Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Prolegomena to any future mereology of the body

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many bioethical arguments rely implicitly on the assumption that the concept of “human part” is one on which everyone must agree, because it is unambiguous. But various parties interpret this “unambiguous” term in incompatible ways, leading to contention. This article is an informal presentation of a topomereological system on whose preferred interpretation several distinct but related meanings of “human part” can be isolated: part of a human body, part of the completion of a human body, and part of a human being. A case is analyzed (the first total artificial heart (TAH) implantation), demonstrating in the process much of the apparatus of the system. By means of a casuistic methodology, the analysis is translated into recommendations for the ethical conduct of future TAH research. The more general conclusion, however, is that formal methods may provide useful tools for clarifying thought processes and organizing arguments in debates over bioethical issues.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The acronym is standard in the literature. In fact, the “Jarvik-7” was a bi-ventricular prosthesis attached to vestigial atria [1, p. 849].

  2. Dr. Clark’s post-implant suicidal ideation gets significant attention in a comprehensive discussion of the case by his psychiatrists, Berenson and Grosser [3, p. 913]. Notably absent, however, is any mention of a competency evaluation or any other indication that his requests to be killed were taken seriously. The oversight is all the more strange since, as Berenson and Grosser were aware, his desire to die was not itself a symptom of anything, but rather a rational reaction to his deficits and hence evidence of competence [3, p. 915; 4]. As patient/subject, then, Clark was deprived of both basic patient and basic subject protections. As subject, he was deprived of his right to give a “competent, voluntary, informed, and understanding” consent to the experiment [5, p. 202]; as patient, he was deprived of his right as a competent adult to have treatment withdrawn at his request [4; 5, p. 89]. For more on these points, see “Recommendations” and “Discussion”, infra.

  3. The situation bears some comparison to that of “David G.” (Donald “Dax” Cowart), who also was suffering greatly from life-preserving medical treatment but unable to end his life without the cooperation of others [6]. A full discussion of Robert Burt’s very insightful critique of the received bioethical notion of autonomy is beyond the scope of this paper. For counter-critiques, see [7, 8].

  4. The options currently available to the researcher now are few and unsatisfactory. The sorting of implanted devices into “parts” or “treatments” (with distinctive rights and duties attached to each) is well-nigh hopeless. In general, ethicists will be able to find good reasons for treating devices as both [10]. Indeed, there is no rigid ontological distinction between them (see footnote 12). Some alternatives have been suggested, including a “biofixture” analysis and an “integral device” analysis [11, 12]. These categories are murky; they provide no clear guidance on how or why we should behave in one way as opposed to another when faced with a novel situation involving parts.

  5. With a few notational exceptions (⊆ instead of <, ⊂ instead of ≪, ⇒ and ⇔ for the material conditional and biconditional, respectively), this survey basically follows [20, chs. 1–2]. Although up-to-date only until 1987, this work remains a very valuable resource for anyone interested in mereology. Chapter 2, “Survey of Extensional Mereology,” presupposes a knowledge of set theory through order; chapters 7 and 8, “Essential Parts” and “Dependence,” presuppose an acquaintance with modal logic. A technically sound yet accessible general introduction to the field of “mereotopology” (see footnote 8) is [17]. For more recent developments in this field, see the current bibliographies of Maureen Donnelly, Barry Smith, and their various collaborators.

  6. An alternative supplementation principle is “Weak Supplementation.” A mereology with Weak Supplementation does not afford the PPP as an inference when added to the axioms for the partial ordering.

  7. There are exceptions to this rule, but they are considered aberrant (see [20, p. 13]). Unrestricted operations of + and · make a mereology equivalent in power to a Boolean Algebra without a null element [20, p. 34].

  8. Calling TM a “mereotopology” (as developers of formal models for spatial representation usually call their systems) would be misleading, for TM differs significantly from prior systems. For example, it rejects Casati and Varzi’s axiom C.1 [17, p. 52] and the inorganic axiom C.3’ [17, p. 54]. Furthermore, while the various mereotopologies all posit an apparatus of regions independent of objects, TM rejects such an apparatus for philosophical reasons. These distinctive features justify the deviation from the standard nomenclature.

  9. Some cases of poor adjustment have been reported when men receive female donor hearts [3, p. 915], including at least one case of an acute schizophrenic reaction [3, p. 916].

  10. The Oriental medical doctor (OMD) will partition the body as Western doctors do—up to a point—recognizing most of our major organ systems. But she will also observe channels (meridians) and their vessels, divergences, sinews, and points, which do not in general correspond to any material feature recognized by biomedicine [26].

  11. See [14] for an effective axiomatic treatment of this approach.

  12. In [28], Zemach distinguishes four basic ways entities can be situated with respect to spacetime. These include events, which are partitionable both in time and space; continuants, which are partitionable in space but “wholly present” in time; processes, which are partitionable in time but wholly present in space; and types, which are wholly present both spatially and temporally. Zemach contends that each of these ontologies is complete: each is alone capable of accounting for all the phenomena of the spacetime world. Hence, as noted, Quine (and others) take “continuants” to be “events,” etc. I will rely on Zemach’s insight later, when I consider the Jarvik-7 (nominally a machine, a “continuant”) as a process, viz., in its aspect as a sustaining mechanism or activity essential to life and, as such, wholly present wherever it is present at all. The usage is not without precedent; Hudson [29] effectively deploys the concept to solve the problem of vague boundaries for persons.

  13. “A container is a fillable thing, and fillability is a complex dispositional property that cannot be explained in terms of simple part-whole structures” [17, p. 139].

  14. See [34, p. 42]. One might wonder how a law can be a law if it is not a necessary truth (i.e., true in every possible world). The formulation is standard for Humeans, although it has been subjected to forceful critiques by scientific realists like Armstrong and Lowe, who hold that the proper form of scientific laws must posit relations among universals (see, e.g., [35]).

  15. This is why I prefer this formulation of Niche to that of [36], according to which “Niche” excludes the encompassed part.

  16. I will eschew the obvious choice of “identical to the body” for the simple reason that there is no reason preferentially to identify “person” with any one of the three types of human wholes; and identifying persons with all three would contradict the transitivity of identity sentences (since none of these wholes is identical to any of the others).

  17. This caveat is necessary, e.g., to allow for the construal of temporal person parts as persons (see, e.g., [38, p. 190, 39, p. 55, 40, p. 23]).

  18. Since in all these cases we will have manifest behavior to explain, it will be simpler to posit that the principles reflect a desire that some state of affairs be instantiated than that they reflect a belief that actions intended to bring about a state of affairs more consistent with the principles is morally obligatory; for this would still require attention to the contentious question of whether or how “reason can be practical” (i.e., how moral beliefs motivate). Locke wrote, “The motive, for continuing in the same State or Action, is only the present satisfaction in it; the motive to change is always some uneasiness [desire]; nothing setting us upon any new Action, but some uneasiness” [42, p. 249].

  19. Studies indicate that distrust of physicians may also play a role [5, p. 192].

  20. That processes are “wholly present” wherever they are present at all is true by the definition of processes (see supra). But can a consistent mereology include axioms that assert the existence of such things? A viable solution can follow the lead of the Anti-Foundation Axiom of set theory, which posits a unique solution (Ω) to the equation X = {X} [45]. Briefly, I will define a class of Ω objects, objects which are proper parts of themselves. Given this definition and the definition of a process as any entity that is part of all its proper spatial parts, it is easy to show (1) that Ω objects obey the four basic axioms of extensional mereology; (2) all processes with any proper parts are Ω objects; (3) all parts of processes are identical to the whole and to each other. Further details (as of the whole system) will be presented elsewhere.

  21. The idea that one is part of something greater that is also a part of oneself plays an important role in the teachings of Christianity, Hinduism, and Mahayana Buddhism.

  22. Personal psychological factors, such as a generally compliant nature and difficulty saying “no” to requests, may also have contributed to his attitude towards the experiment [3, p. 911].

  23. For more on casuistry, see [47].

  24. Although Rady and Verheijde assert that dependent patients die within minutes of the deactivation of their LVAD, at least one case reports normal heart function for over 24 h in a presumptively dependent patient after LVAD failure [48, p. 2; 49, p. 1690]. We do not know who is “dependent” until the device is turned off.

  25. This is not intended to be a blanket condemnation of paternalistic physician decision-making. There are cases where the physician can see a brighter future for the patient with great clarity, which may in some circumstances justify continuing treatment over a refusal (see [50] for a discussion of pertinent considerations). Novel interventions by their nature cannot invoke this exception.

  26. The use of LVADs as destination therapy (i.e., not as a “bridge-to-transplant”) raises the question of whether portability is an adequate substitute for full implantability. The answer here is “no.” Portable, partially implanted devices are in effect “wholly external organs” and (in addition to turning a body cavity into a hollow) leave a troublesome ambiguity surrounding patients’ physical boundaries. See my response to an objection in the “Discussion” section infra; see also footnotes 24 and 27.

  27. Although their deactivation is not an immediate cause of death, LVADs are not true assistive devices; their implantation degrades natural circulatory function [51].

  28. The reader may safely infer from this that I think the regulations requiring the organs of such patients to be evaluated for transplant suitability are ill-advised (see, e.g., [54]).

  29. A competent adult patient has both a constitutional [5, p. 89] and a common law [4, p. 272] right to refuse treatment. The sensational cases involving a “right to die” almost always involve decisions for incompetents or non-adults. (For an exception that nevertheless affirms the right, see ([5, ch. 3].) Dr. DeVries averred, “After implantation, the recipient reserves the right to discontinue participation in additional experimental procedures, in which case supportive care will be provided” [1, p. 850].

  30. Cf. Dr. Kevorkian’s “killing machine” [5, ch. 16].

  31. In an (unfortunately) very influential article, Rachels argues that “the bare difference between killing and letting die does not in itself make a moral difference” [59, p. 40]. This conclusion is based on analogy to a case of “passive malthanasia”: A man bent on murder for gain allows his prospective victim to die. There is no moral difference between having committed the murder and having “[stood] by, ready to push the child’s head back under if necessary, but it is not necessary” [59, p. 40]. A case of “passive euthanasia” should be analogous to that of passive malthanasia. Imagine that a physician has decided to euthanize a patient, and finds him (as the victim in the first case) drowning. He stands by, ready to give the patient a shot of potassium, but it is not necessary to do so. Grant arguendo that this physician is as morally culpable as the physician who actually gives a shot. But there is a morally significant difference between what this physician does and what a physician does when she “lets a patient die.” When a physician “lets die,” she does not stand by ready to kill if necessary. Indeed, if the patient should miraculously recover, she would be ecstatic. Put another way, termination of treatment does not apodictically entail termination of life. Therefore, it is not morally equivalent to it (on Rachels’s argument, at any rate; for a different argument to the same conclusion for neonates only, see [60]).

  32. As to Recommendation (1a), all the ethicists I have read on the topic insist on the necessity of comprehensive, effective informational activities with patients prior to VAD implantation—unlike the presumption of permission appropriate to established medical intervention [4] and much more like that required of subjects in human subject research (see footnote 2). The extent to which these recommendations are currently being implemented in actual consent procedures is unknown.

References

  1. DeVries, William C. 1988. The permanent artificial heart—four case reports. Journal of the American Medical Association 259(6): 849–859.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Brauer, Ralph. 1988. The promise that failed. New York Times Magazine, August 28.

  3. Berenson, Claudia K., and Bernard I. Grosser. 1984. Total artificial heart implantation. Archives of General Psychiatry 41: 910–916.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Roth, Loren H., Alan Meisel, and Charles W. Lidz. 1977 [1983]. Tests of competency to consent to treatment. In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams and Michael Buckner, 270–275. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  5. Annas, George J. 1993. Standard of care. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Burt, Robert A. 1979. Taking care of strangers. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Diamond, Bernard L. 1980. Resolving doctor-patient conflicts. In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams, and Michael Buckner, 268–270. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Epright, Carmela. 2008. Before and after Schiavo. In Biomedical ethics, ed. Howard B. Radest, vol. 17 of Humanism today. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

  9. Altman, Lawrence K. 1983. Recipient of artificial heart calls ordeal worthwhile. New York Times, March 3.

  10. Simon, Jeremy R., and Ruth L. Fischbach. 2008. Case study: “Doctor, will you turn off my LVAD?” Hastings Center Report 38(1): 14–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Paola, F., and R. Walker. 2000. Deactivating the implantable cardioverter-defibrillator: A biofixture analysis. Southern Medical Journal 93: 20–23.

    Google Scholar 

  12. England, Ruth, Tim England, and John Coggan. 2007. The ethical and legal implications of deactivating an implantable cardioverter-defibrillator in a patient with terminal cancer. Journal of Medical Ethics 33(9): 538–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Leśniewski, Stanisław. 1916. Podstawy ogólnej teoryi mnogości I. [Foundations of the general theory of manifolds.] Moscow: Popławski. (Prace Polskiego Koła Naukowego w Moskwie. Sekcya matematyczno-przyrodnicza, No. 2.)

  14. Tarski, Alfred. 1937. Appendix E. In The axiomatic method in biology, ed. J.H. Woodger, 161–172. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Leonard, Henry S. 1930. Singular terms. PhD diss., Harvard University.

  16. Leonard, Henry S., and Nelson Goodman. 1940. The calculus of individuals and its uses. Journal of Symbolic Logic 5: 45–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Casati, Roberto, and Achille C. Varzi. 1999. Parts and places. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Neuhaus, Fabian, and Barry Smith. 2008. Modelling principles and methodologies—relations in anatomical ontologies. In Anatomy ontologies for bioinformatics, ed. Albert Burger, Duncan Davidson, and Richard Baldock. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Bittner, Thomas, and Barry Smith. n.d. Formal ontologies for space and time. http://www.ifomis.org/bfo/publications. Accessed January 2012.

  20. Simons, Peter. 1987. Parts: A study in ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Grätzer, George. 1998. General lattice theory, 2nd ed. Basel: Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Kazmi, Ali Akhtar. 1990. Parthood and persistence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16(suppl.): 227–250.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Perry, John. 1975. The problem of personal identity. In Personal identity, ed. John Perry, 3–30. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  24. van Inwagen, Peter. 1990. Four-dimensional objects. Noûs 24(2): 245–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Grünbaum, Adolf. 1970 [1967]. Zeno’s metrical paradox of extension. In Zeno’s Paradoxes, ed. Wesley C. Salmon, 176–199. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Co.

  26. Ellis, Andrew, Nigel Wiseman, and Ken Boss. 1991. Fundamentals of Chinese acupuncture, rev. ed. Brookline, MA: Paradigm Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Nerlich, Graham. 2003. Space-time substantivalism. In Oxford handbook of metaphysics, ed. Michael J. Loux, and Dean W. Zimmerman, 281–314. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Zemach, Eddy. 1970. Four ontologies. Journal of Philosophy 67: 231–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Hudson, Hud. 2001. A materialist metaphysics of the human person. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Brogaard, Berit. 2004. Species as individuals. Biology and Philosophy 19: 223–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Donnelly, Maureen, Thomas Bittner, and Cornelius Rosse. 2006. A formal theory for spatial representation and reasoning in biomedical ontologies. Artificial Intelligence in Medicine 36: 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Meisenberg, Gerhard, and William H. Simmons. 2006. Principles of medical biochemistry, 2nd ed. Philadelphia: Mosby Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Husserl, Edmund. 1970. Logical investigations (trans: Findlay, J.N.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  34. Tiles, Mary. 1989. The philosophy of set theory. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Lowe, E. Jonathan. 2002. Kinds, essence and natural necessity. In Individuals, essence and identity, ed. Andrea Bottani, Massimiliano Carrara, and Pierdaniele Giaretta, 189–206. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  36. Smith, Barry, and Achille C. Varzi. 1999. The niche. Noûs 32: 214–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Hampshire, Stuart. 1991 [1952]. The analogy of feeling. In The nature of mind, ed. David M. Rosenthal, 98–103. New York: Oxford University Press.

  38. Sider, Theodore. 2001. Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Hawley, Katherine. 2001. How things persist. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Balashov, Yuri. 2007. About stage universalism. Philosophical Quarterly 57: 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Strawson, Peter F. 1991 [1958]. Persons. In The nature of mind, ed. David M. Rosenthal, 104–114. New York: Oxford University Press.

  42. Locke, John. 1975. An essay concerning human understanding. Ed. Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  43. Insight Team of the Sunday Times of London. 1979. Suffer the children: The story of thalidomide. New York: The Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Rennie, Drummond. 1980. Informed consent by “well-nigh abject adults.” In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams, and Michael Buckner, 293–295. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Aczel, Peter. 1988. Non-well-founded sets. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Keen, Ernest. 1993. Being conscious is being-in-the-world. In Self and consciousness: multiple perspectives, ed. Frank S. Kessel, Pamela M. Cole, and Dale L. Johnson, 45–63. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Brody, Baruch. 1988. Life and death decision making. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Rady, Mohamed Y., and Joseph L. Verheijde. 2011. LVADs as destination therapy: Difficult ethical decisions. Leahy Clinic Medical Ethics 18(2): 1–2, 7.

  49. Stepanenko, Alexander, Miralem Pasic, Evgenij V. Potapov, Yuguo Weng, Thomas Krabatsch, and Roland Hetzer. 2010. Accidental intraperitoneal tunneling of driveline of left ventricular assist device. Annals of Thoracic Surgery 90: 1690–1691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Siegler, Mark. 1977. Critical illness: The limits of autonomy. In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams, and Michael Buckner, 276–281. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  51. Bramstedt, Katrina A., and Neil S. Wenger. 2001. When withdrawal of life-sustaining care does more than allow death to take its course: The dilemma of left ventricular assist devices. Journal of Heart and Lung Transplantation 20(5): 544–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Rizzieri, Aaron G., Joseph L. Verheijde, Mohamed Y. Rady, and Joan L. McGregor. 2008. Ethical challenges with the left ventricular assist device as a destination therapy. Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine 3:20.

  53. Dejohn, Carla, and Joseph B. Zwischenberger. 2006. Ethical implications of extracorporeal interval support for organ retrieval (EISOR). ASAIO Journal 52(2): 119–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Verheijde, Joseph L., Mohamed Y. Rady, and Joan L. McGregor. 2007. The United States Revised Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (2006): New challenges to balancing patient rights and physician responsibilities. Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine 2(1): 19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Rachels, James. 1983. Barney Clark’s key. Hastings Center Report 13(2): 17–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Altman, Lawrence. 1985. The ordeal of a “human experiment.” New York Times, May 14.

  57. Wiegand, Debra Lynn-McHale, and Peggy G. Kalowes. 2007. Withdrawal of cardiac medications and devices. AACN Advanced Critical Care 18(4): 415–425.

  58. President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. 1983. Deciding to forego life-sustaining treatment: A report on the ethical, medical and legal issues in treatment decisions. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Rachels, James. 1975. Active and passive euthanasia. In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams, and Michael Buckner, 38–42. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  60. Robertson, John A., and Norman Frost. 1976. Passive euthanasia of defective newborn infants: Legal considerations. In Medical ethics, ed. Natalie Abrams, and Michael Buckner, 382–389. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  61. Bunzel, B., K. Laederach-Hofmann, G.M. Wieselthaler, W. Roethy, and G. Drees. 2005. Posttraumatic stress disorder after implantation of a mechanical assist device followed by heart transplantation: Evaluation of patients and partners. Transplantation Proceedings 37: 1365–1368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Kaan, Annemarie, Quincy-Robyn Young, Sarah Cockell, and Martha Mackay. 2010. Emotional experiences of caregivers of patients with a ventricular assist device. Progress in Transplantation 20(2): 142–147.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Chapman, Elizabeth, Jayan Parameshwar, David Jenkins, Stephen Large, and Steven Tsui. 2007. Psychosocial issues for patients with ventricular assist devices: A qualitative pilot study. American Journal of Critical Care 16: 72–81.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Marcuccilli, Linda, and Jesus Casida. 2012. Overcoming alterations in body image imposed by the left ventricular assist device: A case report. Progress in Transplantation 22: 212–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Altman, Lawrence K. 1985. U.S. panel strongly endorses artificial heart. New York Times, May 24.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author gratefully acknowledges many helpful suggestions from the Journal’s editorial staff, including Jeremy R. Simon and several anonymous reviewers. The assistance of Dorothy Walsh of the interlibrary loan staff of College of Staten Island, CUNY was invaluable. I am indebted to Angela Fried for preparing the diagrams. Very special thanks are due Douglas Lackey, who commented on an early draft and whose suggestion provided the original impetus for this project.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edward Fried.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fried, E. Prolegomena to any future mereology of the body. Theor Med Bioeth 34, 359–384 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9263-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9263-3

Keywords

Navigation