Skip to main content
Log in

Justifying group-specific common morality

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some defenders of the view that there is a common morality have conceived such morality as being universal, in the sense of extending across all cultures and times. Those who deny the existence of such a common morality often argue that the universality claim is implausible. Defense of common morality must take account of the distinction between descriptive and normative claims that there is a common morality. This essay considers these claims separately and identifies the nature of the arguments for each claim. It argues that the claim that there is a universal common morality in the descriptive sense has not been successfully defended to date. It maintains that the claim that there is a common morality in the normative sense need not be understood as universalist. This paper advocates the concept of group specific common morality, including country-specific versions. It suggests that both the descriptive and the normative claims that there are country-specific common moralities are plausible, and that a country-specific normative common morality could provide the basis for a country's bioethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Bernard Gert [1 pp. 11–13]; Bernard Gert [2, p. 269].

  2. See, e.g., Tom L. Beauchamp, [3, pp. 259–260]; Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, [4, pp. 3–4]; Tom L. Beauchamp, [5, p. 394].

  3. Baker suggests additional counterexamples, as follows:

    “Promise keeping,” for example, cannot be a cultural universal because the practice is necessarily limited to those cultures that use languages capable of formulating performative utterances—i.e., utterances that perform the action characterized, e.g., “I promise”. [7, p. 424]

    A similar problem afflicts Beauchamp’s claim that “respect [for] the rights of others” is characteristic of “all moral societies.” Historically, the languages of most societies do not contain a term designating the concept of having a right. This concept first emerges in Anglo-Saxon culture in the thirteen (sic) century, when it was invented as a defense against the depredations of Norman conquerors. The philosophical notion that individuals have rights emerged even later, in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Anglo-Saxon culture. [7, p. 425]

  4. I suggest that there are better ways to state the purpose of morality. Gert’s formulation seems too narrow, in that more is involved in morality than avoiding harming. In particular, harm, liberty, and justice would seem to be distinct concepts that are part of morality. An example of an alternative formulation is that the purpose of morality is to diminish the amount of harm, curtailment of liberty, and injustice that is suffered by those individuals toward whom moral precepts apply. However, I shall put these issues aside and accept, for sake of argument, Gert’s formulation.

  5. This interpretation is consistent with Beauchamp’s statement: “If norms other than the ones I have specified were demonstrated to be shared across cultures, this finding would constitute evidence of a common morality, albeit one different from the account I have proposed [3, p. 264].”

  6. A similar statement is made in Beauchamp, “The Mettle of Moral Fundamentalism”:

    I believe...that it is an institutional fact about the substance of morality (not merely the formal features of the concept of morality and not merely my view of it) that it contains fundamental and shared precepts. It is by appeal to this shared moral substance that persons are enabled to make justifiable cross-temporal and cross-cultural judgments [5, p. 395].

  7. Gert points out that common morality does not resolve controversial moral issues, such as the morality of abortion, physician-assisted suicide, or the allocation of health care resources. Moreover, one of the important topics it is unable to resolve, according to Gert, is the range of individuals toward whom one has an obligation to follow the moral rules. He states that almost all moral agents agree that we should follow the rules, at the very least, in our interactions with all moral agents, persons who previously were moral agents and who remain conscious, and children. But the question of what other individuals we have an obligation not to harm is a matter of disagreement. For example, he states that common morality does not resolve controversies over the moral standing of animals or human embryos and fetuses. See [1, pp. 8, 138–148]; [13, p.v.]; [14, p. 255].

References

  1. Gert, Bernard. 1998. 2005 rev. ed. Morality: Its nature and justification. New York: Oxford University Press.

  2. Gert, Bernard. 2002. Replies to my critics. In Rationality, rules, and ideals: Critical essays on Bernard Gert’s moral theory, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong and R. Audi, 261–316. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Beauchamp, Tom L. 2003. A defense of the common morality. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13(3): 259–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Beauchamp, Tom L., and J.F. Childress. 2001. Principles of biomedical ethics, fifth ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Beauchamp, Tom L. 1998. The mettle of moral fundamentalism: A reply to Robert Baker. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8(4): 389–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Turner, Leigh. 2003. Zones of consensus and zones of conflict: Questioning the “common morality” presumption in bioethics. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13(3): 193–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Baker, Robert. 1998. Negotiating international bioethics: A response to Tom Beauchamp and Ruth Macklin. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8(4): 423–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Gert, Bernard, C.M. Culver, and K.D. Clouser. 1997. Bioethics: A return to fundamentals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1993. Religious ethics in a pluralistic society. In Prospects for a common morality, ed. G. Outka and J.P. Reeder Jr., 93–113. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Engelhardt, H. Tristram Jr. 1996. The foundations of bioethics, second ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gewirth, Alan. 1978. Reason and morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Baier, Kurt. 1965. The moral point of view: A rational basis of ethics, abridged ed. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gert, Bernard. 2004. Common morality: Deciding what to do. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gert, Bernard. 1988. Morality: A new justification of the moral rules. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gert, Bernard. 1990. Rationality, human nature, and lists. Ethics 100(2): 279–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Engelhardt, H. Tristram Jr. 2006. Global bioethics: An introduction to the collapse of consensus. In Global bioethics: The collapse of consensus, ed. H.T. Engelhardt Jr., 1–17. Salem, MA: M & M Scrivener Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Engelhardt, H. Tristram Jr. 2006. The search for a global morality. In Global bioethics: The collapse of consensus, ed. H.T. Engelhardt Jr., 18–49. Salem, MA: M & M Scrivener Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carson Strong.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Strong, C. Justifying group-specific common morality. Theor Med Bioeth 29, 1–15 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-008-9058-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-008-9058-0

Keywords

Navigation