Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Phenomenology: What’s AI got to do with it?

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Nowadays, philosophers and scientists tend to agree that, even though human and artificial intelligence work quite differently, they can still illuminate aspects of each other, and knowledge in one domain can inspire progress in the other. For instance, the notion of “artificial” or “synthetic” phenomenology has been gaining some traction in recent AI research. In this paper, we ask the question: what (if anything) is the use of thinking about phenomenology in the context of AI, and in particular machine learning? We will isolate one sense of “phenomenology”, namely the sense in which it is commonly understood within analytic philosophy of perception. Then, we will give examples of projects within sensory substitution and restoration science that rely heavily on machine learning and to which, according to us, phenomenology in the sense specified makes a relevant contribution. Finally, we will shed some light on what this contribution looks like and why it is important.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The hard problem of consciousness is contrasted with so-called “easy problems” of consciousness– the kinds of problems science currently has the resources (at least in principle) to explain.

  2. Although mechanistic explanation was traditionally associated with the rejection of functional (in particular, teleological) explanation, explanations in the psychological sciences are replete with functions and mechanisms working in tandem (Craver, 2013). The sorts of functions of interest to Cummins were specifically causal, rather than teleological or etiological functions, i.e. a la Millikan (1989) and Dretske (1988). Causal functions are determined by an analysis of what a system or phenomenon does with some containing system. Some mechanists defend the use of functional descriptions as they assist in the discovery of mechanisms (Bechtel, 2008; Craver, 2001). But mechanistic explanation is also both compatible with and aided by considerations of biological or etiological functions (Block, 1971; Craver, 2013; McClamrock, 1993).

  3. Some other philosophers however suggest that phenomenology has no role to play in individuating the senses (e.g. Keeley 2002).

  4. Though see Phillips (2018, 2020) for opposing arguments.

  5. The claim is not that the sensation itself is what makes the experience unpleasant. This is debatable (see e.g. Aydede & Fulkerson 2019). Rather, the claim is that the functional role of sensory affect requires a conscious sensation to which a valence is attached. In learning, for instance, the sensation is associated with some stimulus such that the affective response becomes associated with that stimulus. Conscious sensation thus has a role in explanations that call on sensory affect.

  6. However, those sympathetic with Kim (1992) might wield the causal exclusion argument and insist that sensory phenomenology is merely epiphenomenal, and thus it cannot itself be the cause or realizer of these functions. We have two lines of reply. The first is metaphysical: it’s not obvious that we should accept Kim’s causal exclusion argument. Several philosophers have appealed to Woodward’s interventionist account of causation to rebut the “master argument for epiphenomenalism” based on Kim’s causal exclusion argument (e.g. Rescorla 2014; Shapiro, 2010; Shapiro & Sober, 2007). We think such an appeal could be made to defend sensory phenomenology from an epiphenomenal fate, but we will not provide such a defense here. For now, it is sufficient to show that it is not a given that sensory phenomenology is epiphenomenal. The second line of reply is epistemological and brief. Even if it were to turn out that causal exclusion is irresistible, until sensory phenomenology has been successfully reduced, it will be necessary to appeal to it in explanations of behavior. Indeed, we will rely on sensory phenomenology in the tests we use to discover the neural basis of sensory phenomenology.

  7. For a recent discussion of whether SS devices should be understood as substituting or restoring the original sense modality, see Pence (2020).

References

  • Akins, K. (1996). Of Sensory Systems and the “Aboutness” of Mental States. The Journal of Philosophy, 93(7), 337–372. https://doi.org/10.2307/2941125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M., & Fulkerson, M. (2019). Reasons and Theories of Sensory Affect. In D. Bain, M. Brady, & J. Corns (Eds.), The Philosophy of Pain: Unpleasantness, Emotion, and Deviance. Routledge

  • Beavers, A. F. (2002). Phenomenology and artificial intelligence. Metaphilosophy, 33(1–2), 70–82. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9973.00217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. In Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. (pp. xiv, 286–xiv, 286). Princeton University Press

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. In Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. (pp. xiii, 308–xiii, 308). Taylor & Francis Group/Lawrence Erlbaum Associates

  • Bensemann, J., & Witbrock, M. (2021). The effects of implementing phenomenology in a deep neural network. Heliyon, 7(6), e07246–e07246. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.heliyon.2021.e07246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besold, T. R., Zaadnoordijk, L., & Vernon, D. (2021). Feeling Functional: A Formal Account of Artificial Phenomenology. Journal of Artificial Intelligence and Consciousness, 08(01), 147–160. https://doi.org/10.1142/s2705078521500077

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. J. (1971). Are Mechanistic and Teleological Explanations of Behaviour Incompatible? The Philosophical Quarterly, 21(83), 109–117. https://doi.org/10.2307/2218333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2019). Deep learning: A philosophical introduction. Philosophy Compass, 14(10), e12625. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2001). Intentionalism Defended. The Philosophical Review, 110(2), 199–240. https://doi.org/10.2307/2693675

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (4 vol.). Oxford University Press

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2006). Perception and the fall from Eden. In T. S. Gendler, & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford University Press

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2010). The Character of Consciousness. Oxford University Press

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2015). Outside Color: Perceptual Science and the Puzzle of Color in Perception. MIT press

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2017). Perceptual Pragmatism and the Naturalized Ontology of Color. Topics in Cognitive Science, 9(1), 151–171. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2018). Vision. In M. Sprevak, & M. Colombo (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Computational Mind. Routledge

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (50th ed.). The MIT Press. http://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt17kk81z

  • Coeckelbergh, M. (2011). Humans, animals, and robots: A phenomenological approach to human-robot relations. International Journal of Social Robotics, 3(2), 197–204. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12369-010-0075-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2001). Role Functions, Mechanisms, and Hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68. https://doi.org/10.1086/392866

  • Craver, C. F. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: a perspectivalist view. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Functions: Selection and Mechanisms. Springer

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis.Journal of Philosophy, 72(November)

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The Nature of Psychological Explanation (19 vol.). MIT Press. 3

  • Dennett, D. (2003). Who’s on first? Heterophenomenology explained. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2018). The fantasy of first-person science. The Map and the Territory (pp. 455–473). Springer

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. In Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. (pp. xi, 165–xi, 165). The MIT Press

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1972). What Computers Can’T Do: The Limits of Artificial Intelligence (27 vol.). Harper & Row. 2

  • Dreyfus, H. L., & Haugeland, J. (1974). The computer as a mistaken model of the mind. Philosophy Of Psychology. Macmillan

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1992). What Computers Still Can’T Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. MIT Press

  • Feyaerts, J., & Vanheule, S. (2017). The Logic of Appearance: Dennett, Phenomenology and Psychoanalysis. In Frontiers in Psychology (Vol. 8, p. 1437). https://www.frontiersin.org/article/https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01437

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The Language of Thought (87 vol.). Issue 1). Harvard University Press

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science (34 vol.). MIT Press. 2

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology (94 vol.). MIT Press. 1

  • Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548774.001.0001

  • Fulkerson, M. (2014). Rethinking the senses and their interactions: the case for sensory pluralism.Frontiers in Psychology, 5

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1998). Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature. Cambridge University Press. https://books.google.com/books?id=DI4_p8qQU9kC

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016). Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep Origins of Consciousness. Farrar, Straus and Giroux. https://books.google.com/books?id=CRNmDQAAQBAJ

  • Haugeland, J. (1985). Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea (38 vol.). Issue 151). MIT Press

  • Keeley, B. L. (2002). Making Sense of the Senses: Individuating Modalities in Humans and Other Animals. The Journal of Philosophy, 99(1), 5–28. https://doi.org/10.2307/3655759

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). The nonreductivist’s troubles with mental causation. In J. Heil, & A. R. Mele (Eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press

  • Kriegel, U. (2013). Phenomenal Intentionality. Philosophy of Mind Series. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199764297.001.0001

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms.Philosophy of Science, 67(1)

  • Macpherson, F. (2011a). Individuating the Senses. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The Senses: Classic and Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford University Press

  • Macpherson, F. (2011b). The Senses: Classic and Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford University Press USA

  • Macpherson, F. (2011c). Taxonomising the senses. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 153(1), 123–142. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41487620

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzotti, R., & Chella, A. (2018). Good Old-Fashioned Artificial Consciousness and the Intermediate Level Fallacy. In Frontiers in Robotics and AI (Vol. 5, p. 39). https://www.frontiersin.org/article/https://doi.org/10.3389/frobt.2018.00039

  • Matthen, M. (2015). The Individuation of the Senses. In M. Matthen (Ed.), Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception. Oxford University Press

  • McClamrock, R. (1993). Functional analysis and etiology. Erkenntnis, 38(2)

  • Meijer, P. (1992). An experimental system for auditory image representations. Biomedical Engineering IEEE Transactions On, 39, 112–121. https://doi.org/10.1109/10.121642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici, A. (2018). The Phenomenal Basis of Intentionality. Oxford University Press

  • Merikle, P. M., & Daneman, M. (1998). Psychological investigations of unconscious perception. In Journal of Consciousness Studies (Vol. 5, Issue 1, pp. 5–18). Imprint Academic

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). In Defense of Proper Functions. Philosophy of Science, 56(2), 288–302. https://doi.org/10.1086/289488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nudds, M. (2004). The Significance of the Senses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 31–51. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4545404

  • Nudds, M. (2007). The senses as psychological kinds. 1–34. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/1772

  • Nudds, M. (2009). Discriminating senses. The Philosophers’ Magazine, 45(45)

  • Phillips, I. (2018). Unconscious Perception Reconsidered. Analytic Philosophy, 59(4), 471–514. https://doi.org/10.1111/phib.12135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. (2020). Blindsight Is Qualitatively Degraded Conscious Vision. Psychological Review. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Port, A. A., Kim, C., & Patel, M. (2020). Deep Sensory Substitution: Noninvasively Enabling Biological Neural Networks to Receive Input from Artificial Neural Networks. https://arxiv.org/abs/2005.13291

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science. MIT Press

  • Rescorla, M. (2014). The Causal Relevance of Content to Computation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 173–208. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24673003

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A., & Sober, E. (2007). Epiphenomenalism - the do’s and the don “ts.”. In G. Wolters, & P. K. Machamer (Eds.), Thinking About Causes: From Greek Philosophy to Modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2010). Lessons from Causal Exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 594–604. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41057495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Springle, A. A. (2019). Methods, minds, memory, and kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 634–660. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2019.1607277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Springle, A. A., & Humphreys, J. (2021). Anti-intellectualism, instructive representations, and the intentional action argument. Synthese, 1–37. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03145-0

  • Tóth, V., & Parkkonen, L. (2019). Autoencoding sensory substitution. https://doi.org/10.13140/RG.2.2.10576.87048

  • Zaadnoordijk, L., & Besold, T. R. (2018). Artificial phenomenology for human-level artificial intelligence. CEUR Workshop Proceedings, 2287, 1–6

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alessandra Buccella.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Buccella, A., Springle, A. Phenomenology: What’s AI got to do with it?. Phenom Cogn Sci 22, 621–636 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09833-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09833-7

Keywords

Navigation