Skip to main content
Log in

On the difference between the ‘In’ and ‘According to’ operators

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Semanticists and philosophers of fiction that formulate analyses of reports on the content of media—or ‘contensive statements’—of the form ‘In/According to s, \(\phi \)’, usually treat the ‘In s’-operator (In) and the ‘According to s’-operator (Acc) on a par. I argue that In and Acc require separate semantic analyses based on three clusters of linguistic observations: (1) preferences for In or Acc in contensive statements about fictional or non-fictional media, (2) preferences for In or Acc in contensive statements about implicit or explicit content and (3) tense preferences in contensive statements with In and Acc. To account for these three observations I propose to adopt Lewis’s possible world analysis for contensive statements with In and to analyse contensive statements with Acc as indirect speech reports.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terminology is originally Voltolini’s (2006). I use the terms as Recanati (2018) does.

  2. Most theorists take parafictional statements to also have implicit variants where the fiction operator is covert (e.g., “Bilbo travels to the Lonely Mountain”). Moreover, as Sainsbury (2014) notes, parafictional discourse can also feature other fiction operators such as ‘partial fiction operators’ like ‘In/According to the first three chapters of s’ or fiction operators such as ‘It is argued in/clear by s that’. Following Voltolini (2019), I take these to be derivative of the In and Acc operators.

  3. Notable exceptions are Dohrn (2015) (whose observations are discussed in this paper), Sainsbury (2014) and Voltolini (2019). The latter two authors argue that In involves a more ‘distanced’ stance towards the fiction than Acc. However, these authors do not discuss the linguistic observations concerning the diverging behaviour of In and Acc discussed in the current paper. Rather, part of their debate is on whether the following minimal pair illustrates the semantic difference between In and Acc:

    figure b

    Whereas Sainsbury takes (Ia) to be true and (Ib) false, Voltolini takes both to be false. I do not further discuss these types of statements in this paper since my focus lies on the use of In and Acc in parafictional statements and both (Ia) and (Ib) seem to have a distinct ‘metafictional’ flavour, i.e., talk about fictional entities as fictional entities (see e.g., Kripke (2011), Recanati (2018), Semeijn and Zalta (2021)).

  4. See Lewis’s (1978) Analysis 1 and 2, Ryan’s (1980) Principle of Minimal Departure, Walton’s (1990) Reality and Mutual Belief Principles, and Friend’s (2017) Reality Assumption.

  5. Interestingly, Dohrn (2015) and Zucchi (2021) also note this about Acc but do not distinguish between In and Acc in this respect, i.e., they judge statements such as (13) to be equally inappropriate or odd (see (Dohrn, 2015, p.51) and (Zucchi, 2021, p.126, footnote 24)).

  6. This example is taken from the online grammar platform Scribbr which advises writers to use simple present to report on the content of fictions, except is cases such as (24) that involve relative past tense constructions.

  7. I assume that nonverbal media are also ROI subjects and hence we also report on those as ‘telling us’ things. In case the reader thinks nonverbal media don’t assert in this way, they may read for instance ‘the Star Wars saga’ as ‘the script of the Star Wars saga’.

  8. More precisely, someone’s doxastic commitments are determined by their assertions and their retractions. This points to a potential benefit of the ROI analysis; Whereas doxastic commitments can be retracted, the fact that p was asserted cannot. Consider the case in which John earlier asserted that seagulls were the best but later took that back and has now asserted that seagulls are the worst. It is still true that John asserted that seagulls are the best. However, it is false that John’s (current) doxastic commitments entail that seagulls are the best. Importantly, it also seems false to say that according to John, seagulls are the best. In response to this we may add the qualification of talking about an agent’s unretracted assertions to the analysis of the phrase ‘According to s, p’ in terms of assertion.

  9. See e.g., Brasoveanu and Farkas (2007), Sæbø (2013), Bary and Maier (2020), Abreu Zavaleta (2019) for some further discussion on this topic.

  10. See e.g., Currie (1990), García-Carpintero (2013), Friend (2011), Stock (2011).

  11. The equivalent situation for the Anne/Chrissy case would be if Anne made a series of assertions and one can ‘read between the lines’ that she indirectly meant to make an additional claim (e.g., that Chrissy is not to be trusted).

  12. There is a potential source of terminological confusion here. General lessons that we may draw from fictions (e.g., that love conquers all) are not ‘implicit fictional truths’ in the sense described here; It is not content that is mere background information assumed to be common ground between author and audience. As discussed in Sect. 5.1, I assume that these general truths are part of what is asserted by the medium, albeit indirectly (i.e., it is part of the ‘explicit’ content in this sense).

  13. Reports with past or future tense attitude verbs (see e.g.,‘Adeela believed/will believe that Sara is nervous’) pose additional complications since tense in these reports can be bound rather than indexical (see e.g., Abusch (1997), Toshyuki and Sharvit (2012)).

  14. In fact, Lewis (1978) uses both past and present tense in his examples of parafictional truths.

  15. See Zucchi (2001) for an alternative possible world analysis of In that accounts for this present tense preference by switching the time of evaluation to the time of the described events.

  16. The same reasoning applies to contensive statements with In that report on non-fiction (e.g., (10)) which thus also display a preference for present tense (cf. Zucchi (2001)):

    figure aq
  17. See e.g., Abusch (1997). In English, sequence of tense for instance occurs in indirect speech reports on past events. Suppose that Adeela at \(t_{1}\) said: “Sara is nervous”. If, at a later point \(t_{2}\), I would report on this speech act, I would say:

    figure ar

    Because the main verb of (VI) (i.e., “asserted”) is in past tense, the subordinate verb (i.e., “was”) ‘shifts back’ to past tense as well (even though Adeela’s utterance itself was in present tense).

References

  • Abreu Zavaleta, M. (2019). Weak speech reports. Philosophical Studies, 176(8), 2139–2166. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1119-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abusch, D. (1997). Sequence of tense and temporal de re. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20(1), 1–50. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005331423820

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, P., & Hacquard, V. (2014). Factivity, belief and discourse. L. Crnič & U. Sauerland (Eds.), The art and craft of semantics: A festschrift for irene heim (Vol. 1, pp. 69-90). MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.

  • Anand, P., & Korotkova, N. (2019). Speech reports. (lecture notes. http://esslli2019.folli.info/courses/speech-reports/)

  • Bary, C., & Maier, E. (2020). The landscape of speech reporting. (manuscript. https://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/003526)

  • Bauer, M., & Beck, S. (2014). On the meaning of fictional texts. D. Gutzman, J. Köpping, & C. Meier (Eds.), Approaches to meaning: Composition, values, and interpretation (Vol. 32, p. 250-275). BRILL.

  • Bauer, M., & Beck, S. (2021). Isomorphic mapping in fictional interpretation. E. Maier & A. Stokke (Eds.), The language of fiction (pp. 277–300). Oxford University Press.

  • Berbeira Gardón, J.L. (2006). On the semantics and pragmatics of will. M. Carretero et al. (Eds.), A pleasure of life in words: A festschrift for Angela Downing (pp. 445–465). Universidad Complutense de Madrid.

  • Brasoveanu, A., & Farkas, D. (2007). Say reports, assertion events and meaning dimensions. G. Alboiu, A. Avram, L. Avram, & D. Isac (Eds.), Pitar mos: A building with a view. papers in honour of Alexandra Cornilescu (pp. 175–196). Editura Universitǎţii din Bucureşt.

  • Bryson, S. (2014). Scribbr post: Verb tenses in academic writing rules, differences & examples. Retrieved from https://www.scribbr.com/language-rules/tenses/#::text=There%20are%20three%20main

  • Carlson, G. N. (1982). Generic terms and generic sentences. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11(2), 145–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00278382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1990). The nature of fiction. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dohrn, D. (2015). According to the fiction: A metaexpressivist account. F. Dorsch & D.-E. Ratiu (Eds.), Proceedings of the European society for aesthetics (Vol. 7, pp. 37–60). The European Society for Aesthetics.

  • Enç, M. (1996). Tense and modality. S. Lappin (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 345–358). Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

  • Friend, S. (2008). Imagining fact and fiction. K. Stock & K. Thomson-Jones (Eds.), New waves in aesthetics (pp. 150–169). Palgrave Macmillan UK. Retrieved from https://doi.org/10.1057/97802302274538

  • Friend, S. (2011). Fictive utterance and imagining II. Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 85, 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friend, S. (2017). The real foundation of fictional worlds. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 29–42. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2016.1149736

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García-Carpintero, M. (2013). Norms of fiction-making. British Journal of Aesthetics, 53(3), 339–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2000). The puzzle of imaginative resistance. Journal of Philosophy, 97(2), 55–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Cornell University Press.

  • Kaufmann, M., & Kaufmann, S. (2020). Talking about sources. (manuscript. http://magdalena-kaufmann.uconn.edu/papers/givenPREFINAL.pdf)

  • Kissine, M. (2008). Why will is not a modal. Natural Language Semantics, 16, 129–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krawczyk, E. (2012). Inferred propositions and the expression of the evidence relation in natural language: Evidentiality in Central Alaskan Yup’ik Eskimo and English (Unpublished doctoral dissertation). Georgetown University.

  • Kripke, S. (2011). Vacuous names and fictional entities. Philosophical Troubles (pp. 52–74). Oxford University Press.

  • Kroon, F., & Voltolini, A. (2018). Fictional Entities. E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/fictional-entities/.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

  • Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37–46. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009693

  • Maier, E. (2019). On the exceptionality of reported speech. Linguistic Typology, 23(1), 197–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier, E., & Semeijn, M. (2021). Extracting fictional truth from unreliable sources. E. Maier & A. Stokke (Eds.), The language of fiction (pp. 186–220). Oxford University Press.

  • Murday, B. (2010). Two-dimensionalism and fictional names. F. Lihoreau (Ed.), Truth in fiction (pp. 43–76). De Gruyter.

  • Prior, A. (1967). Past, present and future. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2000). Oratio obliqua, oratio recta: An essay on metarepresentation. MIT Press.

  • Recanati, F. (2018). Fictional, metafictional, parafictional. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 118(1), 25-54. Retrieved 2018-05-03, from https://academic.OxfordUniversityPress.com/aristotelian/article/118/1/25/4898115

  • Ross, J. (2012). The semantics of media. Dordrecht: Springer. Retrieved from https://books.google.nl/books?id=cLuLBQAAQBAJ

  • Ryan, M. (1980). Fiction, non-factuals, and the principle of minimal departure. Topics in Catalysis, 9(4), 403–422. https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-422X(80)90030-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R.M. (2014). Fictional worlds and fiction operators. M. García- Carpintero & G. Martí (Eds.), Empty representations (pp. 277-289). Oxford University Press.

  • Salkie, R. (2010). Will: Tense or modal or both? English Language and Linguistics, 14(2), 187–215. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1360674310000055

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sæbø, K. J. (2013). Reports of specific indefinites. Journal of Semantics, 30(3), 267–314. https://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Semeijn, M., & Zalta, E. N. (2021). Revisiting the wrong kind of object problem. Organon F, 28(1), 168–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R.C. (1968, 01). A theory of conditionals. N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory: American philosophical quarterly monograph series 2 (Vol. 6, pp. 98–112). Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

  • Stalnaker, R.C. (1978). Assertion. P. Cole (Ed.), Pragmatics (Vol. 9, pp. 315–32). New York Academic Press.

  • Stock, K. (2011). Fictive utterance and imagining. Supplementary Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 85, 145–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toshyuki, O., & Sharvit, Y. (2012). Embedded tenses. R.I. Binnick (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of tense and aspect. Oxford University Press.

  • Voltolini, A. (2006). How ficta follow fiction: A syncretistic account of fictional entities. Springer Netherlands. Retrieved from https://books.google.fr/books?id=eTxGAAAAQBAJ

  • Voltolini, A. (2019). Varieties of fiction operators: Methods and applications. A. Capone, M. Carapezza, & F. Lo Piparo (Eds.), Further advances in pragmatics and philosophy: Part 2 theories and applications (pp. 199– 210). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-111

  • von Fintel, K., & Heim, I. (2011). Intensional Semantics. unpublished textbook. Retrieved from http://web.mit.edu/fintel/fintel-heim-intensional.pdf

  • von Stechow, A., & Zimmermann, E. (2005). A problem for a compositional treatment of de re attitudes. G. Carlson & F. Pelletier (Eds.), Reference and Quantification: The Partee Effect (pp. 207–228). CSLI.

  • Walton, K.L. (1990). Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Harvard University Press. Retrieved from http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674576032

  • Zalta, E. N. (1983). Abstract objects: An introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. Springer.

  • Zalta, E.N. (2003 [1987]). Erzählung als Taufe des Helden: Wie man auf fiktionale Objekte Bezug nimmt. Zeitschrift für Semiotik, 9(1-2), 85-95. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/42971494 (Translated (Arnold Günther) as Referring to fictional characters in Dialectica, 2(2003):243-254.)

  • Zipfel, F. (2011). Unreliable narration and fictional truth. Journal of Literary Theory, 5(1), 109–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zucchi, A. (2001). Tense in fiction. C. Cecchetto, G. Chierchia, & M.T. Guasti (Eds.), Semantic interfaces: Reference, anaphora and aspect. CSLI.

  • Zucchi, A. (2021). On the generation of content. E. Maier & A. Stokke (Eds.), The language of fiction (pp. 107–130). Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research is supported by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO), Vidi Grant 276-80-004 (Emar Maier) and Rubicon Grant Let’s stop talking about Holmes. Many thanks to Natasha Korotkova, Emar Maier and three anonymous reviewers for valuable comments that helped improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Merel Semeijn.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Semeijn, M. On the difference between the ‘In’ and ‘According to’ operators. Linguist and Philos 47, 239–264 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09395-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-023-09395-0

Keywords

Navigation