Skip to main content
Log in

You can see what ‘I’ means

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper takes up the question of whether we can visually represent something as having semantic value. Something has semantic value if it represents some property, thing or concept. An argument is offered that we can represent semantic value based on a variety of number-color synesthesia. This argument is shown to withstand several objections that can be lodged against the popular arguments from phenomenal contrast and from the mundane example of reading.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Siegel (2006, pp 490–491).

  2. Forthcoming. Levine reviews but does not endorse the argument.

  3. Forthcoming.

  4. Especially Schwitzgebel (2008).

  5. The expectation that there will be a phenomenal contrast is built into the name of the argument.

  6. Pylyshyn (2003).

  7. Lewis (1980).

  8. Siegel (2006, pp. 490–491).

  9. see Tye 1995 and Dretske 1995.

  10. Ramachandran and Hubbard (2001).

  11. Ward and Sagiv (2007).

  12. It is questionable whether this would be the sort of de-coupling needed here since without the color photism, we would end up with a different visual experience.

  13. This argument concerns congenital synesthesias. Acquired synesthesias resulting from trauma or induced through hypnosis may be better described by associationism.

  14. Asher et al. (2009).

  15. Galton (1883).

  16. Ward and Simner (2005).

  17. Sollberger (2011). Gray (2001) offers a contrasting view.

  18. Maurer and Mondloch (2004).

  19. See Maurer and Mondloch (2004).

  20. For discussion see Ward et al. (2008), and Rothen and Meier (2010).

  21. For discussion see Ramachandran and Hubbard (2001, 2003), and also Mulvenna (2007).

References

  • Asher, J. E., Lamb, J., Brocklebank, D., Cazier, J., Maestrini, E., Addis, L., et al. (2009). A whole-genome scan and fine-mapping linkage study of auditory-visual synesthesia reveals evidence of linkage to chromosomes. American Journal of Human Genetics, 84, 279–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. (1883). Inquiries into human faculty and its development. London: Dent & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, R. (2001). Cognitive modules, synesthesia and the constitution of psychological natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 65–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). Veridical hallucination an prosthetic vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58(3), 239–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, D., & Mondloch, C. (2004). Neonatal synesthesia: A re-evaluation. In L. Robertson & N. Sagiv (Eds.), Attention on synesthesia: Cognition, development and neuroscience (pp. 193–213). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulvenna, C. M. (2007). Synaesthesia, the arts and creativity: A neurological connection. Frontiers of Neurology and Neuroscience, 22, 206–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXIX(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V. S., & Hubbard, E. M. (2001). Synesthesia: A window into perception, thought and language. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(12), 3–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V. S., & Hubbard, E. M. (2003). Hearing colors, tasting shapes. Scientific American, April, 52–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothen, N., & Meier, B. (2010). Higher prevalence of synaesthesia in art students. Perception, 39, 718–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naïve introspection. Philosophical Review, 117, 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Gendler Szabo & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), In perceptual experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sollberger, M. (2011). Rethinking synesthesia. Philosophical Psychology (forthcoming).

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J., & Sagiv, N. (2007). Synesthesia for finger counting and dice patterns: A case of higher synesthesia? Neurocase, 13(2), 86–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J., & Simner, J. (2005). Is synesthesia an X linked dominant trait with lethality in males? Perception, 34(5), 611–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, J., Thompson-Lake, D., Ely, R., & Kaminski, F. (2008). Synaesthesia, creativity and art: What is the link? British Journal of Psychology, 99, 127–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Gary Bartlett, Peter Mandik and Elizabeth Schechter for feedback that led to improvements.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jennifer Matey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Matey, J. You can see what ‘I’ means. Philos Stud 162, 57–70 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9988-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9988-2

Keywords

Navigation