Skip to main content
Log in

Legal punishment of immorality: once more into the breach

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Gerald Dworkin’s overlooked defense of legal moralism attempts to undermine the traditional liberal case for a principled distinction between behavior that is immoral and criminal and behavior that is immoral but not criminal. According to Dworkin, his argument for legal moralism “depends upon a plausible idea of what making moral judgments involves.” The idea Dworkin has in mind here is a metaethical principle that many have connected to morality/reasons internalism. I agree with Dworkin that this is a plausible principle, but I argue that some of the best reasons for accepting it actually work against his enforcement thesis. I propose a principled distinction between the immoral-and-criminal and the immoral-but-not-criminal, and argue that a principle at least very much like it must be correct if the metaethical principle Dworkin avows is correct.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, the special Symposium issue on Law, Liberty and Morality: 50 Years On of Criminal Law and Philosophy.

  2. Liberal perfectionists sometimes argue for the legitimacy of the state using legal instruments to promote certain values. Joseph Raz’s principle of autonomy, for example, “permits and even requires governments to create morally valuable opportunities, and to eliminate repugnant ones” (Raz 1986, p. 417). Yet Raz disavows legal moralism in favor of a (peculiar sort of) harm principle. Direct support of Dworkin’s opposition to Hart and Feinberg is more recent. See, especially, Richard Arneson who writes, “My views on the enforcement of morals as such (legal moralism) owe a lot to Dworkin’s insights” (2013, p. 441, n. 12).

  3. He subjects the views of Ronald Dworkin (in Dworkin 1990) and Joel Feinberg (in Dworkin 1999) to close scrutiny.

  4. Or, more generally, between moral obligation and accountability. Stephen Darwall presents morality/reasons internalism in Darwall (1997, p. 306). He connects this view to the metaethical principle Dworkin invokes in Darwall (2006a, pp. 276–277), Darwall (2006b, pp. 26–27) and Darwall (2007, pp. 290–292). Others who make similar arguments include Skorupski (1999, pp. 42–43) and Portmore (2011, pp. 43–44).

  5. Dworkin (1999, p. 946). If debates about the morality of homosexual sex are passé, then substitute some other more controversial contemporary issue.

  6. Mill [(1859) 2004, p. 10]. Though just “one very simple principle,” interpretations of it vary. Daniel Jacobsen canvasses many of them and presents a novel understanding of Mill’s “Doctrine of Liberty” in Jacobsen 2000.

  7. Dworkin has attempted to raise problems for the version Rawls defended in Theory of Justice in Dworkin (1974).

  8. See Rawls (2005), Larmore (1996), Scanlon (1998) and Gaus (2011).

  9. I have been presenting Mill’s harm principle as an early version of a public justification test for the legitimacy of legal coercion, which focused exclusively on harm-based reasons. Since some reasons that might plausibly be public in the requisite sense are not really harm-based, and some harm-based reasons might not really be public in the requisite sense, we should introduce the modification that follows. However, an anonymous referee suggests that Mill’s harm principle is more a substantive constraint on the law’s content rather than a test of public reasoning. I don’t object to this interpretation of Mill, but since it is no less susceptible to Dworkin’s objection, we should introduce the modification that follows.

  10. Alternatively, moralistic considerations that are considerations (or reasons) distinctive to some group will fail the test of public justification.

  11. Arneson elaborates in Arneson (2010) and Arneson (2014).

  12. Mill ([1859] 2004, p. 10). Emphasis added.

  13. Dworkin (1999, p. 928, n. 8). Emphasis added.

  14. In fairness, though, Dworkin would not be the only one. See, for example, Bird (2014) and Quong (2014).

  15. Dworkin defends an enforcement thesis in terms of majority preferences in Dworkin (1990). But, again, in Dworkin (1999), he claims to be concerned with the critical, rather than positive, morality.

  16. Gaus argues for this in Gaus (2009b).

References

  • Arneson, R. (2010). Against freedom of conscience. San Diego Law Review, 47(4), 1015–1040.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (2013). The enforcement of morals revisited. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 7(3), 435–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (2014). Rejecting the order of public reason. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 537–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, C. (2014). Coercion and public reason. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 13(3), 189–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2007). Morality in a natural world. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (1997). Reasons, motives and the demands of morality: An introduction. In S. Darwall, A. Gibbard & P. Railton (Eds.), Moral discourse and practice (pp. 305–312). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006a). The value of autonomy and autonomy of the will. Ethics, 116, 263–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006b). The second-person standpoint: morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2007). Morality and practical reason: A Kantian approach. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory (pp. 282–320). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, P. (1965). The enforcement of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1974). Non-neutral principles. The journal of philosophy, 71(14), 491–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1990). Equal respect and the enforcement of morality. Social Philosophy and Policy, 7(2), 180–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1999). Devlin was right: Law and the enforcement of morality. William and Mary Law Review, 40, 927–946.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1987a). The moral limits of the criminal law: Harm to others. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1987b). Some unswept debris from the Hart-Devlin debate. Synthese, 72(2), 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1988a). The moral limits of the criminal law: Harmless wrongdoing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1988b). Liberalism, community, and tradition. Tikkun, 3(3), 38–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. The Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2009a). The moral foundations of liberal neutrality. In T. Christiano & J. Christman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in political philosophy. Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2009b). The place of religious belief in public reason liberalism. In M. Dimovia-Cokson & P. Stirk (Eds.), Multiculturalism and moral conflict. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2011). The order of public reason. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2012). Sectarianism without perfection? Quong’s political liberalism. Philosophy and Public Issues, 2(1), 7–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1963). Law, liberty and morality. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsen, D. (2000). Mill on liberty, speech, and the free society. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29(3), 276–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2005). The evolution of morality. Massachusetts: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, C. (1996). The morals of modernity. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1963). Collected works of John Stuart Mill. In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The subjection of women (Vol. 21). Toronto: Routledge.

  • Mill, J. S. ([1861] 1979). Utilitarianism. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Mill, J. S. ([1859] 2004). On liberty. New York: Barnes & Noble Books.

  • Portmore, D. (2011). Commonsense consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, J. (2014). On the idea of public reason. In D. Reidy & J. Mandle (Eds.), A companion to Rawls. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2005). Political liberalism. Columbia, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski, J. (1999). The domain of reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1961). Social morality and individual ideals. Philosophy, 36(136), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Symposium on Law, Liberty and Morality: Fifty Years On (2013). Criminal Law and Philosophy, 7(3), 417–548.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I owe thanks to Paul Billingham, Russell DiSilvestro and Gerald Dworkin for comments and discussion on this paper. A Summer 2014 grant from the California State University, Sacramento Provost’s Research Incentive Fund supported my completion of the project.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kyle Swan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Swan, K. Legal punishment of immorality: once more into the breach. Philos Stud 174, 983–1000 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0727-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0727-y

Keywords

Navigation