Skip to main content
Log in

Temporal experience in anxiety: embodiment, selfhood, and the collapse of meaning

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This essay explores the unique temporal experience in anxiety. Drawing on first-person accounts as well as examples from literature, I attempt to show how anxiety not only disrupts our physiological and cognitive timing but also disturbs the embodied rhythms of everyday social life. The primary goal, however, is to articulate the extent to which human existence itself is a temporally structured event and to identity the ways that anxiety disrupts this structure. Using Martin Heidegger’s account of human existence (or Dasein) as a point of departure, I show how the mood of anxiety has the power to alter our self-interpretations by closing down or constricting our experience of the future. I argue that a constricted future impedes our ability ‘to be’ because it closes off the range of projective meanings that we would ordinarily draw on to create or fashion our identities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The pervasive co-occurrence of depression and anxiety means that temporal acceleration and retardation can occur simultaneously in the same individual. As one woman writes, “It’s like I’m in a fog and can’t fully concentrate. My words are slurred and I feel like I’m in a dream… I feel extra slow like I’m moving in slow motion, but at the same time I can’t hold still. My thoughts are scattered, yet I can’t put them into words… I get nervous to talk to co-workers because I just know my words will come out faster than my brain can put it together to make sense.” (Schuster 2017) This is one of the many reasons that the DSM’s separation of the disorders into two distinct categories is highly problematic. Anxiety and depression not only share common physiological characteristics, hereditary factors, and genetic etiologies (e.g. the production of neurotransmitters such as serotonin and dopamine); they generally respond to comparable pharmacological and psychotherapeutic treatments and have symptomatic similarities, especially in regards to feelings of guilt, shame, and loss of self-control. To this end, I agree with Scott Stossell (2015) who suggests, “The dividing line between this set of disorders… seems to be an artifact as much of politics and culture (and marketing) as of science.” (p. 40)

  2. As a DSM criteria for generalized anxiety disorder, this cognitive impairment may contribute to, among other thing, ‘irritability’, ‘sleep disturbances’, ‘difficulty concentrating’ and ‘[the] mind going blank’ (American Psychiatric Association 2013, 222)

  3. Interestingly, in Being and Time, Heidegger identifies this aspect of public life in terms ‘curiosity’ (Neugier), referring to a pervasive sense of ‘restlessness’ (Unruhe). (1962, 216) He sees it as being symptomatic of the larger socio-cultural upheavals of modernity, where technologically mediated speed, busy-ness, and distractibility creates a situation of chronic sensory arousal and time pressure where “Dasein “never [dwells] anywhere… [and is] constantly uprooting itself.” (p. 217) He will later refer to it as ‘acceleration’ (Schnelligkeit), identifying it as one of the signature features of modernity embodied in a kind of ‘mania’ where “one is unable to bear the stillness” of their own lives. (1999, 83; cf. Aho 2007)

  4. In § 49 of Being and Time, Heidegger makes it clear that ‘dying’ (Sterben) refers to an inability ‘to be’. It is not to be confused with ‘perishing’ (Verenden) or ‘demising’ (Ableben). Verenden refers to the physiological death of the kind we share with animals, and Ableben refers to the uniquely human anxiety that accompanies the subjective awareness of our impending physiological perishing. Sterben, on the other hand, refers to the dying of our ability to exist, that is, to understand or make sense of who we are. This is an event that belongs to the temporal structure Dasein itself. Our identity or self-understanding, on this view, is fragile and always vulnerable to collapse. (cf. Aho 2016; Blattner 1994; Thomson 2013)

  5. As Freeman (2000) explains, “There can be no story without an ending, and there can be no ending without a story.” (p. 88)

  6. Although it is beyond the scope of this paper, it is important to note that this longing for narrative stability emerges not just at the temporal but at the spatial, bodily, and intersubjective level as well. The experience of anxiety can disrupt our sense of “ontological security” (Laing 1960), that is, our unconscious and taken for granted state of being ‘at home’, of being habitually integrated, engaged, and bound up in the world. On this view, my identity and experience of reality as a whole is largely held together by this pre-reflective, embodied connection. The erosion of the self emerges when this connection breaks down and the public world reveals itself as unreliable, insecure, and, in severe cases, ‘unreal’. (cf. Aho 2014, 126–132)

References

  • Aho, K. (2007). Acceleration and time pathologies. Time and society, 16(1), 25–42.

  • Aho, K. (2009). Heidegger’s neglect of the body. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aho, K. (2014). Existentialism: An introduction. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aho, K. (2016). Heidegger, ontological death, and the healing professions. Medicine, Healthcare, and Philosophy, 19(1), 55–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aho, K., & Guignon, C. (2011). Medicalized psychiatry and the talking cure: A hermeneutic intervention. Human studies: a journal for philosophy and the social sciences, 34, 293–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2000). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 4thedition, text revised. Washington: American Psychiatric Assocation.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Washington: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blattner, W. (1994). The concept of death in being and time. Man and World, 27, 49–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carver, R. (1998). Where I’m calling from: Selected stories. New York: Atlantic Monthly Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenreich, B. (2009). Bright-sided: How positive thinking is undermining America. New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, M. (2000). When the story’s over: Narrative foreclosure and the possibility of self-renewal. In M. Andrews, S. Day Sclater, C. Squire, & A. Treacher (Eds.), Lines of narrative: Psychosocial perspectives. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2003). The phenomenology of shame, guilt, and the body in body dysmorphic disorder and depression. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 33(2), 223–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2005). The phenomenology of the body space and time in depression. Comprendre, 15, 108–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2006). Implicit and explicit temporality. Philosophy, psychiatry, and. Psychology, 12(3), 195–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2010). Temporality and psychopathology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-010-9189-4

  • Gadamer, H. G. (1996). The enigma of health, trans. J. Gaiger and N. Walker. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, C. (1984). Moods in Heidegger’s Being and Time. In R. Solomon & C. Calhoun (Eds.), What is an emotion? Classic and contemporary readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, C. (1993). Authenticity, moral values, and psychotherapy. In C. Guignon (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: Harper and Row.

  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Nietzsche volume I: The will to power as art, trans. D. F. Krell. New York: HarperCollins.

  • Heidegger, M. (1982). Basic problems of phenomenology, trans. A. Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (1992). The concept of time, trans. W. McNeill. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). Basic writings. D.F. Krell (Ed.) New York: HarperCollins.

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). Fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude, trans. W. McNeill and N. Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger. (1999). Contributions to philosophy: From enowning, trans. P. Emad and K. Maly. Bloomington: Indiana University Press

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Zollikon Seminars, trans. F. Mayr and R. Askay. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Hosseini, K. (2013). The kite runner. New York: Riverhead Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl. E. 1966. The phenomenology of internal time consciousness, trans. J. Churchill. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Karp, D. (1996). Speaking of sadness: Depression, disconnection, and the meanings of illness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laing, R. D. (1960). The divided self: A study of sanity and madness. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, R. (1997). A geography of time. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin Wyllie (2005) Live Time and Psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 12(3), 173-185.

  • Minkowski, E. (1970). Lived time: Phenomenological and psychopathological studies. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piguet, C., et al. 2009. Phenomenology of racing and crowded thoughts in mood disorders: A theoretical appraisal. Journal of affective disorders. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.Jad.2009.05.006.

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2002). Heidegger’s attunement and the neuropsychology of emotion. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 287–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2012). Varieties of temporal experience in depression. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(2), 114–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M., Ruddell, M., & Smith, B. (2014). What is a ‘sense of foreshortened future?’: A phenomenological study of trauma, trust, and time. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1026. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, S. (2017). 33 subtle ways anxiety affects your daily life. In The mightyRetrieved from https://themighty.com/2017/01/how-anxiety-affects-daily-life/

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, P. (1988). Discerning the subject. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanghellini, G., & Rosfort, R. (2013). Emotions and personhood: Exploring fragility—Making sense of vulnerability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stossell, S. (2015). My age of anxiety: Fear, hope, dread, and the search for peace of mind. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, E. (1966). Phenomenological psychopathology. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Styron, W. (2007). Darkness visible: A memoir of madness. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. (2011). Illness as unhomelike being-in-the-world: Heidegger and the phenomenology of medicine. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy, 14(3), 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, I. (2013). Death and demise in being and time. In M. Wrathall (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Heidegger’s being and time (pp. 260–290). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ulmer, D., & Schwartzburd, L. (1996). Heart and mind: The practice of cardiac psychology. Washington: American Psychological Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. F. (2004). Oblivion: Stories. New York: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. F. (2006). Consider the lobster: And other essays. New York: Little, Brown and Company.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin Aho.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Aho, K. Temporal experience in anxiety: embodiment, selfhood, and the collapse of meaning. Phenom Cogn Sci 19, 259–270 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9559-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-018-9559-x

Keywords

Navigation