Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Merleau-Ponty on human development and the retrospective realization of potential

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay, I propose that human development is the emergence of something significantly new out of a past situation that does not hold that novel achievement as a determinate potential except retrospectively. Development, in other words, might best be understood as a “realization” in the sense of a making-real of some new form of being that had no prior place in reality, that was not programmed in advance, but that once realized can have its roots traced back to determinate conditions and potentials in its own past. This amounts to a rethinking of the nature of developmental potential as retrospectively determined. But it also involves a reconception of the locus of such potential: I argue that developmental potential must be understood as located in the human-organism-in-its-situation, rather than simply in the human organism. I take my bearings from phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and I make my case by elucidating three different forms of human development described by Merleau-Ponty: intellectual realizations of insight; the realization of a new perceptual-motor skill; and a child’s realization of a new lived way of making sense of the interpersonal world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We can see this in Merleau-Ponty’s study of animal learning (1963), his exploration of child development (1964a, 1973, 1988), his lectures on institution (2003), his interest in the creativity of artistic and linguistic expression (2012, 1993a, b), his accounts of the human development of sensory, perceptual and motor habits, human adaptations to disturbances in experience and bodily functioning, and intellectual insights (2012), and, towards the end of his career, his study of the emergence of new forms of living being within nature (1995).

  2. See, for example, Merleau-Ponty’s claim that “Neither empiricism nor intellectualism grasp consciousness in the act of learning” (2012, 30). Though he asserts this in the context of a particular argument and concerning conscious learning alone, this essay seeks to show how, if we think through Merleau-Ponty’s thoughts, we find that the same retrospective logic at work in conscious learning is also at work in the bodily learning involved in sensorimotor development, and the existential learning involved in emotional and linguistic development.

  3. Plato, Meno, 80d–e.

  4. I will refer to Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception (2012) with ‘PhP,’ putting the French pagination first, the English translation pagination second.

  5. Merleau-Ponty describes this retrospective illusion in relation to our understanding of perception in multiple places, including the Structure of Behaviour, 217–20 (I will henceforth refer to this text as SB). Indeed, the acknowledgement of this retrospective illusion, which consists in taking the determinate results of a process, or what unfolds from that process, to have been there all along, as the cause of that process, is arguably at the basis of the overarching argument of the Phenomenology of Perception and of Merleau-Ponty’s texts on artistic expression and childhood development.

  6. This is a conclusion for which Merleau-Ponty repeatedly argues. It is one of the central conclusions, for instance, of the chapter on reflex behavior in The Structure of Behavior, and of the chapters “The Spatiality of One’s Own Body and Motricity,” “Sensing,” “Space,” “The Thing and the Natural World” in the Phenomenology of Perception, and of his lecture course entitled “Le monde sensible et le monde de l’expression.

  7. Merleau-Ponty emphasizes this point in The Visible and the Invisible, 133.

  8. This is a point central to the account of perception articulated by James J. Gibson, in The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception.

  9. Compare the effects of pink on violent and aggressive behaviour. Schauss (1979) reports a study wherein subjects show less strength in their arms when looking at pink. He also reports an experiment done by his students, Baker and Miller, involving painting a prison holding cell pink: the pink seems to have reduced or eliminated initial violent behaviour within the cell; this tactic was then used in other jails and delinquent youth centres (sp. Santa Clara County Jail and Kuiper Youth Center). In The Power of Color, Walker (1991, especially chapter 3) reports similar studies and phenomena, including the significant reduction of suicides resulting from painting green a bridge that was black.

  10. Merleau-Ponty notes how there is a retrospective illusion (though he does not name it as such) that accompanies color sensation, with the result that several psychological accounts have assumed that the child must be seeing green, even if she is unable to distinguish it. That is, because green seems so immediately given to the psychologist, she cannot imagine “a world in which colors are indeterminate.” What psychologists must come to see, according to Merleau-Ponty, is that the emergence of the infant from an experience of indeterminacy to an experience of determinate colours, “[t]he first perception of colors, properly so called, is … a change in the structure of consciousness, the institution of a new dimension of experience…” and this new structure is what makes the identity of the color “before and after” its institution appear (PhP, 54/32, emphasis added). The new structure of experience makes it seem retrospectively as if the green had always been there.

  11. Uexküll (1957) vividly makes the point that what we perceive is a function of our bodily resources and what the environment offers. Thompson (1995) makes this same point in relation to colour, in particular. Merleau-Ponty takes this further by emphasizing the active motor response that is required to bring colour into its determinacy for us.

  12. Thelen and Smith (1996) show, in their book A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action, how a multitude of independent developments converge, or interact dynamically, in order to bring about various new forms of action and cognition.

  13. Merleau-Ponty discusses this in the Structure of Behavior (SB, 40–41). It is based on a study initially done by Fuchs (1920, 1922) and taken up and discussed by Kurt Goldstein (1934/2000, 56–58; and 1923).

  14. Merleau-Ponty cites a (disturbing) third study that also demonstrates how the body improvisationally reorganizes itself in order to solve an unexpected problem posed by the animal’s basic project and its lack of bodily resources. In this case (SB, 40), an animal loses use of its right front limb for seizing food after the partial excision of the relevant cerebral region; it then substitutes its left limb. When, however, the left limb is amputated it regains use of its right limb. If the relevant cerebral region for the right limb is fully excised, the animal can still use its right limb when the situation makes it imperative. In other words, the animal’s bodily functioning is not pre-programmed, but reorganizes itself in light of the task that it encounters, and the systems that are most open to being drawn into the service of resolving the problem encountered.

  15. Certain constraints are set by the organism’s genetic inheritance, so that a tick, for instance, will not develop retinal vision just because there are things that could be seen. But these constraints do not amount to fully determinate potentials; they are rather a relative openness to developing in ways that are responsive to, and that help to determine, the particular environment in which the creature finds itself. Geneticist Richard Lewontin offers a criticism of genetic determinism, or the idea that genes are the one cause at the root of biological development, in his book Biology as Ideology.

  16. I will make reference to this text (1964a) as “CRO.”

  17. The article that initially catches Merleau-Ponty’s attention is by François Rostand (1950). Rostand is, however, himself reflecting upon a case-study reported by Françoise Dolto-Marette (1947). My description of the case-study draws on all these texts.

  18. Fogel and Thelen (1987) make a similar argument, from the dynamic systems perspective, that the development of early expressive and communicative action is not a matter of a development written in advance into the ontogeny of an isolatable infant, but rather of the infant-in-a-typically-supportive-social-situation.

  19. This response is itself an example of a “retrospective illusion”: because Robert’s parents can see clearly that Robert does have a place in the world, and that he has not been usurped but rather occupies his own valuable position relative to his sister, they assume that Robert must be able to see this too. Their own clarity gives the illusion that this “fact” is inherently clear, and they cannot understand Robert’s behavior as a kind of blind, confused groping for an answer to the indeterminate tension he feels. I have written in more detail about the differences between Gricha’s and Robert’s environments in “Emotional Metamorphoses” (2009).

References

  • Blakemore, C. (1976). The conditions required for the maintenance of binocularity in the kitten’s visual cortex. Journal of Physiology, 261, 423–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, C., & Cooper, G. F. (1970). Development of the brain depends on the visual environment. Nature, 228, 477–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, E., & Cornelissen, F. W. (2005). A way of selectively degrading colour constancy demonstrates the experience dependence of colour vision. Current Biology, 15(21), R864–R866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bushnell, E. W., & Paul Boudreau, J. (1993). Motor development and the mind: The potential role of motor abilities as a determinant of aspects of perceptual development. Child Development, 64(4), 1005–1021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1946/1994). The idea of history. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cynader, M., Garry C. (1976) “Aolition of direction selectivity in the visual cortex of the cat. Science, 193, 504–505. doi:10.1007/s11097-017-9519-x.

  • Dolto-Marette, Françoise. (1947). Hypothèse nouvelle concernant les réactions dites de jalousie à la naissance d’un puîné. Psyché 7 524–530 and 8(1947):788–798.

  • Fogel, A., Esther, T. (1987) Development of early expressive and communicative action: reinterpreting the evidence from a dynamic systems perspective. Developmental Psychology, 23(6), 747–761.

  • Fuchs, W. (1920). In A. Gelb & K. Goldstein (Eds.), Eine Pseudofovea bei Hemianopikern. In Psychologische Analysen Hirnpathologischer Fälle. Untersuchungen über das Sehen der Hemianopiker. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological Approach to visual perception. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, K. (1923). "Zur Frage der Restitution nach umschriebenem Hirndefekte." Schweizer Archiv für Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 13, 283-296.

  • Goldstein, K. (1939/2000). The organism: A holistic Approach to Biology derived from pathological data in man. New York: Zone Books.

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1991/2003). Biology as ideology: The doctrine of DNA (CBC Massey lectures). Toronto: House of Anansi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaren, Kym. (2009). Emotional Metamorphoses: The Role of Others in Becoming-Oneself. Embodiment and Agency: New Essays in Feminist Philosophy, edited by Susan Sherwin, Letitia Meynell, and Sue Campbell. Pennsylvania State University Press,: 1–45.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). The Structure of Behavior (trans: Alden fisher). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964a). The Child’s Relations with Others (trans: William cobb). In J. Edie (Ed.), The primacy of perception (pp. 96–158). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964b). Le Visible et l’invisible. Posthumous text established by Claude Lefort. Saint-Amand: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964c). The philosopher and his shadow. In Signs (trans: Richard C. McCleary). Evanston: Northwestern University Press, pp. 159-181.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the invisible. Edited by Claude Lefort (trans: Alphonso Lingis). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1973). Consciousness and the Acquisition of Language (trans: Hugh J. Silverman). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1988). Structure et conflits de la conscience enfantine. In In Merleau-Ponty à la Sorbonne: Résumé de cours 1949–1952. Dijon-Quetigny: Cynara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1993a). Cézanne’s Doubt. In G. A. Johnson (Ed.), The Merleau-Ponty aesthetics reader: Philosophy and painting (pp. 59–75). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1993b). Indirect language and the voices of silence. In G. A. Johnson (Ed.), The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics reader: Philosophy and painting (pp. 76–120). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1995). In D. Séglard (Ed.), La Nature: Notes, Cours du Collège de France. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). L’Institution, la passivité: notes de cours au Collège de France (1954–1955). Tours: Editions Belin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Institution and Passivity: Course Notes from the Collège de France (1954–1955) (trans: Lawlor, Leonard and Massey, heath. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of Perception (trans: Don Landes). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1981). Meno. In Five Dialogues (trans: G.M.A. Grube). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

  • Rauschecker, J. P., & Singer, W. (1981). The effects of early visual experience on the cat’s visual cortex and their possible explanation by Hebb synapses. Journal of Physiology, 310, 215–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rostand, F. (1950). Grammaire et affectivité. Revue française de la psychanalyse, 14, 299–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauss, A. G. (1979). Tranquilizing effect of color reduces aggressive behavior and potential violence. Orthomolecular Psychiatry, 8(4), 218–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soska, K. C., Karen E. A., Scott P. J. (2010) Systems in development: motor skill acquisition facilitates 3D object completion. Developmental Psychology, 46(1), 129–138.

  • Sugita, Y. (2004). Experience in early infancy is indispensable for color perception. Current Biology, 14, 1267–1271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994/1996). A dynamic systems Approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Thompson, E. (1995). Colour vision: A study in cognitive science and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, Jakob. (1957) A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In Instinctive Behavior: The development of a modern concept, translated and edited by Claire H. Schiller, 5–80. New York:International Universities Press.

  • Walker, M. (1991). The power of color. New York: Avery Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kym Maclaren.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Maclaren, K. Merleau-Ponty on human development and the retrospective realization of potential. Phenom Cogn Sci 16, 609–621 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9519-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9519-x

Keywords

Navigation