Skip to main content
Log in

Kant’s racial mind–body unions

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Eric Voegelin’s writings on the historical development of the concept of race in the early 1930s are important to philosophy today in part because they provide a model upon which scholars can further integrate modern philosophy with the critical philosophy of race. In constructing his history, Voegelin’s methodological orientation depends on the centrality of both Kant’s work and the problem of the mind–body union to the concept of race. This essay asks how one might hold these premises if Kant seems to reject the dominant approach to the mind–body union in the mid-eighteenth century, physical influx, and then go on to publish several essays on race that do not thematize that doctrine in any way. I argue that Kant’s racial union of mind and body cannot be understood as an interaction in space, as his contemporaries had presumed. Rather, the union must be approached as a repetition in time. In this way, Kant’s four racial categories are not merely a part of the mind–body problem, but instead each is a veritable mind–body union. This permits the conclusion that ‘race’, as Kant understood it, is a viable solution to the mind–body problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Arendt (1966, p. 158).

  2. Recent Anglophone anthologies to overlook Voegelin’s contribution include: Goldberg (1990), Harris (1999), Babbitt and Campbell (1999), Back and Solomos (2000), Bernasconi and Lott (2000), Bernasconi (2001a), Cashmore and Jennings (2001), Boxhill (2001), Ward and Lott (2002), and Valls (2005). An overview of Voegelin’s work is found in Heilke (1990) and Levy (2003).

  3. Voegelin (1998, pp. 89–90).

  4. Voegelin (1997, pp. 19–36).

  5. Voegelin (1998, p. 8).

  6. Voegelin (1998, pp. 78–79).

  7. Voegelin (1998, p. 78); Also see 136–137; 144.

  8. Voegelin (1997, p. 10).

  9. Leibniz (1989, p. 33).

  10. Cf. Ablondi (2008), for example.

  11. Watkins (1998, p. 138).

  12. Watkins (1995).

  13. Yolton (1991, p. 87).

  14. Crivellato and Ribatti (2007).

  15. Yolton (1991, p. 103).

  16. pp. 74–123.

  17. Marat (1773, p. 49).

  18. Meyer and Hierons (1965).

  19. Hatfield (1995, pp. 209–212).

  20. La Peyronie (1741, p. 1999) and Kaitaro (1996, p. 564).

  21. Kant (1967, p. 56) and Zammito (2002, p. 43).

  22. Whitaker and Turgeon (2007).

  23. Zammito (2002, p. 297).

  24. Kant (1967, p. 79).

  25. AA 12: 35 (Whenever possible, references to Kant’s writings cite the volume and page number of the Akademie Ausgabe, as provided in the margins of various translations).

  26. AA 12: 32.

  27. A p. 395. See also Ameriks (2000, Chapter 3)

  28. AA 1: 19; Watkins (2005, pp. 106–108).

  29. Anderson (1982).

  30. AA 2: 438.

  31. AA 8: 176.

  32. (A 8: 99) Pauline Kleingeld (2007) has recently argued that Kant’s racial hierarchy is predicated on moral characteristics, which, as early as 1779, he saw as detachable from “the physical theory of race itself” (579). She argues that although he ‘attached’ and ‘re-attached’ his mental sterotypes throughout his career, he ultimately excluded predispositions of the soul from his concept of race. Curiously, Kleingeld does not support this argument with any evidence from Kant’s essays explicitly addressing race, instead relying on (1) A letter to Johann Jacob Engel where Kant employs the phrase “attached principles of a moral characterisation,” which Kleingeld stipulates to mean ‘detachable moral characteristics’ (579); (2) A sentence in Perpetual Peace that equates American Indians’ military courage to that of mediaevel European knights (589); (3) Kant’s endorsement of Girtanner’s Über das Kantische Prinzip für Naturgeschicte (1796), which, according to Kleingeld, does not mention the moral characteristcs of races aside from a few comments about the laziness of North American savages (590). In a later text, she develops these themes in order to buttress the notion of a Kantian ‘cultural diversity’ (see Kleingeld 2012, Chapter 4; Muthu 2003, Chapters 4 and 5). Kleingeld is right to investigate the questions of separation and unity of minds and bodies in the race context. However, ‘separability’ never simply means that one can discuss the mind without the body or vice versa. A full treatment of this important theme is beyond the scope of this essay, but one would have to start with what Voegelin calls the ‘isolating construction’ to understand what sorts of mind–body ‘separability’ were available to Kant (1998, p. 90). One could then recognize how far Kant is from adopting these rigorous ontological and genealogical separations of mind and body. Despite our best hopes for Kant, to my knowledge, Kant never retreats from his view that minds are shaped by the same processes that race bodies. As I explain below, this is the basis of ‘race’ as the solution to the mind–body problem. Further discussion of Kleingeld’s 2007 argument can be found in Bernasconi (2011). Concerning the importance of Kant’s racial hierarchy to his political thought and cosmopolitanism, see Hedrick (2008).

  33. Larrimore (1999), Bernasconi (2003), Shell (2006) and Cohen (2009).

  34. AA 25:1187.

  35. Carron (2011, p. 111).

  36. AA 2: 441.

  37. AA 15: 377–378.

  38. AA 2: 433.

  39. Mclaughlin (2007).

  40. AA 2: 430.

  41. AA 2: 441.

  42. AA: 2: 430.

  43. AA 2: 430 my emphasis; also see AA 8: 101.

  44. AA 2:442.

  45. AA 8: 174.

  46. AA 8: 174.

  47. AA 2: 443.

  48. AA 2: 225.

  49. Bernasconi (2001b, p. 1).

  50. Deleuze and Guattari (1994, p. 16).

  51. Voegelin (1998, p. 8).

References

  • Ablondi, Fred. 2008. François Lamy, occasionalism, and the mind–body problem. Journal of the History of Philosophy 46: 619–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, Karl. 2000. Kant’s theory of mind: An analysis of the paralogisms of pure reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Lorin. 1982. Charles Bonnet and the order of the known. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1966. The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Babbitt, Susan, and Sue Campbell (eds.). 1999. Racism and philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Back, Les, and John Solomos (eds.). 2000. Theories of race and racism: A reader. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Robert, and Tommy L. Lott (eds.). 2000. The idea of race. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Robert (ed.). 2001a. Race. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Robert. 2001b. Who invented the concept of race? Kant’s role in the enlightenment construction of race. In Race, ed. Robert Bernasconi, 11–36. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Robert. 2003. Will the real Kant please stand up? The challenge of enlightenment racism to the study of the history of philosophy. Radical Philosophy 117: 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Robert. 2011. Kant’s third thoughts on race. In Reading Kant’s geography, ed. Stuart Elden, and Eduardo Mendieta, 291–318. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonnet, Charles. 1769. La palingénésie philosophique. v.I. Geneva.

  • Boxhill, Bernard (ed.). 2001. Race and racism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carron, Andrew. 2011. The anatomy of blackness: Science and slavery in the age of enlightenment. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cashmore, Ellis, and James Jennings (eds.). 2001. Racism: Essential readings. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Alix. 2009. Kant and the human sciences: Biology, anthropology and history. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crivellato, Enrico, and Domenico Ribatti. 2007. Soul, mind, brain: Greek philosophy and the birth of neuroscience. Brain Research Bulletin 71: 327–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. 1994. What is philosophy? (trans: Tomlinson, Hugh and Burchell, Graham). New York: Columbia.

  • Godart, Guillaume-Lambert. 1755. La physique de l’âme humaine. Berlin.

  • Goldberg, David Theo (ed.). 1990. Anatomy of racism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Leonard (ed.). 1999. Racism. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, Gary. 1995. Remaking the science of mind: Psychology as natural science. In Inventing human science: Eighteenth-century domains, ed. C. Fox, R. Porter, and R. Wolker, 184–231. Berkeley: University of California.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hedrick, Todd. 2008. Race, difference, and anthropology in Kant’s cosmopolitanism. Journal of the History of Philosophy 46: 245–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heilke, Thomas. 1990. Voegelin on the idea of race. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaitaro, Timo. 1996. La Peyronie and the experimental search for the seat of soul: Neoropsychological methodology in the eighteenth century. Cortex 32: 557–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1967. Philosophical correspondence: 17591799 (ed. and trans: Zweig, Arnulf). Chicago: University of Chicago.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2007. Critique of pure reason (trans: Smith, Norman Kemp). New York: Palgrave.

  • Kleingeld, Pauline. 2007. Kant’s second thoughts on race. The Philosophical Quarterly 57: 573–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleingeld, Pauline. 2012. Kant and cosmopolitanism: The philosophical ideal of world citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • La Peyronie, Francois Gigot de. 1741. Observations par lesquelles on tâche de découvrir la partie du cerveau où l’âme exerce ses fonctions. In Mémoires de l’Académie royale des sciences, 199–218. Paris.

  • Larrimore, Mark. 1999. Sublime waste: Kant on the destiny of the races. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 199–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1989. Philosophical essays (trans: Ariew, Roger and Garber, Daniel). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Levy, David J. 2003. Ethos and ethnos: An introduction to Eric Voegelin’s critique of European racism. In Race and racism in continental philosophy, ed. Robert Bernasconi, 98–114. Bloomingdale: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marat, Jean Paul. 1773. A philosophical essay on man: Being an attempt to investigate the principles and laws of the reciprocal influence of the soul on the body. London.

  • Mclaughlin, Peter. 2007. Kant on heredity and adaptation. In Heredity produced: At the crossroads of biology, politics, and culture, 1500–1870, ed. Staffan Müller-Wille, and Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, 277–292. Cambridge, MA: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, A., and R. Hierons. 1965. On Thomas Willis’ concept of neurophysiology. Medical History 9: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muthu, Sankar. 2003. Enlightenment against empire. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shell, Susan M. 2006. Kant’s concept of a human race. In The German invention of race, ed. Sara Eigen, and Mark Larrimore, 55–72. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valls, Andrew (ed.). 2005. Race and racism in modern philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voegelin, Eric. 1997. Race and state, ed. Klaus Vondung (trans: Hein, Ruth). Baton Rouge: Louisiana University Press.

  • Voegelin, Eric. 1998. The history of the race idea: From Ray to Carus, ed. Klaus Vondung (trans: Hein, Ruth). Baton Rouge: Louisiana University Press.

  • Ward, Julie K., and Tommy L. Lott (eds.). 2002. Philosophers on race: Critical essays. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, Eric. 1995. The development of physical influx in early eighteenth-century Germany: Gottsched, Knutzen, and Crusius. The Review of Metaphysics 49: 295–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, Eric. 1998. From pre-established harmony to physical influx: Leibniz’s reception in eighteenth century Germany. Perspectives on Science 6(1–2): 136–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, Eric. 2005. Kant and the metaphysics of causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitaker, Harry A., and Yves Turgeon. 2007. Charles Bonnet’s neurophilosophy. In Brain, mind and medicine: Essays in eighteenth century neuroscience, ed. H. Whitaker, C.U.M. Smith, and S. Finger, 191–200. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yolton, John. 1991. Locke and French materialism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, John. 2002. Kant, Herder and the birth of anthropology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Elias Nale.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nale, J.E. Kant’s racial mind–body unions. Cont Philos Rev 48, 41–58 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-014-9314-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-014-9314-0

Keywords

Navigation