1 Introduction

As first observed by Carlson (1987), same and different can give rise to external and internal readings, as illustrated by (1) and (2).

figure a

The external reading in (1) exhibits a fairly straightforward relationship where a different or the same book is compared with the antecedent expression a book in prior discourse. The internal reading in (2) is more challenging – since there is only a single book-denoting expression, it is difficult to see how to express the relevant comparison in a logical representation. Indeed Barker (2007) has argued that internal and external readings for same are completely different, and simply reflect a lexical ambiguity. Brasoveanu (2011) proposes a uniform account of internal and external readings for different, but this account relies on added complexity in the analysis of distributive quantification. More recently Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) observe a distinction between same and different in external readings, where same is subject to parallelism effects that do not apply to different. To account for this, Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) propose some unusual complications to the lexical meaning of same, namely that it includes a discourse parallelism requirement which is not part of the meaning of different.

In this paper, we argue that none of these innovations are required. We propose a novel account which rests on two simple claims: the first is that same and different are able to take scope, and the second is that they give rise to an additive presupposition. No distinctions between same and different are stipulated, other than the inescapable fact that same involves identity while different involves non-identity. Furthermore, we apply standard mechanisms of scope-taking and presupposition resolution to explain the diverse observations alluded to above.

Our analysis consists in elucidating the ways in which the presuppositions generated by same and different can be resolved in different contexts, and how this interacts with the different scopal possibilities. It emerges that the difference between external and internal readings is a reflection of the familiar distinction between presupposition binding and accommodation. Furthermore, we show that the parallelism effects observed by Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) follow directly from the interaction between the scope-taking possibilities and the requirement that an additive presupposition must contrast appropriately with the host. Since our proposal relies entirely on standard mechanisms of presupposition resolution and scope-taking, it has evident conceptual advantages over previous proposals. Our proposal also has new empirical consequences involving the distribution of same and different in comparatives.

In Sect. 2, we characterize the presupposition generated by same and different – both of them generate an additive presupposition, just as too does (Krifka (1999) and much subsequent work). We also describe the syntactic scope-taking possibilities of same and different. Then in Sect. 3 we show that external readings reflect presupposition binding, and we show that the parallelism effects of Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) reflect the way in which same and different have different scope-taking possibilities. In Sect. 4 we show that internal readings reflect presupposition accommodation. In Sect. 5 we examine a further consequence of our account, based on the fact that different can generate a presupposition arising from the local containing DP, while same must move to a higher position. We show that this provides a solution to a puzzle first identified by Heim (1985), concerning same and different in comparative constructions. In Sect. 6 we compare our analysis to related work, and Sect. 7 concludes.

2 Proposal: same and different are additive

At the core of our proposal is the claim that same and different are additive just like too is.Footnote 1 That is, both same and different generate the same presupposition as too. At the same time, there is a basic syntactic difference: same and different are adjectives, while too is a sentential adverbial. Below we characterize the presuppositions of same, different, and too, and then present our syntactic analysis of same and different as scope-taking adjectives.

2.1 The presupposition of same and different

Consider (3):

figure b

It has often been observed that a discourse like (3a) is somewhat odd or degraded, compared to (3b) (see Sæbø 2004, Amsili and Beyssade (2006), Winterstein and Zeevat (2012) among others). One way to explain this is based on the preference to maximize presuppositions (Heim, 1991): in (3b) it is presupposed that someone other than Bao also read War and Peace; something that could have been presupposed by (3a), but was not. It is important to note that this argumentation applies to alternatives like (3a) and (3b) above because they share the same propositional content (see Amsili and Beyssade (2009) and Eckardt and Fränkel (2012) for analyses of obligatory too using Heim’s Maximize Presupposition!) This illustrates the general property of additivity, which is described by Rossdeutscher et al. (2012:1783) as follows “...the host of the item is the case in addition to something else that was already stated” (see also Forker (2016)). In (3), the hostFootnote 2 of too is Bao read the book. As Rossdeutscher et al. (2012) put it, too is additive because the host is true “in addition to something else that was already stated” – this is the presupposition generated by too. In (3), the presupposition is satisfied by “Daiwen read War and Peace”.

The contrast illustrated by (3a) and (3b) has been widely discussed in the literature. However, what has not previously been observed is that the degradedness of (3a) is also remedied by same, as shown by (4):Footnote 3

figure d

(4) is fully acceptable in the absence of too; indeed, on our view too now becomes somewhat infelicitous, similar to (3):

figure e

On the account we will propose, same generates the same presupposition in (4) as too in (3): namely, that someone other than Bao read War and Peace. This provides a natural explanation for the above observations: we argue that (4) has the same propositional content as (3a), but (4) generates a presupposition not made by (3a). This explains the preference for (4) over (3a). It also explains the fact that the cooccurrence of same and too in (4) is odd in much the same way as the cooccurrence of also and too in (5).Footnote 4

Let us return to the presuppositional nature of too, illustrating with example (3b): we assume that too is syntactically adjoined to the TP Bao read it, which we describe as the host, H. H generates a presupposition P – in this case, that someone else read War and Peace. This is a requirement that an antecedent P be found in surrounding discourse. Because this presupposition is additive, H must differ from P in a way that is foregrounded, while otherwise sharing the same background material. Since P is a presupposition, it must be true in the context in which H occurs. In general, then, we can describe too as generating an additive presupposition as follows:Footnote 5

figure h

Points (6a) and (6b) ensure that P contrasts appropriately with H.Footnote 6 That is, (6a) ensures that P is not equal to H, while (6b) requires that P is an element of \(H^F\), the focus value of H, which is the set of alternatives to H that can be constructed by different substitution for any focused elements within H. (6c) ensures that P is true in context, i.e., that it is presupposed.

Our definition assumes P to be propositional, since it is required to be true in (6c). This means both H and P would naturally be associated with sentential syntactic phrases, i.e. TP’s. They can also be associated with DP’s such as “the/a book”, which make a truth-conditional claim of existence. In this paper H and P are restricted to TP’s and such DP’s. We suggest that other sub-sentential syntactic types are not possible for H and P, because they have lambda-bound arguments and thus their truth value in context cannot be meaningfully assessed.

We propose that same and different are additive in precisely the same way as too is. However, unlike too, same and different also involve scope-taking, as we see below.Footnote 7

2.2 The syntax of same and different

Our proposal adapts the approach of Sun (2021), where same is decomposed into two elements: a simple identity relation, \(\lambda x,y.x = y\), which Sun terms IDENT, and a scope taking element, termed -EQTV.Footnote 8 We propose that the scope taking element is TOO, the denotation of the additive particle too, as defined above.

We posit a second meaning for IDENT given in (7). Here IDENT receives an index i, and thus it represents the property of being identical to \(u_i\):

figure j

We require the indexed IDENT to allow for external readings, where there is an antecedent in surrounding context (Hanink (2021) also makes use of an index for external readings, though on her account the index heads its own syntactic phrase). Sun does not consider such external readings, and we would expect that a similarly indexed IDENT would be required for her account to extend to external readings.Footnote 9 We define NOT-IDENT as follows:

figure k

Here then is our proposal:

figure l

A relevant difference between our proposal and Sun’s analysis is that on Sun’s analysis EQVT and IDENT both contribute at-issue meaning in the form of identity relations, whereas on ours only (NOT-)IDENT contributes at-issue meaning and TOO, the correspondent of Sun’s EQVT head, is purely presuppositional. In other words, on our analysis same and different are presupposition triggers, on Sun’s they are not.

Further note that, in our definition of TOO above, the sentence adverbial too is syntactically adjoined to the host H. As an element of same or different, TOO undergoes covert movement, where it moves to a position adjoined to the host.

The claim that same and different take scope has been a widely-held view in the literature going back to the foundational works of Heim (1985) and Carlson (1987), as well as much subsequent work, including Barker (2007), Barker (2012), Hardt et al. (2012), Zhang (2016), Chatain (2020), and Sun (2021).

Let us consider a simple DP, in (11)

figure m

This DP has the following base-generated structure, where EqP stands for Equative Phrase (cf. Sun (2021: (12))):

figure n

We assume TOO raises to adjoin to the DP, as shown below:

figure o

The movement of TOO is motivated by the requirement that the host H be a saturated expression, which was discussed above concerning (6). In its base position TOO is the sister of an unsaturated expression, the NOT-IDENT property, and therefore must move. The DP, as a saturated expression, provides a suitable host.Footnote 10 A related question is why TOO, as part of an AP, is allowed to move. Here we follow Sun’s (2018) analysis of same in comparative constructions, in which EqP raises out of the AP to left-adjoin at the clausal level. We further note that on Bhatt and Pancheva’s (2004) influential analysis of comparatives , DegP -er is a subpart of an AP and moves out of that AP to Merge with the standard clause. We suggest that the three cases are structurally analogous, even if the motivation for the movement differs.

As we saw above, NOT-IDENT\(_i\) represents the property of being not equal to u\(_i\). This combines with the property book by Predicate Modification, giving the property \(\lambda x. x \ne u_i\) & book(x). When combined with the indefinite article a, we get the following logical representation, using DRT-style notation:Footnote 11

figure p

In this example, TOO moves to a position adjoined to the local DP. However, it is not limited to this; TOO can move to higher positions, constrained only by the general conditions governing syntactic movement, giving rise to alternatives in the scope possibilities for TOO. As we will see, these alternative scope possibilities are the key to explaining the observed variations in external and internal readings for same and different.

2.2.1 Definiteness and same/different

Our decomposition of same and different provides a basis for explaining the fact same requires the definite article, while different requires an indefinite. In our account, like that of Sun (2021), a phrase like same boy involves the combining of two properties, IDENT\(_i\), the property of being identical to an individual i, and the property of being a boy. As Sun (2021)[page 7] points out, this means “The phrase same boy ...has at most one individual in its extension ...we can attribute the impossible co-occurrence between same and indefinite determiners ...to the speaker preference of using a linguistic form with a stronger presupposition if that presupposition is satisfied.” Thus “a same boy” conflicts with a preference to maximize presuppositions (Heim, 1991).Footnote 12

An analogous argument explains the preference for the indefinite article with different. With the different NP, the definite article presupposes that NP denotes a singleton set in context. This contradicts the assertion of different, that the individual denoted by NP is non-identical to another individual in context, which means NP must denote a set with at least two elements.

3 External readings as presupposition binding

3.1 Deriving external readings

We can now illustrate the proposal with examples of external readings involving same and different, starting with different in (15):

figure q

We derive the following syntactic representation, shown in (16). Different is represented as TOO NOT-IDENT\(_i\). Here, TOO raises to a position adjoining the local DP.

figure r

We note that both Bao and different naturally receive focus marking here.Footnote 13 The host H is the local DP, which is the sister of TOO. We represent it with DRT-style notation:

figure s

Since different receives focus, the focus value of H is as follows:

figure t

The NOT-IDENT\(_i\) property can vary in the focus value of H. That is, we specify that the focus value consists of all propositions of the form of (18) with a substitution of some property for X. The condition that a property holds of u\(_j\) is essentially vacuous, since there are properties (such as that of being self-identical) that hold of all individuals. Therefore, the presupposed P that is required is simply that there exists a book.

We need to find an antecedent P that satisfies the 3 conditions on TOO. The obvious candidate is the name, War and Peace, which we represent as an individual that has the property of being the book, War and Peace, as follows:

figure u

We consider our conditions (6a)–(6c) in the definition of TOO above. It’s clear that (6a) is satisfied, since H and P do not have the same denotations, and (6c) is also evidently satisfied, since \(u_i\) is already part of the context c. For condition (6b), P must be contained in the focus value of H: to determine this, we note that it is standard to consider contextual and world knowledge in this determination (Rooth, 1992b). In view of this, P is semantically equivalent to P\(^\prime \):

figure v

We can see that P\(^\prime \) is an element of \(H^F\), since they are structurally equivalent, apart from the substitution of the property WP in P\(^\prime \) for the variable X in \(H^F\).

We turn now to an external reading involving same, in (21):

figure w

As in (15), we consider the possibility that TOO raises to the position adjoined to the local DP:

figure x

Now H has the following representation:Footnote 14

figure y

Again we can consider that P would be the book War and Peace, represented as follows (analogous to \(P^{\prime }\) in (20)):

figure z

Observe that, in context c, it is established that u\(_i\) is the book War and Peace, and therefore in this context, H and P have the same denotations. This means that we fail to find appropriate contrast, as condition (6a) is violated. We therefore consider an alternative in which TOO raises to a higher position, as shown in (25):

figure aa

Now, we give the representation for H and for \(H^F\):

figure ab
figure ac

The presupposition can now be satisfied by setting P to the complete preceding sentence, “Daiwen read War and Peace”, represented as follows:

figure ad

It’s clear that (6a) is satisfied since the two sentences have distinct denotations, and (6c) is satisfied since the denotation of P has already been added to the current context, c. The denotation of P is an element of the focus value of H, since the subject Bao is focus-marked. Thus (6b) is also satisfied.

In these two examples, we have seen a difference in the scope of TOO resulting from covert movement. In (15), involving different, TOO raised to a position adjoined to the local DP – an individual-denoting position. In (21), TOO raised to a higher position, adjoined to the containing TP – an eventuality-denoting position. This is quite general – for same, TOO must always move beyond the local DP. Otherwise, H would always have the same denotation as P, thus failing to satisfy the presupposition generated by TOO.

In general, then, different can generate individual or eventuality-sized presuppositions, while same must generate an eventuality-sized presupposition. This difference was noted in Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) and Hardt and Mikkelsen (2020), where stipulations were proposed in terms of the lexical meanings of same and different. Here we show that no such stipulations are required; the difference is derived from the general requirement that an additive presupposition contrasts appropriately with the host, as is known to be the case with too. We will now see how this can explain external and internal readings, as well as the parallelism effects observed with same.

3.2 Deriving parallelism effects

Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) observe three different types of parallelism effects for same, and they note further that these effects do not arise in analogous cases involving different or pronouns. Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) account for this contrast by stipulations concerning the lexical meanings of same vs different; here no such stipulations are required.

3.2.1 Negated antecedent

The first contrast observed by Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) involves negation, as in (29):

figure ae

On our account, (29a) is felicitous because different can generate a DP-sized presupposition host, with TOO raising to adjoin to DP, as we saw in the derivation for (16). This results in the following host:

figure af

As discussed above in Sect. 3.1 (see in particular footnote 13), we assume there is focus on different, thus giving the following focus value for H:

figure ag

The presupposition is the antecedent War and Peace, i.e.,

figure ah

This antecedent satisfies our three conditions: (6a) is satisfied since P differs in denotation from H, and (6c) is satisfied since P is true in context (i.e., the book War and Peace exists). The condition (6b) is satisfied since we can ignore the difference in indexes on u\(_i\) and u\(_j\), and we can assume that there is some property X that holds of u\(_i\).

As we saw above in Sect. 3.1, examples involving same always require a larger presupposition host; TOO must raise higher than the local DP. In this case, TOO must raise high enough to include the contrasting Bao. Thus we have the presupposition host,

figure ai

To satisfy the presupposition, we consider the antecedent Daiwen didn’t read War and Peace. Because of the negation, there is not appropriate contrast between (29) and (29b). The focus value of the host is the set of propositions of the form, X read book(u\(_j\)), and the negated antecedent, Daiwen didn’t read War and Peace, is not an element of that set. A potential alternative is to raise the negation as follows:

figure aj

In this case, the embedded drs denotes the proposition, Daiwen read War and Peace, which is an element of the host focus value as required. However, this is ruled out in our approach since it is not true in context.

3.2.2 Parallel antecedent

The second contrast is illustrated by (35):

figure ak

Consider first the case of different – here, we select a different book as H, and the DP War and Peace serves as P, satisfying the appropriate contrast condition. For same the containing DP is not an option as H for reasons discussed above; instead we select the containing TP, Hien read the same book. The only option for P is Daiwen praised War and Peace, but here the appropriate contrast condition fails because ‘Daiwen praised War and Peace’ is not a member of the focus semantic value of ‘Hien read War and Peace’.Footnote 15

A reviewer provides the examples in (36b) and (37b) and suggests that they violate parallelism and yet are felicitous. (We have added focus accents to these examples.)

figure al
figure am

At first glance, it appears that (36a) is not in the focus semantic value of (36b), though this is required by the conditions imposed by TOO. However, according to Rooth (1992a) (pp. 8–9), the calculation of focus semantic values does not require syntactic isomorphism, but allows for semantic inferences. From The same book impressed her brother, we can infer that Daiwen’s brother had a positive reaction to War and Peace. Focus accent on impress therefore includes people having other reactions to War and Peace, including someone hating the book.

We propose a similar explanation for (37). From the host clause in (37b), we can infer that Beloved won a prize, since receiving a prize entails winning a prize. The focus accent on another further means that the focus semantic value of (37b) includes Beloved winning the Pulitzer prize.

3.2.3 Distinct antecedent

Following an observation of Hardt et al. (2012), Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) argue that same gives rise to a “distinct antecedent” requirement: the eventuality denoted by the host must be distinct from the eventuality denoted by the antecedent. Example (38) illustrates.Footnote 16

figure an

As Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) point out, the most natural reading for (38a) is that there is a single fish-catching event, and on that reading, (38a) is felicitous while (38b) is not.

To see why (38b) is infelicitous, consider the options for the host H. We have already seen that, with same, H can never be the denotation of the immediately containing DP, since there won’t be appropriate contrast. But since here we have the same event, larger containing constituents also fail to exhibit appropriate contrast. If the host H is the containing TP, both H and P will denote the same event, thus again leading to infelicity.

This applies only on the same-event reading of (38); as Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) also noted, (38b) is felicitous if one interprets it as referring to different fish-catching events. This can be facilitated with contrasting modifiers, as shown in (39), which does satisfy appropriate contrast.

figure ao

Here the antecedent P is contained in the focus value of H, since we have contrasting manner modifiers, namely with a nice fishing pole and without any fishing equipment. This forces a multiple event interpretation, where Daiwen somehow catches the same fish on two different occasions. Thus our presuppositional account correctly rules out (38b) while allowing for the acceptable (39).Footnote 17

This concludes our discussion of external readings of same and different and we now turn to internal readings.

4 Internal readings as accommodation

4.1 Deriving internal readings

Example (40) involves an internal reading for different. We propose that it has the LF structure in (41).Footnote 18

figure aq
figure ar

As we see in (41), TOO raises to adjoin to TP, and every boy raises to adjoin above TOO. The semantic representation of (41) is the drs in (42).

figure as

This is a tripartite quantificational structure, as is familiar from DRT. Note that we repeat the condition boy x in the nuclear scope, as well as in the restrictor. In the above structure, it is redundant to repeat boy x in the nuclear scope, since the same condition is applied to x in the restrictor. However, this condition will make a substantive contribution in the definition of the presupposition host and the resulting accommodation. This follows a general principle, which Pasternak (2020: 6) terms the Interpreted Lower Restrictor Hypothesis (ILRH), and describes as follows: “When a DP of the form [\(_{\textsc {dp}}\) D NP] undergoes movement, NP is also semantically interpreted at the trace position, so that after lambda abstraction the resulting predicate is restricted to individuals in [[NP]].”

Pasternak points out that the ILRH principle has been widely discussed in recent years, building on proposals of Fox (2002, 2003). Pasternak (p.5) points out that there have been “several empirical arguments...in favor of ILRH”, noting that Erlewine (2014) applies this approach to issues involving association with focus, and he argues further that a puzzle involving Antecedent-Contained Deletion (ACD) provides “particularly compelling evidence for ILRH”, citing an account due to Sauerland (1998) and Sauerland (2004). Furthermore, according to Pasternak, ILRH has been used by authors such as Fox (2002), Sportiche (2005), and Romoli (2015) “to account for the famed conservativity hypothesis” of Barwise and Cooper (1981) and Keenan and Stavi (1986). As we will see, ILRH plays a key role in the account of internal readings; thus, we argue that this constitutes an additional piece of evidence supporting ILRH.

As usual, we determine the host, H, as the sister to TOO; in (42), this is the following:

figure at

We observe that different is focus-marked, and therefore the condition \(y \ne z\) is replaced with a variable in the focus value of H:

figure au

Since there is no overt antecedent in context, the presupposition P cannot be bound, and therefore must be accommodated. In general, an accommodated presupposition P must closely match H semantically, except for focused elements. We suggest that there is some flexibility in terms of variable binding, in the construction of an accommodated P. In particular, the accommodated material P is constructed from H with the following optional changes:

  1. 1.

    Bound variables in H can be renamed in P

  2. 2.

    Free variables in H can receive a binder in P

This means that an accommodated P will only differ with H with respect to focused material or to indexing.Footnote 19 Here we rename variables x and y as u and z respectively, and we bind u in the drs for P. Furthermore, we omit the focus-marked condition \(y \ne z\) – as described above with respect to external readings, the condition that some property holds of an individual is essentially vacuous, thus we can ignore this condition in the construction of P:

figure av

Following van der Sandt (1992), accommodated content can occur at various accessible points, as defined in DRT. In our example there are three accessible points: the first is the VP or nuclear scope. We term this in-situ accommodation. The second accessible point is the restrictor, and the third is the context preceding (40); in DRT terms this is the top level. Here we pursue the second option, accommodation to the restrictor. Below we will make some remarks on the other two alternatives.

By accommodating the presupposed P to the restrictor, we get the following, with the accommodated material underlined.

figure aw

The underlined material is P as defined above. It is here that the relevance of ILRH becomes clear—this is the requirement that leads to a copy of boy x appearing in H. When this is copied to the restrictor, we then have two predications of distinct boys, which is important in deriving the internal reading correctly. There is one additional condition: \(u \ne x\). Hardt and Mikkelsen (2020) argue that this is a general condition on accommodation, to ensure that an accommodated variable is distinct from currently defined variables.

Recall that TOO gives rise to three conditions on the presupposition P. First, condition (6a) is satisfied: \(P \ne H\), since we have stipulated that \(u \ne x\). Condition (6b) is also satisfied, based on the (reasonable) assumption that x receives focus in H. Finally, condition (6c) requires that P is true in the context in which H occurs. This must be true, since the input context for the nuclear scope (H) is the output context of the restrictor (P). That is, anything asserted in the restrictor will be true in the context of the nuclear scope; since P is asserted in the restrictor, it is true in the input context for the H. We conclude that the presupposition generated by TOO is satisfied. Furthermore, (46) has the desired truth conditions: for every pair of boys x and u and book z such that u read z, there is a book y that x read, and the two books, y and z, are not identical.

Notice that we allow every to capture all 3 free variables in the restrictor; that is, we allow unselective binding. This is a basic feature of DRT, where an operator can be interpreted to range over each variable occurring free in the restrictor, as introduced in Heim (1982) and Kamp (1981). This is exactly what is desired here – we wish to consider all triplets \(<x,u,z>\) where x and u are boys, and z is a book that u read. (Equivalent for our purposes is a situation-based alternative (Heim, 1991; Elbourne, 2001) in which the restrictor ranges over minimal situations – in this case, the relevant triplets of boys and books. Moltmann (1992) is a somewhat similar alternative.)

We provide an analogous account for internal readings with same, as in (47):

figure ax
figure ay

This yields the tripartite drs in (49):

figure az

Here we identify the presupposition host H:

figure ba

We observe that same is focus-marked, and therefore the condition \(y = z\) is replaced with a variable in the focus value of H:

figure bb

Next, we construct P from H, just as we did for example (42) above – again we can ignore the property variable condition X(y) and we rename y as z and x as u, resulting in:

figure bc

Finally, P is accommodated into the restrictor (shown underlined in (53)):

figure bd

This gives the desired meaning: for every pair of boys x and u and book z such that u read z, there is a book y that x read, and the two books, y and z, are identical.

As Carlson (1987, p. 532) points out, a sentence with an internal reading “provides its own context”, which can be seen as another way of saying that it relies on accommodation. Of course these same sentences can occur in a context where no accommodation is needed, as in (54):

figure be

In this case, an external reading is possible, where every boy read a book that was not War and Peace.

4.2 Alternative accommodation sites

We have seen how internal readings in (40) and (47) can be derived through accommodation of a presupposed P to the restrictor. In principle, van der Sandt (1992) would argue that the presupposed P could be accommodated at three different positions:

  1. 1.

    Top Level

  2. 2.

    Restrictor

  3. 3.

    Nuclear Scope

Accommodation to the restrictor is often the preferred option, as noted by van der Sandt concerning his example (53)) (van der Sandt, 1992), p 363:

figure bf

This receives the following representation, with presupposed material underlined:

figure bg

The presupposed material is accommodated to the restrictor drs, as follows:

figure bh

As van der Sandt notes, this captures the reading, “Every man who has a wife loves her”, which, he argues, is the most natural reading. Similarly, we find that accommodation to the restrictor gives the most natural reading for our examples (40) and (47).Footnote 20

In our judgement, these examples do not have natural readings associated with the alternative accommodation sites. It is notoriously difficult to determine the conditions under which a given accommodation is possible; here, we offer some suggestions concerning this particular case. We begin with the lowest-level reading, where the presupposition is accommodated within the nuclear scope, as follows:

figure bi

This would be true as long as we can find, for each boy, some other boy who read a different book. This is a weaker reading than we derived above by accommodation to the restrictor. It would be true, for example, if nine boys read War and Peace and a single boy read The Color Purple. We don’t find this to be a possible reading; according to van der Sandt (1992) there is a general preference, such that, with a choice of accommodating to a higher or lower position, the higher choice is preferred. This would explain why accommodation to the restrictor is preferred over accommodation to the nuclear scope.

We turn now to the other alternative, involving accommodation to the top level, as shown in (59)):

figure bj

Here, we have an assertion that some boy u read some book z, and then it is asserted that every boy read a book that is not equal to z. This, of course, is an external reading for different. In general, accommodation does not seem to be possible for external readings for same and different. An out-of-the-blue assertion of (60) or (61) is infelicitous.

figure bk
figure bl

Same and different pattern with too in this way; Kripke (2009) notes that accommodation with the additive presupposition trigger too is infelicitious in (62):

figure bm

Kripke (2009) points out that accommodation is infelicitous here, despite the fact that one can of course infer that someone else is having dinner in New York. Heim’s (1992) proposes that (62) is infelicitous because too requires a salient alternative to Sam (p. 189; see also Geurts and van der Sandt (2004) and Grubic (2019) for relevant discussion). More concretely, we would say that the relevant alternative has not been introduced into the discourse context. Similarly with (60) and (61): the context does not provide for a salient individual other than Sam leading to presupposition failure. Heim formalizes this analysis of too as in (63).

figure bn

Crucially for our purposes the presupposition contains a variable, \(x_i\). In the infelicitous examples above, that variable cannot be resolved as the context fails to make an antecedent available; there is no salient alternative to Sam. Thus (60) and (61) are infelicitous for the same reason as (62); this provides further support for our proposal that same and different generate the same presupposition as too.

Note that, when the presupposition is accommodated into the restrictor, the accommodated variable is an element of the set that is the domain of every boy. We would suggest that the accommodated variable has therefore already been introduced into the context, and thus accommodation is permitted.

4.3 Multiple occurrences

We now turn to cases involving two occurrences of different or same, such as the following:Footnote 21

figure bq

In our view, the truth conditions are as follows: for every pair of linguists \(<l_1, l_2>\) there are papers \(p_1,p_2\) and conferences \(c_1,c_2\) such that \(l_1\) sent \(p_1\) to \(c_1\), and \(l_2\) sent \(p_2\) to \(c_2\) and \(p_1\) \(\ne \) \(p_2\) and \(c_1\) \(\ne \) \(c_2\).

We derive the following drs, following the same approach outlined in Sect. 4.1, where each occurrence of different is represented as TOO NOT-IDENT, and each occurrence of TOO is adjoined to the nuclear scope.

figure br

For each occurrence of different, there is a TOO adjoined to the nuclear scope. Both TOO’s generate a presupposition based on the host to which it is adjoined. If we consider the innermost TOO first, we accommodate its presupposition by copying to the restrictor, giving the following (accommodated material underlined):

figure bs

Just as with example (40), the accommodated material satisfies the presupposition of the innermost TOO. We now turn to the outermost TOO, and we observe that its presupposition is exactly the same as the innermost TOO. This is because the presupposition is determined by the host H, which in turn is fully determined by propositional content. Since, we claim, TOO adds nothing to propositional content, both occurrences of TOO have an identical host H and thus generate an identical presupposition. Thus the accommodated material satisfies the presupposition for the outermost TOO as well.

4.4 Too and internal readings

Our analysis draws a close parallel between same and different, on the one hand, and too on the other. In light of that it is initially surprising that too doesn’t allow internal readings. This is seen in (67), which cannot mean ‘There is a book that every boy read’ on analogy with (68).

figure bt
figure bu

One might expect (67) to exhibit an internal reading, since too has the same presupposition as same and we derive the internal readings for same based on the presupposition it generates, which is then accommodated in the restrictor. Specifically one could contemplate a similar derivation involving too for (67):

figure bv

Just as with same, here we would get the following host H and accommodate P:

Presupposition host H:

figure bw

Construct P to satisfy H:

figure bx

Then P would be accommodated to the restrictor, resulting in the following representation:

figure by

However, this is not possible for too. We tentatively suggest that this relates to the fact that too is syntactically adjoined to the matrix clause in example (67), while same or different appear syntactically within the nuclear scope. As we discussed in Sect. 4, internal readings for same and different involve movement of TOO to a higher position in the tree; namely, it is adjoined to the nuclear scope. For too, this would require movement to a lower position in the tree, and we suggest that, at least in this case, such lowering is ruled out.

4.5 Island sensitivity

On our proposal, external readings involving same require movement of TOO to a higher position, to satisfy appropriate contrast, while this is not true of different. This suggests that external readings with same are subject to island constraints.Footnote 22 In our judgment, this is correct, as illustrated by (73):

figure bz

Here TOO must raise to adjoin to the matrix clause, which means it must escape the wh-island produced by why, and indeed we find (73) rather degraded; on the other hand, we find (74) to be fully acceptable, with different substituted for same:

figure ca

We see a similar effect with the following example involving an adjunct island:

figure cb

Again, we find different fully acceptable, while same is somewhat degraded.

These cases reflect a basic feature of our account: same must always move so that it adjoins to a host that contrasts appropriately with an antecedent. In (73) and (75), the material within the island does not satisfy appropriate contrast, which forces same to move beyond the island, thus giving rise to the violation. If there is contrasting material within the island, same is not required to move beyond the island, and thus the violation does not arise. This is illustrated by the following variantFootnote 23 to (73):

figure cc

Here we have contrasting material (sabotaged, next day) within the embedded clause, which means that same is not required to move out of the island. In this case we detect no ill-formedness.

These judgments are delicate, and we performed an informal pilot study to explore them further. In our study, over sixty respondents were asked to rate sentences from 1 (perfect) to 5 (unacceptable). They gave an average score of 2.4 to example (73), while (74) received a score of 1.9. Similarly with example (75), the version with same received a score of 2.04, while the score with different was 1.4.

These results support our prediction that such examples with same are degraded compared to their counterparts with different. However, one might object that the examples with same receive an intermediate status, and indeed in our survey the counterparts of the above examples involving overt wh movement receive notably worse scores. We suggest that this relates to the type of violation involved with the movement of TOO with same and different. In our view, the violation is a pragmatic one, since TOO is required to move to produce a host whose presupposition can be satisfied. Thus it is not surprising that such violations are not as strongly felt as those involving syntactic ill-formedness.

It has previously been observed that same and different are subject to island constraints for internal readings. For example (77) is a variant of example (6a) from Carlson (1987):

figure cd

We agree with Carlson’s judgment that such an example is degraded, with different as well as same. This follows from the fact that same or different appears here within a wh-island, and the internal reading requires that TOO move from its surface position to adjoin to the nuclear scope, thus giving rise to a wh-island violation.

5 Comparatives

We have proposed that same and different both involve the additive presuppositional operator TOO, which, we argue, can move covertly to take various higher scope positions. We have shown that this allows us to derive a variety of observations, by relying on standard mechanisms of presupposition binding and accommodation. A key observation is that, with same, TOO must raise higher than the containing DP; otherwise it fails to satisfy the general conditions imposed by TOO. Here we show that this provides a solution to a puzzle first noted by Heim (1985:21-22), in her discussion of same and different comparative-like constructions, such as (78) :

figure ce

Heim notes that, (78b) “is, for some reason, very marginal” while (78a) is fully acceptable.Footnote 24

Our explanation of this puzzle is straightforward: same and different differ in the size of presupposition they trigger: as we have seen, same cannot generate a presupposition based on the containing DP; instead it must raise to a higher position in determining the presupposition. On the other hand, different allows for a presupposition based on the containing DP, as well as larger constituents. In the above examples, only the local DP presupposition can be satisfied. This means that same should be infelicitous and different should be felicitous.

We begin with the unproblematic (79): here, same and different are both felicitous.

figure cf

To apply our approach to such examples involving comparatives/equatives, we use a simplified version of the approach in Sun (2021).Footnote 25 First, note that here we use the relational (NOT-)IDENT. Second, that the standard phrase, as Don Cherry (played), appears at LF as a complement to same (TOO IDENT), as shown in (80):

figure cg

We raise TOO to the TP level and then raise the IDENT as-clause (Sun, 2021)[page 6] resulting in (81):

figure ch

Following Sun (2021)[page 7], we treat than/as as binder of u – the tune Don Cherry played; we also provide an OP that binds z – the index of the tune that Ornette Coleman played. Again following Sun (2021), we interpret these binders as lambda abstractors. On Sun’s account, this results in two properties or sets of individuals, whose maximal elements are then required to be identical. We take a different approach, inspired by Hanink (2021), where the resultant properties are converted to individual-denoting expressions as a result of iota-conversion, as shown in (82):Footnote 26

figure ci

IDENT is applied to its two arguments, represented by (82) (b) and (c), resulting in:

figure cj

This gives the desired reading for (78a): the tune played by Don Cherry is identical to the tune played by Ornette Coleman. Consider now the presupposition generated by TOO. The host H is represented as follows:

figure ck

With Ornette Coleman receiving focus-marking, the focus value of H is the following:

figure cl
figure cm

This satisfies the conditions on TOO, since P is true in context, and not identical to H, but it is in the focus value of H, since Don Cherry in P can be substituted for X in H, and i denotes the same tune as z.

We won’t provide the derivation for (78b) here – it is precisely the same, except we substitute NON-IDENT for IDENT and than for as. We turn now to the contrast between the acceptable (78a) and the degraded (78b). We begin by showing how the meaning is derived for the acceptable (78a):

figure cn

As before, we raise TOO to take scope over the containing DP. Also, NOT-IDENT and its complement than-Phrase is raised to adjoin to the matrix TP. This is shown in (88).

figure co
figure cp

We apply NOT-IDENT to (89) a and b above, which results in the following semantic representation:

figure cq

That is, the tune played by Ornette Coleman is not equal to the tune picked out by the demonstrative “this one”. This is the desired reading, for the acceptable (78a). We now turn our attention to TOO; as usual, TOO plays no role in the derivation of at-issue meaning, but rather, places a presuppositional constraint. In the tree in (88), we can see that the Host determined by TOO is the DP [a\(_z\) tune], with the drs in (91):

figure cr

The presupposed P is as follows:

figure cs

We consider the three conditions on acceptability for P and H: first, they differ in their denotation. As discussed above in Sect. 3.1, we reason that different is focus-marked, and therefore the focus value of H is represented as follows:

figure ct

That is, the focus value is the set of individuals that are tunes and have some additional property X, where X represents the substitution resulting from focus on different. We conclude that P is an element of the focus value of H. Finally, P is true in context, since the tune designated by this one exists, as asserted by P. Since the presupposition P satisfies the requirements imposed by TOO, example (78a) is felicitous.

We now turn to the degraded (78b), repeated here:

figure cu

The derivation proceeds exactly as the derivation for (78a) above, resulting in a tree similar to (88) – the only difference being IDENT appearing in place of NOT-IDENT. This again gives the following candidates for H and P:

figure cv

However, in this case the presupposition is not satisfied, since H is identical to P – that is, they both denote the same tune. This violates the requirement for appropriate contrast. As we saw above, this is a general fact about same – it must raise higher than the local containing DP, to the level of the containing TP, giving the following structure:

figure cw

In this case, H = [Ornette Coleman played z ]. There is no P in context that would appropriately contrast with H; there is no TP-sized P that is available to satisfy the presupposition hosted by H.

The contrast between (78b) and (78a), we propose, is due to the lack of a binder for an TP-sized presupposition. In other words, these are unreduced phrasal comparatives in the terms of Bhatt and Takahashi (2011). There is no underlying clausal source. Instead the standard is just a DP. This is sufficient for different which allows for a DP-sized presupposition and hence (78a) is well-formed.Footnote 27

We end this section with a brief discussion of our analysis as it relates to Bhatt and Takahashi’s (2011) influential analysis of English (and Hindi) comparative constructions. The unreduced phrasal comparatives in (78) are noteworthy because Bhatt and Takahashi (2011: 586–590) argue that English does not have unreduced phrasal comparatives. At first the two proposals thus seem to be at odds with each other, but we suggest that in fact the data above lends indirect support to Bhatt and Takahashi’s (2011) argument. The key observation is that Bhatt and Takahashi’s (2011) claim is based on the nature of the degree head in English and the comparatives in (78) do not involve degrees. Rather, they involve comparison of individuals, what Heim (1985: 22) calls “identity comparisons”; see also Charnavel (2015:138). Since Bhatt and Takahashi (2011) attribute the unavailability of unreduced comparatives to the nature of the degree head (a 2-place degree head, as opposed to a 3-place degree head), there is no expectation that it extends to non-degree comparatives like the ones in (78). In fact, one could argue that the contrasting behavior of degree and non-degree comparatives favors Bhatt and Takahashi’s (2011) proposal over an alternative that posits a general ban on unreduced comparatives in English. We conclude that the comparatives in (78) are unreduced phrasal comparatives and that this conclusion is consistent with Bhatt and Takahashi’s (2011) analysis of degree comparatives.

6 Related work

In this section we discuss four aspects of our analysis as they relate to prior work on same and different. The first aspect is what we call uniformity - that a single analysis accounts for all three uses of same and different: external, internal and comparatives. Second we discuss scope-taking for same and different, which is an important idea in much of the literature. Third, we examine lexical decomposition of same and different, and finally, we consider presupposition as it has arisen in previous work.

6.1 Uniformity

We have considered same and different as found in the following three environments:

figure cy

In our account, a single lexical entry for each of same and different derives their external, internal and comparative uses. The differences between the readings come down to how the additive presupposition is satisfied. In external readings the additive presupposition is bound by preceding material (Hien read War and Peace in example (97)). In comparative readings the presupposition is bound by the material in the as-clause (as Bao did). Finally, in internal readings, the presupposition is accommodated.

Most earlier work focuses on a subset of these three readings. For instance, Carlson (1987) and Barker (2007) focus on internal readings. In fact, Barker goes as far as to argue against unifying the analysis of external uses (his ‘deictic’ use) and internal uses of same (p. 413ff). Sun (2021), focuses on internal and comparative readings, while leaving the external readings aside. Brasoveanu (2011) analyzes both internal and external readings but does not discuss comparative readings, and his account focuses almost entirely on different.

Heim (1985) focuses on internal readings; however, her analysis, which applies to comparatives and superlatives as well as same and different, also provides for external readings, in the following way: the general analysis applies a comparison operator to two entities on a dimension f – that is, \(OP<a,b> f\). The second entity b is typically provided by a than-clause or of-clause. However, Heim notes, in an example like “Daiwen sang the loudest”, the comparison set “needs to be supplied pragmatically”, which is represented as follows:

figure cz

In general, Heim allows the comparison element to be supplied pragmatically, which is simply indicated by .... This allows for external readings for same and different, as well as for superlatives and comparatives.

In unpublished work, Matushansky (2011) argues for a uniform account of same and different in the three environments we are considering. Her argument for this is similar to ours in that it defines same as IDENT and different as NOT-IDENT. However, her account does not involve the presuppositional and additive nature of same and different, which is essential to our account. Because of this, Matushansky’s account does not explain the many differences between same and different, such as the parallelism effects (Sect. 3.2) and Heim’s observation concerning comparatives (Sect. 5). Finally, Charnavel (2015) presents a uniform account for same and different as well as other terms of similarity and difference. This account relies on the postulation of a variety of silent structures. For example, Charnavel considers the following external use of different (her 6\(^\prime \)):

figure da

Here, Charnavel postulates a silent from X, where X is a pronoun. Then the pronoun is resolved in the normal way—in this case, selecting the antecedent Frida. Charnavel also considers internal occurrences of different (her 12\(^\prime \)):

figure db

Here the silent material is than X, where X can be interpreted as a reciprocal, which, Charnavel argues, gives rise to the desired internal reading. Our approach does not require this extensive postulation of silent structures; also, Charnavel’s account does not address most of the central phenomena addressed here, including parallelism effects and the analogies with too. Charnavel (2015) conducts a survey of eighteen languages, finding that the same word is almost always used for internal, external, and comparative readings of same.Footnote 28 This strong cross-linguistic tendency for internal, external, and comparative readings to be expressed identically supports the kind of uniform approach we have proposed here.

6.2 Scope

The claim that same and different can take scope plays a key role in our proposed account; it also figures prominently in prior literature on same and different. Heim (1985, p.25) notes that “For the comparison operators same and different ...their scopes obey the same constraints as wh-movement”. Similarly, Carlson (1987, p. 534), in his consideration of internal readings, argues that “the licensing NP must appear within the same ‘scope domain’ as the dependent expression [i.e., same or different] ...the two NP positions must be relatable by Move Alpha, in a GB framework”. These claims are taken for granted in much subsequent work: as mentioned above, Barker (2007) argues that same must take scope in internal readings; Hardt et al. (2012, p. 341) argue that “same must take scope over a containing event-denoting expression ...the scope-taking of same is subject to standard island constraints”.

While the idea that same and different can take scope is a quite familiar one, our proposal is novel in the following way: for us, what the scope determines is the particular presuppositions generated by the TOO operator. In addition, our account generates novel predictions concerning island constraints for external readings, as described in Sect. 4.5.

6.3 Decomposition

It is a central feature of our proposal that it is decompositional – we decompose same into IDENT and TOO and different into NOT-IDENT and TOO. In this, we follow Sun (2021) who decomposes same into IDENT and an equative head EQTV. Similarly, Heim (1985:23) decomposes same and different into a comparison operator and a ‘predicate remainder’ – “y-JENIG(x)” or “y-ARTIG(x)”. In each of these accounts, the decomposition results in a scope-taking element that moves at LF, and another element that remains in place. In both Sun’s and Heim’s accounts, decomposition for same and different is motivated by the analogy with comparatives. In the case of comparatives, the scope-taking operator, -er, is morphologically identifiable. This is not the case for same and different; here, the decomposition in Sun’s and Heim’s accounts has an air of redundancy. Consider Heim’s analysis of same, which is decomposed into an operator, which is essentially simple identity, and a predicate remainder, y-JENIG(x). As Heim (1985:23) herself points out, “y-JENIG(x) is plainly the identity relation \(x=y\)”. Similarly, Sun (2018) decomposes same into IDENT and an equative head EQTV, both of which amount to identity relations. By contrast, on our account, same is decomposed into an identity relation IDENT, which remains in-situ, and a scope-taking element TOO which plays a quite distinct semantic role. As we have shown, this is what makes it possible to capture the presuppositional semantics of same and different. Our proposal also raises the question whether there are languages in which a morpheme meaning too is part of the expression of same. At present, we do not know of any such languages, but the possibility remains.

6.4 Presupposition

A core contribution of our proposal involves the presuppositional nature of same and different. In Hardt et al. (2012), it is claimed that same is presuppositional, on an analogy with TOO. However, there is no suggestion related to different; also, the proposal is limited to external readings. Hardt and Mikkelsen (2020) expands on this, proposing that both same and different are presuppositional, and showing how internal and external readings correspond to the accommodation and binding of presuppositions. The current account builds directly on this proposal, expanding on it in important ways. A crucial difference is that we propose a specific decomposition of same and different into (NOT-)IDENT and TOO. This makes it possible to provide explicit syntactic derivations which illustrate the different scope-taking possibilities of TOO, something that is completely absent from the account in Hardt and Mikkelsen (2020). This allows us to account for the parallelism effects of Hardt and Mikkelsen (2015) in a way that, we argue, is more theoretically economical than that of Hardt and Mikkelsen (2020). Furthermore, we show that a range of other empirical consequences follow from our proposal, including the complementary distribution with too, as well as contrasts between same and different in certain comparative constructions.

7 Conclusions

It has been widely accepted, at least since Carlson (1987), that same and different involve scope-taking in some form. We have argued that the point of this movement is to establish a particular additive presupposition, and we have shown that this provides a novel, uniform account of internal, external and comparative uses. In particular, the distinction between external and internal readings emerges as the familiar distinction between presupposition binding and accommodation. We have shown that, by attending to the details of the binding or accommodation of the relevant presuppositions, it is possible to account for the phenomena of internal, external and comparative readings of same and different, without positing any additional mechanisms.

At a more general level, this paper has shown that additive presuppositions are not restricted to particles like too, also, and as well, but also arise with other syntactic forms, specifically adjectives. Left unexplained, however, is why additive presuppositions arise with these particular lexical items; we suspect that cross-linguistic investigation might shed some light on this.