Skip to main content
Log in

The origin of agency, consciousness, and free will

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Living organisms appear to have agency, the ability to act freely, and humans appear to have free will, the ability to rationally decide what to do. However, it is not clear how such properties can be produced by naturalistic processes, and there are indeed neuroscientific measurements that cast doubt on the existence of free will. Here I present a naturalistic theory of agency, consciousness, and free will. Elementary forms of agency evolved very early in the evolution of life, utilizing an extension of the basic Darwinian scheme that combines and entangles deterministic and stochastic causation. The extension effectively produces an active form of causation, as well as meaning intrinsic to the organism. Consciousness arose when animals evolved advanced nervous systems and social lifestyles that enabled communication mutually affecting each animal’s intrinsic meaning. I argue that various forms of agency that subsequently arose in evolution, preconscious, conscious, intelligent, symbolic, and rational agency, still coexist in humans. This coexistence, combined with the fact that agency is not instantaneous but takes time to build up, makes simple interpretations of neuroscientific results on free will (taken here as rational, symbolic agency) problematic. The conclusion of the study is that conscious free will, including a form of agent causation, is fully consistent with a naturalistic world-view and can be produced by the specific processes discussed. The result closely resembles existing approaches to life and mind that are inspired by phenomenology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terms ‘feedback’ and ‘feedback loop’ are used in this article in the technical sense as any kind of cyclic, circular, or mutual causation, and not as denoting only stabilizing (negative) feedback.

  2. It is sometimes assumed that neuronal systems are (primarily) deterministic systems. However, in practice neurons and neuronal systems display a considerable level of stochasticity, both at the neuronal and behavioural level (Faisal et al. 2008), and indeed a major effort in neurobiological experiments consists of separating signal from noise.

  3. For readers who like to think in mathematical terms, the following may help. The transformation proposed here roughly corresponds to the difference between addition and multiplication. If d and s stand for deterministic and stochastic factors, respectively, then d + s could be either primarily deterministic or primarily stochastic, depending on the size of d and s. But in d × s it would be impossible to say which factor is the more (or only) important one. E.g., in 123 + 5 one might neglect 5, but in 123 × 5 neglecting 5 would make no sense. The modulated stochastic causation of Fig. 1c is in fact a multiplicative interaction of deterministic and stochastic factors. The final result in Fig. 1d is obviously further complicated by the feedback cycle, the evolutionary drive, the time-varying environment, and the retention of changes in the organism (through its state and learning).

  4. For example in the work of Merleau-Ponty (discussed in de Preester 2003, pp. 201–202), in the work of Damasio with its emphasis on homeostasis as implicitly valuable to the organism, e.g. “the extension and transfer of homeostatic goals to objects and situations that become imbued with biological value” (Damasio and Carvalho 2013, p. 145), and in the work of Kauffman with its emphasis on the autonomy of life, acting on its own behalf, implying “Once there is an autonomous agent, there is a semantics from its privileged point of view” (Kauffman 2000, p. 111).

  5. Noting that molecules act ‘as if’ they prefer to be spread out through a volume rather than remain concentrated in a corner of this volume would not add explanatory power beyond the mechanistic explanation. The mechanisms work purely ‘on the spot’, without being forward looking in any sense.

  6. In that scheme the modulation of stochasticity can only be understood from its expected future benefits, not from its immediate mechanistic consequences (which are at a particular point in time not distinguishable from those of a non-modulated stochasticity). Thus the mechanism itself is, in some sense, forward looking, although it has evolved through regular, backward looking evolutionary mechanisms (van Hateren 2014a).

References

  • Anderson, P. W. (1972). More is different. Science, 177, 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. F., Mele, A. R., & Vohs, K. D. (2010). Free will and consciousness: How might they work? New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. F., Masicampo, E. J., & Vohs, K. D. (2011). Do conscious thoughts cause behavior? Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 331–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brembs, B. (2011). Towards a scientific concept of free will as a biological trait: spontaneous actions and decision-making in invertebrates. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 278, 930–939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2005). Natural theories of consciousness. In P. Carruthers (Ed.), Consciousness: essays from a higher-order perspective (pp. 36–60). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, D. (2007). Semiotics: the basics. Oxon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A., & Carvalho, G. B. (2013). The nature of feelings: evolutionary and neurobiological origins. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 14, 143–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. S. (2009). Subjects of the world: Darwin’s rhetoric and the study of agency in nature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester, H. (2003). Meaning: what’s the matter? Intrinsic relations and the organism. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 7, 195–205.

  • Dehaene, S., & Changeux, J. P. (2000). Reward-dependent learning in neuronal networks for planning and decision making. Progress in Brain Research, 126, 217–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds: Toward an understanding of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom evolves. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, R. A. (2013). The two-stage model to the problem of free will. In A. Suarez & P. Adams (Eds.), Is science compatible with free will?: Exploring free will and consciousness in the light of quantum physics and neuroscience (Chap. 16). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faisal, A. A., Selen, L. P. J., & Wolpert, D. M. (2008). Noise in the nervous system. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9, 292–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fried, I., Mukamel, R., & Kreiman, G. (2011). Internally generated preactivation of single neurons in human medial frontal cortex predicts volition. Neuron, 69, 548–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galhardo, R. S., Hastings, P. J., & Rosenberg, S. M. (2007). Mutation as a stress response and the regulation of evolvability. Critical Reviews of Biochemistry and Molecular Biology, 42, 399–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2006). Where’s the action? Epiphenomenalism and the problem of free will. In S. Pockett, W. Banks, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Does consciousness cause behavior? An investigation of the nature of volition (pp. 109–124). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Eimer, M. (1999). On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research, 126, 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, M. (2009). Is free will an illusion? Nature, 459, 164–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. A. (2000). Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ram, Y., & Hadany, L. (2012). The evolution of stress-induced hypermutation in asexual populations. Evolution, 66, 2315–2328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2003). On being the object of attention: implications for self–other consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 397–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, M. E. (2014). The neuroscientific study of free will: a diagnosis of the controversy. Synthese, 191, 245–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2007). Free will as a problem in neurobiology. In J. Searle (Ed.), Freedom and neurobiology: Reflections on free will, language, and political power (pp. 37–78). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2013). Theory of mind and Darwin’s legacy. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the U.S.A., 110(suppl. 2), 10343–10348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H. J., & Haynes, J. D. (2008). Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience, 11, 543–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge Mass.: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Carpenter, M. (2007). Shared intentionality. Developmental Science, 10, 121–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., & Aitken, K. J. (2001). Infant intersubjectivity: research, theory, and clinical applications. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 42, 3–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tse, P. E. (2013). The neural basis of free will: Criterial causation. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Hateren, J. H. (2013). A new criterion for demarcating life from non-life. Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 43, 491–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Hateren, J. H. (2014a). Active causation and the origin of meaning. Biological Cybernetics. doi:10.1007/s00422-014-0622-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Hateren, J. H. (2014b). Consciousness results when communication modifies the form of self-estimated fitness. arXiv:1401.6761 [q-bio.NC] http://arxiv.org/abs/1401.6761

  • Varela, F. G., Maturana, H. R., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems, 5, 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language. Translated from the original 1934 Russian edition. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weir, A. A. S., Chappell, J., & Kacelnik, A. (2002). Shaping of hooks in New Caledonian crows. Science, 297, 981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers of the manuscript for thoughtful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. H. van Hateren.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

van Hateren, J.H. The origin of agency, consciousness, and free will. Phenom Cogn Sci 14, 979–1000 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9396-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9396-5

Keywords

Navigation