analysis of unqualified talk of reference to talk of reference relative to an assignment—again: no such analysis is in the offing—but it does show how the two are related.
So, turn to the concepts of truth and reference in a context of use u (where, I am assuming, u denotes some possible situation that determines some non-empty set of admissible assignments). Just as with their cousins the non-modal, non-relational concepts of truth and reference simpliciter, we can’t hope for a reductive analysis. However, as opposed to their non-modal, non-relational counterparts we can’t even turn to the T-schema or R-schema in order to characterise their extension. Still, I claim (again sparing the reader the now onerous details), we can make sense of the definite description ‘the truth tracking assignment in u’, that is, the description denoting the assignment g such that:
A is true in u iff A is true relative to g.
So placing the predicates ‘true in the context of use u’ and ‘true relative to the truth tracking assignment in u’, and the functionals “The value of ‘x’ in u” and “The value of ‘x’ relative to the truth tracking assignment in u” in the meta-object language, one can show that it is possible to make supervaluational sense of these expressions in such a way as to guarantee that the following holds:
-
1.
A is true in u iff A is true relative to the truth tracking assignment in u.
-
2.
(The value of ‘x’ in u) = (the value of ‘x’ relative to the truth tracking assignment in u).
What this shows is that there is some assignment g (the truth tracking assignment in u) such that A is true in u iff A is true relative to g. Such an existence claim cannot be cashed out in terms of a description that determinately refers to an assignment, as it is indeterminate which one of the in u admissible assignments that tracks truth in u. Again, this does not amount to a supervaluational reductive analysis of truth and reference in a context of use, but it does show that the predicate ‘true in u’ is conceptually distinct from (and need not have the same extension as) the predicate ‘determinately true in u’.
‘Determinately’ in the object language?
Having studied what happens when the semantic vocabulary is put in the object language, a natural question becomes: what happens when we add the ‘Determinately’ operator to the object language, giving us sentences of the form ‘Determinately A’, or ‘Det A’ for short. Here one should proceed with considerable caution.
On the supervaluational analysis, a sentence is determinately true iff it is true relative to all assignments that make all the posits true. The problem is that in the course of an argument the sets of posits change. New posits can be added and old posits can be retracted. On letting x be such that \(x^2 = 4\), ‘Det (\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\))’ is true. On dropping this posit ‘Det (\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\))’ is false. This has nothing to do with the fact that determinately is a modality, we get the same phenomenon if we replace determinately true by its analysans. On letting x be such that \(x^2 = 4\), ‘\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\)’ is true relative to all assignments that make all the posits currently in force true. Now drop the assumption that \(x^2 = 4\). It is then no longer the case that ‘\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\)’ is true relative to all assignments that make all the posits currently in force true. I have added the phrase currently in force to make explicit what hitherto has been implicit: the posits that can be said to be currently in force changes over time, in the course of an argument what counts as a posit currently in force changes, accordingly what counts as determinately true changes.
The standard principles of logic, to the extent that they focus on syntactic form, are not designed to capture logical relations between expressions that can change their semantic value in ongoing discourse or reasoning. An assertion of ‘You [pointing to Bill] are guilty and you [pointing to Anne] are not guilty’ does not express an inconsistent proposition even though it has the syntactic form of a contradiction (‘You are guilty and you are not guilty’). In a similar way, logic is affected when the Det-operator is introduced. While Det (\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\)) follows on the assumption that \(x^2=4\), we cannot on the basis of this drop the assumption, apply the principle of conditional proof, and infer the material conditional:
$$\begin{aligned} (x^2=4)\supset {Det } (x=2 \;{ or }\; x= -2). \end{aligned}$$
For when the posit is dropped the context has changed. As a result the consequent of the conditional becomes false, which thus entails the falsity of the antecedent, i.e. we would wrongly infer that \(x^2\ne 4\). Conditional proof is no longer a valid rule of inference.
If we are to do logic on the basis of syntactic form when we are dealing with these kinds of expressions we have two choices. Either we keep close to the syntactic structure of natural language at the risk of abandoning the standard principles of logic as applied to syntactic form, or we make sure to de-contextualise the expressions in question. For instance, adopting the latter strategy we can rewrite ‘You are guilty and you are not guilty’ as ‘You\(_1\) are guilty and you\(_2\) are not guilty’ where the indices make sure that repeated uses of ‘you’ are not necessarily to be treated as referring to the same individual. In a similar way one can de-contextualise the determinately operator. For instance, one can relativise it to a context of use, as in ‘Det[in the context of use u] B’, or relativise it to a specific collection of posits, as in ‘Det[given only posits \(A_1, \ldots , A_n\)] B’. So, for instance, Det[given only posit \(x^2 = 4\)] (\(x=2\) or \(x= -2\)) would be true regardless of what is currently being assumed while Det[given only posit \(x^2 = 4\)] (\(x=2\)) and Det[given no posit] (\(x=2\) or \(x=-2\)) would be false regardless of what is currently being assumed. Now all the standard principles of classical logic are safe.
In the literature on the Det-operator, the first strategy is by far the most popular. Some [e.g. Keefe (2000)] embrace the resulting clash with principles of classical logic. Williamson (1994, p. 151–152) considers such an approach to be ‘revisionary’ with respect to logic. This is certainly true in one sense, but is perhaps a bit unfair. If one wants to do logic keeping the surface syntactic structure of ‘You are guilty and you are not guilty’ (making sure it doesn’t logically behave like a contradiction), clearly some principles of classical logic need to be revised, but this does not necessarily amount to a deep break with the semantic commitments that we take to underlie classical logic (e.g. the fact that we allow that a singular term like ‘you’ can denote different individuals when it occurs in different parts of a sentence does not mean that we allow that one and the same person can, at a given moment, be both guilty and not guilty). The same can be said for ‘revisionary’ approaches to the Det-operator: the classical principles of reasoning were not developed for cases where the truth value of a sentence changes as we reason (and because we reason). In any case, one can avoid such charges of revisionism by de-contextualising the determinately modality in the way suggested above.