Skip to main content
Log in

Surveys, intuitions, knowledge attributions

Comments on Keith DeRose’s “Contextualism, Contrastivism, and X-Phi Surveys”

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. As opposed to claims about knowledge, or who knows what: epistemic contextualism (EC) is a semantic thesis about the truth conditional contents of the propositions expressed by certain sentences—viz., that they are ‘context’-dependent and—variable: in itself, EC is silent about knowledge. For discussion of this and other points, arguments and issues surrounding EC, see Rysiew 2007a.

  2. This is a misleading way of putting it since, according to EC, there is no one knowledge relation—at least, no unrelativized one—that all occurrences of ‘know(s)’ pick out (cf. previous note; Bach 2005, Section 1). Fortunately, this doesn’t affect the current discussion.

  3. Version cited: http://pantheon.yale.edu/%7Ekd47/Contextualism%20and%20X-Phi-10-10.pdf. Last accessed 26 Aug 2011.

  4. DeRose’s is most explicit about what makes for “the best cases” at 2009, 53ff., 155ff; in the present paper, see p. 3.

  5. The other two such studies are, for reasons DeRose gives (pp. 18–25), not after all clearly relevant to arguing for contrastivism.

  6. Whether this suffices to make contrastivism a form of EC is most likely a terminological issue. (For Schaffer on the differences between contrastivism and canonical versions of EC, see his 2004.) Here, purely for the sake of ease of reference in differentiating between contrastivism and more standard forms of EC—such as have been endorsed by DeRose, Stewart Cohen, and others—I’ll tend to use ‘contextualism’ to refer to the latter.

  7. For other examples see Sudman et al. (1996) and several of the contributions to Schwarz and Sudman (1992).

  8. S&K (Section 6.3) anticipate an attempt to explain the results in the ‘context’ case in terms of conversational pragmatics, one that’s styled after Rysiew (2001) and Brown (2006). While they think the imagined view represents “an interesting and plausible strategy”, they register two objections to it: it cannot explain why we would deny certain claims, they think, and it fails the cancelability test. Brown (2006) and Rysiew (2001, 2005, Section 3; 2007b, Section 4) have responded to just these worries about their views. However, as discussed, it is doubtful that any very sophisticated theory is required for handling the ‘context sensitivity’ case.

  9. This and other recent studies have been the subject of a lot of web discussion among philosophers. That the subjects in the thief contrast case may well be picking up on a presupposition about what was stolen and reading it into the story itself is among the ideas floated at Certain Doubts, by Aaron Zimmerman and Jennifer Nagel in particular: http://el-prod.baylor.edu/certain_doubts/?p=908.

  10. Here, I’m drawing on Bach’s (2005, 76) articulation of the worry. For related concerns, see Nagel (2008).

  11. Though I do think that care should be taken in articulating just what the intuitions are, exactly—whether, e.g., it’s that both of the relevant claims are true (flat-out), that they each enjoy some intuitive plausibility, that what the subject “says” in both cases is “correct” or “appropriate”, or what. In stating what is uncontroversial in this regard, I myself have put it in deliberately weak, and so (it’s hoped) uncontentious, terms—for instance, by saying that the Bank Case, e.g., “illustrates the fact that there is a manifest flexibility in our willingness to attribute knowledge, whether to ourselves or to others: it is incontrovertible that, in some sense anyway, “what counts as knowing” depends upon ‘context’” (Rysiew 2001, 477–478).

  12. Another possibility here—one that DeRose doesn’t consider but which complements his discussion—is that subjects are taking cues from the structure of the questionnaire itself: when they are asked to indicate how strongly they agree with the sentence “When Hanna says, ‘I know [/don’t know] that they bank will be open tomorrow,’ what she says is true” by selecting a value on a 7-point Likert scale, that itself might be taken to suggest that the matter is not straightforward but complex (see Cullen, forthcoming, Section 3.3.1); if so, in the absence of a clear grasp of what such complexities are, much less how to negotiate them, subjects might naturally default towards the ‘safe’, neutral response.

  13. For further discussion, see Rysiew 2007a, Section 4.3.

  14. Nor is it to say that subjects and their judgments can’t be tutored to a large degree, or that carefully crafted probes—where sensitivity to the relevant distinctions is built into the survey itself, as it were—can’t themselves do the work of philosophical savvy on the part of subjects, reliably eliciting their views on the desired issues.

  15. Such an insistence follows immediately after the remark just quoted. DeRose writes: “However, at least with regard to many cases, the intuition about whether a claim involving ‘know(s)’ made in the examples is true can at least be fairly strong, and when that intuition can be buttressed in the ways we are about to investigate, I think it can become the basis of a strong philosophical argument” (2009, 50, n. 2).

  16. DeRose (1999, 2002; in 2009, see 112–117) has argued against the existence of some crucial conflicting intuitions in the case of EC and its competitors; Brown (2006) and Rysiew (2005) have replied.

  17. For some of which, see Rysiew 2007a. My own reaction to EC is rather like DeRose’s position on epistemic aspectism (see above): in spite of whatever intuitive pull the relevant claims enjoy, those intuitions—especially as concerns the sense that the HIGH denial is “correct” (to use a neutral term)—conflict with other things that are in my view much more strongly grounded; and they can, moreover, be accommodated otherwise than by taking them as all face-value true.

  18. Compare DeRose, discussing aspectism: “The issue has always seemed to me to be one of finding the best resolution of such conflicts [among intuitions]…. Key to the construction of resolutions to these conflicts is not just measuring the degree to which the various claims are intuitively plausible, but also, vitally, accounts of the meanings of and connections between the various relevant forms of knowledge claims, by which the intuitive plausibility of the various claims can be explained—and sometimes explained away” (p. 29).

References

  • Bach, K. (2005). The emperor’s new ‘Knows’. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth (pp. 51–89). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2006). Contextualism and warranted assertibility manoeuvres. Philosophical Studies, 130, 407–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. (Forthcoming). Knowledge isn’t closed on saturdays. Review of Philosophy and Psychology.

  • Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, pp. 57–89.

  • Cullen, S. (Forthcoming). Survey-driven romanticism. European Review of Philosophy.

  • Cummins, R. (1998). Reflections on reflective equilibrium. In M. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 113–127). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1999). Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 185–203). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge and context. The Philosophical Review, 111(2), 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Zarpentine, C. (Forthcoming). Do you know more when it matters less? Philosophical Psychology.

  • May, J., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Hull, J. G., & Aaron Z. (Forthcoming). Practical interests, relevant alternatives, and knowledge attributions: An empirical study. Review of Philosophy and Psychology.

  • Nagel, J. (2008). Knowledge ascriptions and the psychological consequences of changing stakes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86(2), 279–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs, 35(4), 477–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2005). Contesting contextualism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 69, 51–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2007a). Epistemic contextualism. In: N. Z. Edward (Ed.) The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, latest archived version, Spring 2009. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/contextualism-epistemology/.

  • Rysiew, P. (2007b). Speaking of knowing. Noûs, 41(4), 627–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies, 119(1–2), 73–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J., & Knobe, J. (Forthcoming). Contrastive knowledge surveyed. Noûs. Version cited: http://www.jonathanschaffer.org/surveyed.pdf. Last accessed 26 Aug 2011.

  • Schwarz, N. (1995). What respondents learn from questionnaires: The survey interview and the logic of conversation. International Statistical Review/Revue Internationale de Statistique, 63(2), 153–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, N., & Sudman, S. (Eds.). (1992). Context effects in social and psychological research. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sudman, S., Bradburn, N. M., & Schwarz, N. (1996). Thinking about answers. San Francisco: Joessy-Bass Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My thanks to the Oberlin Colloquium organizers and attendees; special thanks to Keith DeRose, Cindy Holder, Jennifer Nagel, and Joel Pust.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Rysiew.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rysiew, P. Surveys, intuitions, knowledge attributions. Philos Stud 156, 111–120 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9804-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9804-4

Keywords

Navigation