Skip to main content
Log in

Multilayer networks as embodied consciousness interactions. A formal model approach

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An algebraic interpretation of multigraph networks is introduced in relation to conscious experience, brain and body. These multigraphs have the ability to merge by an associative binary operator \(\odot \), accounting for biological composition. We also study a mathematical formulation of splitting layers, resulting in a formal analysis of the transition from conscious to non-conscious activity. From this construction, we recover core structures for conscious experience, dynamical content and causal constraints that conscious interactions may impose. An important result is the prediction of structural topological changes after conscious interactions. These results may inspire further use of formal mathematics to describe and predict new features of conscious experience while aligning well with formal tries to mathematize phenomenology, phenomenological tradition and applications to artificial consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Readers unfamiliar with abstract mathematics will be able to grasp these benefits by understanding the examples we provide, without any lack of rigour or generality.

  2. Here we will understand causal influence in a broader sense, allowing structural and dynamical influences beyond direct interventions. See Signorelli et al. (2023) for details.

  3. A multiset is a set in which some its elements can appear more than once. Then, multiplicity of a multiset is the number of times a certain element appears in the multiset.

  4. This is based on the categorical networks models of Baez et al. (2018)

  5. In Baez et al. (2018), the authors explicitly describe the symmetric monoidal structure on the category of coloured network models that allow us to consider coloured multilayers.

  6. Bear in mind that modalities can be generalized to more aspects than only the five senses.

  7. The operator \({\varvec{\cup }}\) is also useful to check that our previous 1-coloured sets \(RMG^{t}(n)\) are partial commutative monoids.

References

  • Abramsky, S. (2018). Contextuality: At the Borders of Paradox, Oxford University Press, vol. 1 (pp. 1–471). https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198748991.001.0001

  • AMCS (2021). Association for Mathematical Consciousness Science (AMCS). https://amcs-community.org

  • Baars, B. J. (2005). Global workspace theory of consciousness: toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience. Progress in brain research, 150, 45–53. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0079-6123(05)50004-9

  • Baez, J. C., Foley, J., Moeller, J., & Pollard, B. S. (2018). Network models.

  • Beavers, A. F. (2002). Phenomenology and Artificial Intelligence. Metaphilosophy, 33, 70–82. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9973.00217

  • Birch, J., Schnell, A. K., & Clayton, N. S. (2020). Dimensions of Animal Consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 24, 789–801. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2020.07.007

  • Bitbol, M. (2008). Is Consciousness primary? NeuroQuantology, 6, 53–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M., & Petitmengin, C. (2013). A defense of introspection from within. Constructivist Foundations, 8, 269–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M., & Petitmengin, C. (2016). On the possibility and reality of introspection. Mind and Matter, 14, 51–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 227–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boccaletti, S., Bianconi, G., Criado, R., del Genio, C. I., Gómez-Gardeñes, J., Romance, M., Sendiña-Nadal, I., Wang, Z., & Zanin, M. (2014). The structure and dynamics of multilayer networks. Physics Reports, 544, 1–122. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.physrep.2014.07.001

  • Brooks, R. A. (1990). Elephants don’t play chess. Robotics and Autonomous Systems, 6, 3–15. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0921-8890(05)80025-9

  • Buttazzo, G., & Manzotti, R. (2008). Artificial consciousness: Theoretical and practical issues. Artificial Intelligence in Medicine, 44, 79–82. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.artmed.2008.08.001

  • Calí, C. (2023). Philosophical, Experimental and Synthetic Phenomenology: The Study of Perception for Biological, Artificial Agents and Environments. Foundations of Science, 28, 1111–1124. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09869-7

  • Cea, I., Negro, N., & Signorelli, C. M. (2023). The Fundamental Tension in Integrated Information Theory 4.0’s Realist Idealism. Entropy, 25, 1453. https://doi.org/10.3390/e25101453

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). The puzzle of conscious experience. Scientific American, 273, 80–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crease, R. P. (2012). Phenomenology and Natural Science.

  • de Barros, J. A., Montemayor, C., & Assis, L. P. D. (2017). Contextuality in the Integrated Information Theory. Springer International Publishing, vol. 8369 (pp. 57–70). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-54943-4

  • Dehaene, S., & Changeux, J. P. (2011). Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing. Neuron, 70, 200–27. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2011.03.018

  • Dehaene, S., Lau, H., & Kouider, S. (2017). What is consciousness, and could machines have it? Science, 358, 484–489. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aan8871

  • Demertzi, A., Tagliazucchi, E., Dehaene, S., Deco, G., Barttfeld, P., Raimondo, F., Martial, C., Fernández-Espejo, D., Rohaut, B., Voss, H. U., Schiff, N. D., Owen, A. M., Laureys, S., Naccache, L., & Sitt, J. D. (2019). Human consciousness is supported by dynamic complex patterns of brain signal coordination. Science Advances, 5, 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1126/sciadv.aat7603

  • Ehresmann, A. C., & Vanbremeersch, J. P. (2009). MENS, a mathematical model for cognitive systems. Journal of Mind Theory, 129–180. https://doi.org/10.1021/ja042798i

  • Fong, B., & Spivak, D. I. (2019). An Invitation to Applied Category Theory, Cambridge University Press (p. 348). https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108668804

  • Froese, T., & Paolo, & E. A. D. (2009). Sociality and the life-mind continuity thesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8, 439–463. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-009-9140-8

  • Gallagher, S. (2006). How the Body Shapes the Mind, Oxford University Press (pp. 1–294). https://doi.org/10.1093/0199271941.001.0001

  • Gallagher, S. (2015). On the possibility of naturalizing phenomenology. Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology (pp. 70–93).

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind, first ed., Routledge. https://doi.org/10.5860/choice.50-1996

  • Gallagher, S. (1986). Lived Body and Environment. Research in Phenomenology, 16, 139–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graziano, M. S. A., & Webb, T. W. (2018). Understanding consciousness by building it, Bloomsbury (pp. 187–210).

  • Grünbaum, T., & Christensen, M. S. (2020). Measures of agency. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2020,. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niaa019

  • Hartimo, M., (Ed.) (2010). Phenomenology and Mathematics, vol. 195, Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3729-9

  • Husserl, E. (1983). General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (1999). The Idea of Phenomenology, vol. 44, Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7386-3

  • Jaegher, H. D., Paolo, E. D., & Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 441–447. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009

  • Jordan, J. S. (2012). Consciousness and Embodiment, Springer US (pp. 217–222). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-0463-8_279

  • Kivela, M., Arenas, A., Barthelemy, M., Gleeson, J. P., Moreno, Y., & Porter, M. A. (2014). Multilayer networks. Journal of complex networks, 2, 203–271. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198809456.003.0001

  • Kleiner, J. (2020). Mathematical Models of Consciousness. Entropy, 22, 609. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22060609

  • Kleiner, J., & Hoel, E. (2021). Falsification and consciousness. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2021, 1–15. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niab001

  • LeDoux, J., Birch, J., Andrews, K., Clayton, N. S., Daw, N. D., Frith, C., Lau, H., Peters, M. A., Schneider, S., Seth, A., Suddendorf, T., & Vandekerckhove, M. M. (2023). Consciousness beyond the human case. Current Biology, 33, R832–R840. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2023.06.067

  • Lingis, A. (1986). On Phenomenological Explanation, Springer, vol. 96 (pp. 1–19). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9610-2_1

  • Lori, N., Samit, E., Picciochi, G., Jesus, P. (2019). Free-will Perception in Human Mental Health: an Axiomatic Formalization, Vernon Press (pp. 139–174).

  • MacLane, S. (1998). Categories for the Working Mathematician, second ed, Springer New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4757-4721-8

  • Maclane, S. (1965). Categorical Algebra. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 71, 40–106. https://doi.org/10.1090/S0002-9904-1965-11234-4

  • Martínez-Riaño, D. E., & González, F., Gómez, F. (2023). 1 persistent features of the resting-state connectome in healthy subjects. Network Neuroscience, 7, 234–253. https://doi.org/10.1162/netn_a_00280

  • Mashour, G. A., Roelfsema, P., Changeux, J. P., & Dehaene, S. (2020). Conscious Processing and the Global Neuronal Workspace Hypothesis. Neuron, 105, 776–798. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2020.01.026

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1998). De máquinas y seres vivos, quinta ed., Editorial Universitaria S.A. (p. 136).

  • Mensch, J. (2006). Artificial Intelligence and the Phenomenology of Flesh. PhaenEx, 1, 73. https://doi.org/10.22329/p.v1i1.44

  • Mensch, J. R. (1991). Phenomenology and artificial intelligence: Husserl learns Chinese. Husserl Studies, 8, 107–127. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00123537

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2005). Phenomenology of perception. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mesulam, M. (1990). Large-Scale Neurocognitive Networks and Distributed Processing for Attention, Language, and Memory. Neurological Progress. Annals of Neurology, 28, 597’613. https://doi.org/10.1002/ana.410280502

  • Migeot, J. A., Duran-Aniotz, C. A., Signorelli, C. M., Piguet, O., & Ibáñez, A. (2022). A predictive coding framework of allostatic-interoceptive overload in frontotemporal dementia. Trends in Neurosciences, 45, 838–853. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tins.2022.08.005

  • Naccache, L. (2018). Why and how access consciousness can account for phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 373. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0357

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., & Tononi, G. (2014). From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated Information Theory 3.0. PLoS computational biology, 10, e1003588. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588

  • Paolo, E. D., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. (2017). Sensorimotor Life. An enactive proposal, Oxford University Press (p. 304).

  • Paolo, E. D., Thompson, E., & Beer, R. D. (2021). Laying down a forking path: Incompatibilities between enaction and the free energy principle. PsyArXiv (pp. 1–43). https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/d9v8f

  • Pessoa, L. (2014). Understanding brain networks and brain organization. Physics of Life Reviews, 11, 400–435. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2014.03.005

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petitmengin, C., Remillieux, A., & Valenzuela-Moguillansky, C. (2019). Discovering the structures of lived experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 18, 691–730. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9597-4

  • Petitot, J., Varela, F., Pachoud, B., & Roy, J. M. (1999). Naturalizing Phenomenology.

  • Prentner, R. (2019). Consciousness and topologically structured phenomenal spaces. Consciousness and Cognition, 70, 25–38. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2019.02.002

  • Preston, B. (1993). Heidegger and Artificial Intelligence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 43. https://doi.org/10.2307/2108053

  • Rodríguez, E. (2008). Ideas para naturalizar el estudio de la conciencia, Editorial Granica (pp. 301–324).

  • Roy, J. M., Petitot, J., Pachoud, B., & Varela, F. (1999). Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2000). Consciousness, free action and the brain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 3–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Signorelli, C. M. (2018b). Can Computers Overcome Humans? Consciousness Interaction and its Implications. IEEE (pp. 61–69). https://doi.org/10.1109/ICCI-CC.2018.8482038

  • Signorelli, C. M., Cea, I., & Prentner, R. (2023). We need to explain subjective experience, but its explanation may not be mechanistic. Neuroscience of Consciousness.

  • Signorelli, C. M., Cea, I., Prentner, R., & Melloni, L. (2023). The science of consciousness beyond neuroscience. (in preparation).

  • Signorelli, C. M. (2018). Can Computers become Conscious and overcome Humans? Frontiers Robotics and Artificial Intelligence, 5. https://doi.org/10.3389/frobt.2018.00121

  • Signorelli, C. M., Boils, J. D., Tagliazucchi, E., Jarraya, B., & Deco, G. (2022). From brain-body function to consciousness interaction. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 141. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104833

  • Signorelli, C. M., & Meling, D. (2021). Towards new concepts for a biological neuroscience of consciousness. Cognitive Neurodynamics, 15, 783–804. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11571-020-09658-7

  • Signorelli, C. M., Szczotka, J., & Prentner, R. (2021). Explanatory profiles of models of consciousness - towards a systematic classification. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2021. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niab021

  • Signorelli, C. M., Wang, Q., & Coecke, B. (2021). Reasoning about conscious experience with axiomatic and graphical mathematics. Consciousness and Cognition, 95, 103168. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2021.103168

  • Signorelli, C. M., Wang, Q., & Khan, I. (2021). A Compositional Model of Consciousness Based on Consciousness-Only. Entropy, 23, 308. https://doi.org/10.3390/e23030308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. H., & Schillaci, G. (2021). Why Build a Robot With Artificial Consciousness? How to Begin? A Cross-Disciplinary Dialogue on the Design and Implementation of a Synthetic Model of Consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology, 12,. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2021.530560

  • Thompson, E. (2014). Waking, Dreaming, Being, Columbia University Press (p. 496). https://doi.org/10.7312/thom13709

  • Thompson, E. (2004). Life and mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3, 381–398. https://doi.org/10.1023/b:phen.0000048936.73339.dd

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in cognitive sciences, 5, 418–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., & Koch, C. (2016). Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate. Nature reviews. Neuroscience, 17, 450–61. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., & Edelman, G. M. (1998). Consciousness and complexity. Science, 282, 1846–1851. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.282.5395.1846

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsuchiya, N., & Saigo, H. (2020). Applying Yoneda’s lemma to consciousness research: categories of level and contents of consciousness. Preprint. https://doi.org/10.31219/osf.io/68nhy

  • Tull, S., Kleiner, J. (2020). Integrated Information in Process Theories (pp. 1–22).

  • Varela, F. (1979). Principles of Biological Autonomy, Elsevier North Holland (p. 306).

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (2016). The Embodied Mind, revised ed ed., MIT Press (p. 392).

  • Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, 330–349.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Maturana, H., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems, 5, 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. F., & Wegner, D. M. (2013). Mind-blanking: When the mind goes away. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 1–15. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yoshimi, J. (2007). Mathematizing phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 271–291. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9052-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joaquin Diaz Boils.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

Not applicable.

Informed Consent

Not applicable.

Statement Regarding Research Involving Human Participants and/or Animals

Not applicable.

Competing Interests

Authors declare no conflict of interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix A

Appendix A

In this supplementary section, we briefly discuss our multilayer implementation in light of its algebraic structure through Category Theory and provide some algebraic definitions used in the main text. We first introduce some content on algebraic structures used in the paper, some formal definitions on Multilayer Networks and finally categorical concepts for a formal account of multilayer networks (see Signorelli et al. 2021b, Fong and Spivak 2019, Kivela et al. 2014 for other introductions).

1.1 Monoids A.1

We start by defining a monoid as a particular algebraic structure:

Definition 16

A monoid is a tuple \((M,\oplus ,\epsilon )\) where M is a set and for every \(m,n,p \in M\):

  • \(\oplus \) is a total associative binary operation on M, that is

    $$ (m\oplus n)\oplus p=m\oplus (n\oplus p) $$
  • \(\epsilon \) is the identity for \(\oplus \), that is

    $$ \epsilon \oplus m=m=m\oplus \epsilon $$

A monoid is said to be commutative if \(\oplus \) is commutative, that is, if

$$ m\oplus n=n\oplus m $$

1.2 Tensor product of monoids A.2

We define the tensor product of (commutative) monoids starting from the well-known concept of cartesian product of sets: given two sets F and S their cartesian product is defined as

$$ F\times S=\{(f,s)/f\in F, s\in S\} $$

We can think of the sets of first and second dishes when ordering in a restaurant: F would be all available first dishes and S the second ones, then \(F\times S\) represent all possible combinations one can order.

Now the cartesian product of two given monoids \((M_1,\ominus ,\epsilon _1)\) and \((M_2,\oslash ,\epsilon _2)\) is defined through the componentwise operation \(\star \) given by

$$ (m,n)\star (m',n')=(m\ominus m',n\oslash n') $$

for \(m,m'\in M_1\) and \(n,n'\in M_2\). Now \(M_1\times M_2\) with \(\star \) is a two-fold monoid.

Finally, the tensor product of monoids, written \(M_1\otimes {M_2}\), is the quotient of their cartesian product by the relations

$$ (m,n)\star (m',n)\sim (m\ominus m',n)\qquad (m,n)\star (m,n')\sim (m,n\oslash n') $$
$$ (\epsilon _1,n)\sim (m,\epsilon _2) $$

1.3 Partial monoids A.3

Definition 17

A partial monoid is a monoid \((M,\oplus ,\epsilon )\) where \(\oplus \) is a partial operation. A partial monoid is said to be commutative if \(\oplus \) has this property whenever defined.

1.4 Concepts on multilayer networks A.4

The following is a sketch of some of the concepts involved in the theory of Multilayer Networks belonging to Kivela et al. (2014), they are mentioned and used in the paper and given here in a more formal presentation. If a node u has different aspects \(a_1,\ldots ,a_d\) in layers into the sets \((L_{1},\ldots ,L_{d})\) respectively, a widely used notation is:

$$(u,\textbf{a})\equiv (u,a_{1},\ldots ,a_{d})$$

We note here that in this paper we avoided this notation in favour of a more appropriate way to express the features we want to describe.

The set of edges is partitioned into intra-layer edges and inter-layer edges. Intra-layer edges correspond to the interactions inside layers (e.g. yellow and light blue edges, Fig. 1A) and belong to sets

$$E_{A}=\{((u,\textbf{a}),(v,\mathbf {a'}))\in E_{M}| \textbf{a}=\mathbf {a'}\}$$

1.5 Categorizing multilayers A.5

Category theory is a branch of highly abstract mathematics. One of the main features is its power to generalize relationships across different mathematical structures. This generalization is due to its general definition of objects as mathematical types, morphisms as maps or transformations from objects/types to other objects/types, and the composition operation, which may respect associative and identity law. It can be consulted (Maclane, 1965) as a source of the main categorical concepts.

In order to give a categorical interpretation of our multilayer networks of Section 2.2, we make use of the notions introduced in Baez et al. (2018). Following that reference, we consider a functor that produces many-coloured networks out of non-directed multigraphs.

Denote by \(\mathcal {S}\) the permutation groupoid, that is, a skeleton of the groupoid of finite sets and bijections. \(\mathcal {S}\) is a (strict) symmetric monoidal category.

Definition 18

A one-coloured network model is a lax symmetric monoidal functor \(F:\mathcal {S}\rightarrow Mon\) where Mon is the category of monoids.

Example 19

Let MG(n) be the set of multigraphs on \(\textbf{n}=\{1,\ldots ,n\}\). Then, a network model is a functor \(MG:\mathcal {S}\rightarrow Mon\) with values \((MG(n),+)\) where \(+\) is a multiset sum, that is, the addition of multiplicities of edges sharing the same vertices.

The category of network models over a fixed colour set \(\mathcal {C}\) is denoted by \(NetMod_{\mathcal {C}}\) (see Baez et al. 2018). \(NetMod_{\mathcal {C}}\) is a symmetric monoidal category and therefore we can have tensor functors such as those introduced above.

Definition 20

A network model for multigraphs with coloured edges is a functor

$$ MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}:\mathcal {S}\rightarrow Mon $$

where \(MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}(n)\) is a product of \(\left| \mathcal {C}\right| \) copies of the monoid MG(n), being \(\left| \mathcal {C}\right| \) the cardinal of the set \(\mathcal {C}\).

It is crucial that, in these tensor models, a network is not only a \(\mathcal {C}\)-tuple of multigraphs: it may also be viewed as a multigraph with as many edges of each colour between any pair of distinct vertices as they appear in every layer. The fact that the functor \(MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}\) is indeed a network model comes from the disjoint union operation:

$$ \begin{array}{c} MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}(n)\times MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}(m)\overset{\sqcup }{\longrightarrow }MG^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}(n+m)\end{array} $$

The particular kind of network model considered for the rotation multigraphs of Section 5 depends precisely on the rotation angle and, subsequently, a variable on time. However, it does not satisfy one of the requirements introduced in Baez et al. (2018), namely, being lax monoidal (see Baez et al. 2018). This is due to the fact that the operation analogous to \(\sqcup \) in non-rotation models, turns out to be partial in the rotation ones (i.e. subject to the condition \(\left| \alpha (t)\right| +\left| \beta (t)\right| \ge {{\pi }/{2}}\)).

Definition 21

Given \(t\in T\) and PMon the category of partial monoids, a network rotation model is a functor

$$ RMG^{t}:\mathcal {S}\rightarrow PMon $$

Example 22

A rotation network model for multigraphs with coloured edges is a functor

$$ [RMG^{t}]^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}:\mathcal {S}\rightarrow PMon $$

where \([RMG^{t}]^{\otimes \mathcal {C}}(n)\) is a product of \(\left| \mathcal {C}\right| \) partial monochrome monoids \(RMG^{t}(n)\) (recall that \(\mathcal {C}\) can be a multiset and then \(\left| \mathcal {C}\right| \) refers to the multiset cardinal).

1.6 Distributivity A.6

The \(\odot \) operation is distributive over \(\times \). That is, we obtain:

$$\begin{aligned} (\prod _{i=1}^{d_{1}}G_{i})\odot (\prod _{j=1}^{d_{2}}H_{j})=\prod _{i,j}(G_{i}\odot H_{j})=G_{1}\odot H_{1}\times \ldots \times G_{d_{1}}\odot H_{d_{2}} \end{aligned}$$
(1)

whenever we calculate over expressions of multilayers containing monochrome layers such as

$$ G_{1} \times \ldots \times G_{d_{1}} \in MG^{{c}_1}(n_{1}) \times \ldots \times MG^{{c}_{d_{1}}}(n_{d_{1}}) $$
$$ H_{1} \times \ldots \times H_{d_{2}} \in MG^{{c'}_1}(m_{1}) \times \ldots \times MG^{{c'}_{d_{2}}}(m_{d_{2}}) $$

The expression (Eq. 1) contains all combinations in the form \(G_{i}\odot H_{j}\) for \(i=1,\ldots ,d_{1}\) and \(j=1,\ldots ,d_{2}\) and lives in

$$ MG^{{c}_1\otimes {c'}_{1}}(n_{1}+m_{1}-p_{11}) \times \ldots \times MG^{{c}_{d_{1}}\otimes {c'}_{d_{2}}}(n_{d_{1}}+m_{d_{2}}-p_{d_{1}d_{2}}) $$

where \(p_{ij}=\left| V(G_{i})\cap V(H_{j})\right| \).

1.7 Inclusion-exclusion principle A.7

Counting the number of vertices into a graph

$$[G_{1},\alpha _{1}]\varvec{\odot }\ldots \varvec{\odot }[G_{k},\alpha _{k}]$$

means considering the known as Inclusion-Exclusion Principle in the form:

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{1 \le {i_1} \le k} \left| V(G_{i_1})\right| \!-\! \sum _{1 \le {i_1}< {i_2} \le k} \left| V(G_{i_1}) \cap V(G_{i_2})\right| \!+\! \sum _{1 \le {i_1}< {i_2} < {i_3} \le k} \left| V(G_{i_1}) \cap V(G_{i_2})\cap V(G_{i_3})\right| \!-\!\ldots \end{aligned}$$
$$\begin{aligned} \ldots + (-1)^{k+1} \left| \bigcap _{i=1}^k V(G_{i}) \right| \end{aligned}$$

where k corresponds to the number of graphs.

1.8 Decomposition in biobrane A.8

The decomposition of graphs in Biobrane is determined by the equation:

$$ {\varvec{\odot }}_{j=1}^{m}[{G}_{j},{\alpha }_{j}]={\varvec{\cup }}_{j=1}^{m}[{H}_{j},{\beta }_{j}] $$

where we impose that \(E(G_{j})=E(H_{j})\) for \(j=1,\ldots m\) but \(|V(H_{j})|=n\) and, moreover, \(\left| {\beta }_{j}\right| +\left| \beta _{l}\right| < {\pi /2}\) for \(j,l=1,\ldots ,m\).

\({H_{j}}\) are then defined exactly as \(G_{j}\) but adding an isolated vertice for every missing one in \(G_{j}\) up to n. \([G_{j},\alpha _j]\) are the monochrome graphs in Biobrane from which \([G,\alpha ]\) was constructed and \([H_{j},\beta _{j}]\) are defined from them satisfying the following conditions:

  • every \([H_{j},\beta _{j}]\) is monochromatic

  • every \([H_{j},\beta _{j}]\) has n vertices

  • m is the number of layers used to build and decompose \([G,\alpha ]\) by applications of \(\varvec{\odot }\) and \(\varvec{\cup }\) respectively

  • \(\left| \beta _{j}\right| +\left| \beta _{l}\right| < {\pi /2}\) for \(j,l=1,\ldots ,m\)

  • \(m_1+ \ldots +m_d=m\).

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Signorelli, C.M., Boils, J.D. Multilayer networks as embodied consciousness interactions. A formal model approach. Phenom Cogn Sci (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-024-09967-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-024-09967-w

Keywords

Navigation