Skip to main content
Log in

How does it really feel to act together? Shared emotions and the phenomenology of we-agency

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Research on the phenomenology of agency for joint action has so far focused on the sense of agency and control in joint action, leaving aside questions on how it feels to act together. This paper tries to fill this gap in a way consistent with the existing theories of joint action and shared emotion. We first reconstruct Pacherie’s (Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13, 25–46, 2014) account on the phenomenology of agency for joint action, pointing out its two problems, namely (1) the necessary trade-off between the sense of self- and we-agency; and (2) the lack of affective phenomenology of joint action in general. After elaborating on these criticisms based on our theory of shared emotion, we substantiate the second criticism by discussing different mechanisms of shared affect—feelings and emotions—that are present in typical joint actions. We show that our account improves on Pacherie’s, first by introducing our agentive model of we-agency to overcome her unnecessary dichotomy between a sense of self- and we-agency, and then by suggesting that the mechanisms of shared affect enhance not only the predictability of other agents’ actions as Pacherie highlights, but also an agentive sense of we-agency that emerges from shared emotions experienced in the course and consequence of joint action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout the paper we use the term “agency for joint action” to refer to the general idea of agency which is distinct from individual agency. One may well use “collective agency”, “joint agency” or “shared agency” instead, but the important point is that the term is not dependent on any specific theory of non-individual agency.

  2. Tollefsen’s (2014) brief account of the sense of joint control in joint action is similar to Pacherie’s sense of agency for joint outcomes in that it builds on a perceived match between the predicted and actual effects of agency for joint action. The difference is that Tollefsen relates the sense of joint control functionally to controlling and monitoring joint action, whereas for Pacherie, the phenomenology of we-agency is interesting in its own right.

  3. Feelings and emotions are types of “affect” that we, following a wide interdisciplinary consensus in philosophy, psychology, and sociology, use as an umbrella term for phenomenal states with certain valence and intensity. Emotions are felt evaluative responses to specific objects and events and they motivate the subject to act in accordance with evaluative content of the emotion; to fight or flee in danger, to retaliate or retribute when offended, to hide in shame, and so on. Feelings can be part of emotion, and they can be experienced as bodily sensations or intentional feelings directed at the particular object of emotion or as both kinds of feelings at the same time. However, not all feelings such as rapport or alienation are part of emotions. Thus when we speak about “shared affects”, we refer to shared emotions or shared feelings or both. The notion of affect has a different meaning in the so called “affect theory” that is prevalent in cultural, media, and gender studies (see e.g. Gregg and Seigworth 2010).

  4. A possible philosophical worry about Pacherie’s -- as well as our -- project is that it is indeterminate until it is clarified whether the concept of “we” in “we-agency” refers to a distributed or a non-distributed “we” (see e.g. Bratman 2014). An example of the former could be a group of students from different schools celebrating their graduation on the same day, whereas a group of team members celebrating the victory of their team could exemplify the latter kind of “we”. Pacherie does not raise this question in her discussion for good reasons, we think. First of all, a theoretically pre-defined “we” may not be salient in the phenomenology of we-agency that purposefully avoids theory-laden accounts of experience. Second, a sharp dichotomy between a distributed and non-distributed “we” may be false in paradigm experiences of we-agency as these may combine a robust sense of self-agency with that of we-agency, as we will argue in what follows.

  5. In interpreting the results of the limited empirical studies on the relation between self-agency and we-agency, Pacherie (2014, 38–39) warns against identifying we-agency with pre-reflective cognitive processes that are immune to conscious top-down influence. This cautious note implies that she is thinking of the sense of we-agency as something individuals can (at least sometimes) reflectively experience and exert top-down influence on. If this is the case, then the loss of self-other agential boundary seems too strong a condition for her own account of the sense of we-agency.

  6. Although some theorists attribute intentions to groups in addition to their members, they all admit that groups act only through their members. Gilbert (2014) for example argues that the participants of joint action are jointly committed to constituting, as far as possible, a single subject of action. Yet this only amounts to the parties’ being jointly committed to emulating, by virtue of their actions, a single subject of action.

  7. Her recent paper with John Michael (Michael and Pacherie 2015, p. 107) touches upon this issue in discussing moral sentiments and emotions as an automatic process to reduce uncertainty and achieve cooperation in social dilemma situations. The focus of that paper however is not phenomenological but functional.

  8. There are other philosophical theories of shared emotions, most notably those of Gilbert (2002), Schmid (2009), and Huebner (2011). For a discussion and critique of the former two, see Salmela (2012).

  9. The appraisal process need not be collective though it can be in some cases, such as when an emotional appraisal is formed as a result of public discussion (see Halperin 2014). More typically, though, emotional appraisals are so fast and modular that it is impossible to make let alone commit oneself to them collectively (but see Gilbert 2002, 2014).

  10. The idea of emotions having reasons may strike one as strange. However, the idea that emotions have both justifying and motivating reasons is widely accepted in contemporary philosophy of emotions and metaethics (e.g. Greenspan 1988; D’Arms and Jacobson 2000; Helm 2008; Brady 2011). Emotions have justifying reasons as they are liable to evaluation in terms of appropriateness like other intentional attitudes. For instance, my fear is appropriate if the object of my fear has properties that render it capable of inflicting significant harm on me. Justifying reasons of shared emotions may refer to collectively accepted attitudes of a group, such as its values, goals, or intentions. The same group attitudes may also serve as motivating reasons of shared emotions. Since emotions are not under voluntary control, there can be no deliberation on reasons to feel in the same way as there is deliberation on reasons to act. However, we can talk about reasons (rather than mere causes) of emotion because human emotions are not reflexes or fixed action patterns but flexible responses to cognitively processed situational meanings.

  11. Schmid’s two examples of shared feelings with a phenomenological fusion serve as evidence for this worry. His first example are parents who grieve over the death of their beloved child. The parents share a concern for the child and its well-being in a jointly committed sense that emerges from their love for the child as parents and their reciprocal affective ties as a couple. The second example is joy at the first performance of a symphony, shared by all participants of the event, including the audience, members of the orchestra, the composer, and the stage manager. All participants share a concern about the success of the performance but in significantly different roles. The musicians have jointly committed themselves to offering an excellent performance, whereas the audience has not committed itself to anything; its role amounts to attentive listening at most. Therefore, if a successful performance elicits shared joy with a phenomenological fusion of feelings among everyone present, as Schmid suggests, the emotions of the participants are significantly dissimilar to each other in terms of the underlying concerns, unlike in the case of the grieving parents.

  12. For a more thorough theoretical account on the elicitation of shared emotions, see von Scheve and Ismer (2013).

  13. Existing studies on affective synchrony focus on face-to-face interaction, and there is a lacuna in the understanding of the kind of processes that contribute to the synchronization of individual emotions in computer-mediated, linguistic and symbolic communication insofar as synchronization occurs in these contexts. Therefore, we treat the better understood emotional sharing in face-to-face interaction as a paradigm case in our analysis.

  14. Shared emotions of this kind may not be collectively intentional as they lack a shared intentional object and an underlying shared concern. However, we would not go so far as to deny that these emotions are collective or shared in any sense. Empirical studies of shared or collective or group emotions generally do not distinguish between these importantly dissimilar types of shared emotions even if their social consequences can differ significantly, as we argue in Salmela and Nagatsu 2016.

References

  • Bourgois, P., & Hess, U. (2008). The impact of social context on mimicry. Biological Psychology, 77, 343–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. (2011). Emotions, perceptions, and reasons. In C. Bagnoli (Ed.), Morality and the emotions (pp. 135–149). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (2014). Shared agency. A planning theory of acting together. New York: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chartrand, T. L., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). The chameleon effect: the perception-behavior link and social interaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 893–910.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, R. (2004). Interaction ritual chains. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, R. (2014). Interaction ritual chains and collective effervescence. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 299–311). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). Sentiment and value. Ethics, 110, 722–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J., & Meyer, M. (2008). From emotion resonance to empathic understanding: a social developmental neuroscience account. Development and Psychopathology, 20, 1053–1080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (2001[1912]). The elementary forms of religious life. A new translation by C. Cosman. Abridged with an introduction and notes by M.S. Cladis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Fowler, C. A., Richardson, M. J., Kerry, L. M., & Shockley, K. D. (2008). Language use, coordination, and the emergence of cooperative action. In A. Fuchs & V. Jirsa (Eds.), Coordination: Neural, behavioral and social dynamics (pp. 261–279). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2002). Collective guilt and collective guilt feelings. The Journal of Ethics, 6, 115–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2003). The structure of the social atom: Joint commitment as the foundation of human social behavior. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics (pp. 39–64). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2014). Joint commitment: How we make the social world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godman, M. (2013). Why we do things together: the social motivation for joint action. Philosophical Psychology, 26, 588–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godman, M., Nagatsu, M., & Salmela, M. (2014). The social motivation hypothesis of prosocial behavior. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44, 563–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1988). Emotions and reasons. An inquiry into emotional justification. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregg, M., & Seigworth, G. J. (Eds.). (2010). The affect theory reader. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halperin, E. (2014). Collective emotions and emotion regulation in intractable conflicts. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 281–295). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J., & Rapson, R. (1994). Emotional contagion. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. (2008). Plural agents. Noûs, 42, 17–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hess, U., Houde, S., & Fischer, A. (2014). Do we mimic what we see or what we know? In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 94–107). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hove, M. J., & Risen, J. L. (2009). It’s all in the timing: interpersonal synchrony increases affiliation. Social Cognition, 27, 949–960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. (2011). Genuinely collective emotions. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1, 89–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, S., & Tomasello, M. (2010). Joint music making promotes prosocial behavior in 4-year-old children. Evolution and Human Behavior, 31, 354–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knottnerus, J.D. (2010). Collective events, rituals, and emotions. In S.R. Thye & E.J. Lawler (Eds.), Advances in group processes (vol. 27, pp. 39–62). Bingley: Emerald Publishing.

  • Lakin, J. L., Jefferis, V. E., Cheng, C. M., & Chartrand, T. L. (2003). The chameleon effect as social glue: evidence for the evolutionary significance of nonconscious mimicry. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior, 27, 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambie, J. A., & Marcel, A. J. (2002). Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: a theoretical framework. Psychological Review, 109, 219–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. J. (2001). An affect theory of social exchange. American Journal of Sociology, 107, 321–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. J., Thye, S. R., & Yoon, J. (2008). Social exchange and micro social order. American Sociological Review, 73, 519–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. J., Thye, S. R., & Yoon, J. (2009). Social commitments in a depersonalized world. New York: Russell Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, E. J., Thye, S. R., & Yoon, J. (2014). The emergence of collective emotions in social exchange. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 189–203). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, J. (2011). Shared emotion and joint action. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 355–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, J., & Pacherie, E. (2015). On commitments and other uncertainty reduction tools in joint action. Journal of Social Ontology, 1(1), 89–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miles, L. K., Nind, L. K., & Macrae, N. (2009). The rhythm of rapport. Interpersonal coordination and social perception. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, 585–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2012). The phenomenology of joint action: Self-agency vs. joint-agency. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint Attention: New developments (pp. 343–389). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2014). How does it feel to act together? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13, 25–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, B., Fischer, A., & Manstead, A. (2005). Emotions in social relations. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddish, P., Fischer, R., & Bulbulia, J. (2013). Let’s dance together: synchrony, shared intentionality, and cooperation. PLoS ONE, 8(8), e71182. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0071182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rimé, B. (2007). Interpersonal emotion regulation. In J. J. Gross (Ed.), Handbook of emotion regulation (pp. 466–485). New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, M. (2012). Shared emotions. Philosophical Explorations, 15, 33–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, M. (2013). The functions of collective emotions in social groups. In: H.B. Schmid and A. Konzelmann Ziv (Eds.), Institutions, emotions, and group agents. Springer Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality (vol. 2, pp. 159–176). Berlin: Springer.

  • Salmela, M., & Nagatsu, M. (2016). Collective emotions and joint action: beyond received and minimalist approaches. Journal of Social Ontology, 2, 33–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H.B. (2009). Plural action. Essays in philosophy and social science. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol. 58. Berlin: Springer.

  • Shockley, K., Richardson, D. C., & Dale, R. (2009). Conversation and coordinative structures. Topics in Cognitive Science, 1, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (2002 [1759]). The theory of moral sentiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Sugden, R. (2002). Beyond sympathy and empathy: Adam Smith’s concept of fellow-feeling. Economics and Philosophy, 18, 63–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Summers-Effler, E. (2007). Ritual theory. In J. E. Stets & J. H. Turner (Eds.), Handbook of the sociology of emotions (pp. 135–154). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. (2014). A dynamic theory of shared intention and the phenomenology of joint action. In S. R. Chant, F. Hindriks, & G. Preyer (Eds.), From individual to collective intentionality. New essays (pp. 13–33). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007). The philosophy of sociality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology. Collective intentionality and group agency. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Baaren, R. B., Holland, R. W., Kawakami, K., & van Knippenberg, A. (2004). Mimicry and prosocial behavior. Psychological Science15, 71–74.

  • Vikhoff, B., Malmgren, H., Åström, R., Nyberg, G., Ekström, S.-R., Engwall, M., Snygg, J., Nilsson, M., & Jörnsten, R. (2013). Music structure determines heart rate variability of singers. Frontiers in Psychology, 4(334), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Scheve, C., & Ismer, S. (2013). Towards a theory of collective emotions. Emotion Review, 5, 406–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiltermuth, S. S., & Heath, C. (2009). Synchrony and cooperation. Psychological Science, 20, 1–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2015). You, me and we—the sharing of emotional experiences. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22, 84–101.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Elisabeth Pacherie, John Michael, Hans Bernhard Schmid, Michael Schmitz, and two anonymous reviewers of this journal as well as the audience at the Philosophy of Science seminar, University of Helsinki, Sep 21, 2015 for their insightful and constructive comments to earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michiru Nagatsu.

Additional information

Mikko Salmela and Michiru Nagatsu contributed equally to this work.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Salmela, M., Nagatsu, M. How does it really feel to act together? Shared emotions and the phenomenology of we-agency. Phenom Cogn Sci 16, 449–470 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9465-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9465-z

Keywords

Navigation